Results for 'Marc A. Hight'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. Berkeley on Economic Bubbles.Marc A. Hight - 2015 - In Sébastien Charles (ed.), Berkeley Revisited: Moral, Social and Political Philosophy. Oxford: Voltaire Foundation. pp. 191-208.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  13
    The Correspondence of George Berkeley.Marc A. Hight (ed.) - 2012 - Cambridge University Press.
    George Berkeley, Bishop of Cloyne, was an Irish philosopher and divine who pursued a number of grand causes, contributing to the fields of economics, mathematics, political theory and theology. He pioneered the theory of 'immaterialism', and his work ranges over many philosophical issues that remain of interest today. This volume offers a complete and accurate edition of Berkeley's extant correspondence, including letters written both by him and to him, supplemented by extensive explanatory and critical notes. Alexander Pope famously said 'To (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  3.  17
    Idea and Ontology: An Essay in Early Modern Metaphysics of Ideas.Marc A. Hight - 2008 - Penn State Press.
    The prevailing view about the history of early modern philosophy, which the author dubs “the early modern tale” and wants to convince us is really a fairy tale, has it that the focus on ideas as a solution to various epistemological puzzles, first introduced by Descartes, created difficulties for the traditional ontological scheme of substance and mode. The early modern tale depicts the development of “the way of ideas” as abandoning ontology at least by the time of Berkeley. This, in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  4.  14
    Idea and Ontology: An Essay in Early Modern Metaphysics of Ideas.Marc A. Hight - 2008 - Pennsylvania State University Press.
    "A wide-ranging study of the 'way of ideas' and its metaphysics, culminating in a bold reinterpretation of Berkeley.".
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  5. Berkeley and bodily resurrection.Marc A. Hight - 2007 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 45 (3):443-458.
    : Establishing and defending the Christian faith serves as both a guide and a limit to Berkeley's intriguing metaphysics. I take Berkeley seriously when he says that his aim is to promote the consideration of God and the truth of Christianity. In this paper I discuss and engage Berkeley's superficially weak argument (which I call the natural analogy argument) in defense of the plausibility of the doctrine of bodily resurrection. When his immaterialist resources are properly applied, the argument has more (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  6.  53
    Locke's implicit ontology of ideas.Marc A. Hight - 2001 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 9 (1):17 – 42.
  7.  9
    Locke's Implicit Ontology of Ideas.Marc A. Hight - 2001 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 9 (1):17-42.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  8.  51
    The Son More Visible: Immaterialism and the Incarnation.Marc A. Hight - 2010 - Modern Theology 26 (1):120 - 148.
    In this article we argue that an immaterialist ontology -- a metaphysic that denies the existence of material substance -- is more consonant with Christian dogma than any ontology that includes the existence of material substance. We use the philosophy of the famous eighteenth-century Irish immaterialist George Berkeley as a guide while engaging one particularly difficult Christian mystery: the doctrine of the Incarnation of Christ. The goal is to make plausible the claim that, from the analysis of this one example, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  9. Why My Chair is Not Merely a Congeries: Berkeley and the Single-Idea Thesis.Marc A. Hight - 2007 - In Stephen H. Daniel (ed.), Reexamining Berkeley's Philosophy.
  10. Why we do not see what we feel.Marc A. Hight - 2002 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 83 (2):148-162.
    Of all of Berkeley’s claims about perception, perhaps the most unusual is his assertion that we do not see the numerically same objects we feel. Ideas are radically heterogeneous. The question I seek to answer is why Berkeley thought this thesis true. Traditional accounts hold that Berkeley was forced into accepting heterogeneity by his views concerning either distance or abstraction, but careful analysis reveals these to be mistaken. I conclude that how Berkeley thought of the ontic status of ideas finishes (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  11.  12
    Poverty and Prosperity: Political Economics in Eighteenth-Century Ireland.Marc A. Hight - 2020 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 88:73-96.
    I draw attention to a group of thinkers in Ireland in the first half of the eighteenth century that made significant contributions to the philosophy of political economy. Loosely organized around the Dublin Philosophical Society founded in 1731, these individuals employed a similar set of assumptions and shared a common interest in the well-being of the Irish people. I focus on Samuel Madden, Arthur Dobbs, and Thomas Prior and argue for two main theses. First, these Irish thinkers shared a number (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. Between Substance and Mode: The Ontology of Ideas Among the Early Moderns.Marc A. Hight - 1999 - Dissertation, Syracuse University
    This work studies early modern thought concerning the ontology of ideas. I endeavor to establish, contrary to some current scholarship, that the Early Moderns remained firmly in the grip of a substance/mode ontology narrowed from the substance/property distinction inherited from Aristotle. I argue that this traditional dichotomy provides the most philosophically and historically fruitful approach to understanding early modern thought. In particular, I demonstrate how the increasing radicalization in the metaphysics of the moderns is best explained by remaining within the (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  52
    How immaterialism can save your soul.Marc A. Hight - 2010 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 135 (1):109 - 122.
    I argue that Berkeley has reasonable grounds for believing both that (a) the supposition of the existence of material substance leads to atheism and (b) endorsing immaterialism provides a better support for the Christian faith than any rival that posits the existence of matter. Together, those claims lead to the conclusion that if one wants to be a Christian, there is good reason to think that one ought to be an immaterialist. Je montre que Berkeley a raison de croire que (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14.  4
    Absolute Time: Rifts in Early Modern British Metaphysics by Emily Thomas.Marc A. Hight - 2019 - Review of Metaphysics 72 (3):615-616.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  40
    Berkeley's Metaphysical Instrumentalism.Marc A. Hight - 2010 - In Silvia Parigi (ed.), George Berkeley: Science and Religion in the Age of Enlightenment. Springer.
  16.  87
    Defending Berkeley's divine ideas.Marc A. Hight - 2005 - Philosophia 33 (1-4):97-128.
  17.  47
    John Locke and Natural Philosophy by, Peter R. Anstey: Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011, pp. xii + 252, £35.Marc A. Hight - 2014 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 92 (4):815-815.
  18.  9
    John Locke and Natural Philosophy by, Peter R. Anstey: Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011, pp. xii + 252, £35.Marc A. Hight - 2014 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 92 (4):815-815.
  19. Preserving the Torments of Hell: Berkeleian Immaterialism and the Afterlife.Marc A. Hight - 2011 - Science Et Esprit 63 (2):179-192.
  20. Roger Ariew and Eric Watkins, eds., Modem Philosophy: An Anthology of Primary Sources Reviewed by.Marc A. Hight - 1999 - Philosophy in Review 19 (5):311-312.
  21.  67
    Wilhelm Dilthey.Marc A. Hight - 2010 - The Philosophers' Magazine 49 (49):98-100.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  10
    Wilhelm Dilthey.Marc A. Hight - 2010 - The Philosophers' Magazine 49:98-100.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  22
    Review of John Russell Roberts, A Metaphysics for the Mob: The Philosophy of George Berkeley[REVIEW]Marc A. Hight - 2007 - Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2007 (10).
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  10
    Aboslute Time: Rifts in Early Modern British Metaphysics. [REVIEW]Marc A. Hight - 2019 - Review of Metaphysics 72 (3).
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  16
    Review of Stephen H. Daniel (ed.), New Interpretations of Berkeley's Thought[REVIEW]Marc A. Hight - 2008 - Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2008 (6).
  26. The New Berkeley.Marc Hight And Walter Ott - 2004 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 34 (1):1-24.
    Throughout his mature writings, Berkeley speaks of minds as substances that underlie or support ideas. After initially flirting with a Humean account, according to which minds are nothing but ‘congeries of Perceptions’, Berkeley went on to claim that a mind is a ‘perceiving, active being... entirely distinct’ from its ideas. Despite his immaterialism, Berkeley retains the traditional category of substance and gives it pride of place in his ontology. Ideas, by contrast, are ‘fleeting and dependent beings’ that must be supported (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  79
    The New Berkeley.Marc Hight & Walter Ott - 2004 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 34 (1):1 - 24.
    Throughout his mature writings, Berkeley speaks of minds as substances that underlie or support ideas. After initially flirting with a Humean account, according to which minds are nothing but ‘congeries of Perceptions’, Berkeley went on to claim that a mind is a ‘perceiving, active being … entirely distinct’ from its ideas. Despite his immaterialism, Berkeley retains the traditional category of substance and gives it pride of place in his ontology. Ideas, by contrast, are ‘fleeting and dependent beings’ that must be (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  28.  18
    New Berkeley Correspondence: A Note.Marc Hight - 2010 - Berkeley Studies 21:16-22.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  44
    Berkeley's half-way house.Marc Hight - 2006 - Philosophy Compass 1 (1):28–35.
    George Berkeley's New Theory of Vision is frequently read as a simple precursor or “half-way house” to his later metaphysics. As a result, some allege the value of the New Theory has been overlooked as critics judge it by its association with immaterialism. In this piece I examine the ongoing debate over the nature of the connection between Berkeley's early work on perception and his later immaterialist tracts. I identify four principal positions on the nature of the connection that have (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30. Medicine, money, and morals: physicians' conflicts of interest.Marc A. Rodwin - 1993 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Conflicts of interest are rampant in the American medical community. Today it is not uncommon for doctors to refer patients to clinics or labs in which they have a financial interest (40% of physicians in Florida invest in medical centers); for hospitals to offer incentives to physicians who refer patients (a practice that can lead to unnecessary hospitalization); or for drug companies to provide lucrative give-aways to entice doctors to use their "brand name" drugs (which are much more expensive than (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  31. Marc A. Hight. Idea and Ontology: An Essay in Early Modern Metaphysics of Ideas. [REVIEW]Samuel C. Rickless - 2009 - Berkeley Studies 20:22-33.
    Marc A. Hight has given us a well-researched, well-written, analytically rigorous and thoughtprovoking book about the development of idea ontology in the seventeenth and early eighteenth centuries. The book covers a great deal of material, some in significant depth, some not. The figures discussed include Descartes, Malebranche, Arnauld, Locke, Leibniz, Berkeley, and Hume. Some might think it a tall order for anyone to grapple with the central works of these figures on a subject as fundamental as the nature (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. Intuitions as evidence : an introduction.Marc A. Moffett - 2019 - In Maria Lasonen-Aarnio & Clayton Littlejohn (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of the Philosophy of Evidence. Routledge.
  33.  16
    The Nature and Practice of Trust.Marc A. Cohen (ed.) - 2023 - New York, NY: Routledge.
    Across the social sciences and even in philosophy, trust is most often characterized in terms of expectations and probabilities. This book defends an alternative conception of trust as a moral phenomenon. -/- When one person trusts another to do something, the first relies on the second’s commitment(s). So, trust reflects—and is a product of—agreement about the commitments and obligations that bind persons who live and work together. These commitments and obligations can be implicit, but building (or rebuilding) trust often requires (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. Review: Marc A.Hight, Idea and Ontology. [REVIEW]Samuel Rickless - 2009 - Berkeley Studies:22-34.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. Trust as an intrinsic good, moral reason to trust.Marc A. Cohen - 2023 - In The Nature and Practice of Trust. New York, NY: Routledge. pp. 116-124.
    This chapter argues that trust is an intrinsic good (that is, a good to be pursued apart from material or instrumental beneft), and so we have moral reason to trust.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  69
    The Implicit Morality of the Market and Joseph Heath’s Market Failures Approach to Business Ethics.Marc A. Cohen & Dean Peterson - 2019 - Journal of Business Ethics 159 (1):75-88.
    Joseph Heath defends competitive markets and conceptualizes business ethics with reference to Pareto efficiency, which he takes to be the “implicit morality of the market.” His justification for markets is that they generate Pareto efficient outcomes, meaning that markets optimally satisfy consumer preferences. And, for Heath, business ethics is the set of normative constraints—regulation and beyond-compliance norms—needed to preserve that outcome. The present paper accepts Heath’s claim that the economic justification for markets is ethical, in that satisfying consumer preferences is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  37.  26
    Donald Davidson.Marc A. Joseph - 2004 - Mcgill-Queen's University Press.
    Donald Davidson's work has been of seminal importance in the development of analytic philosophy and his views on the nature of language, mind and action remain the starting point for many of the central debates in the analytic tradition. His ideas, however, are complex, often technical, and interconnected in ways that can make them difficult to understand. This introduction to Davidson's philosophy examines the full range of his writings to provide a clear succinct overview of his ideas. This book begins (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  38. The narrow application of Rawls in business ethics: A political conception of both stakeholder theory and the morality of markets.Marc A. Cohen - 2010 - Journal of Business Ethics 97 (4):563-579.
    This paper argues that Rawls’ principles of justice provide a normative foundation for stakeholder theory. The principles articulate (at an abstract level) citizens’ rights; these rights create interests across all aspects of society, including in the space of economic activity; and therefore, stakeholders – as citizens – have legitimate interests in the space of economic activity. This approach to stakeholder theory suggests a political interpretation of Boatright’s Moral Market approach, one that emphasizes the rights/place of citizens. And this approach to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  39.  28
    Conflicts of Interest, Institutional Corruption, and Pharma: An Agenda for Reform.Marc A. Rodwin - 2012 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 40 (3):511-522.
    Why do physicians have financial conflicts of interest? They arise because society expects physicians to act in their patients’ interest, while simultaneously, financial incentives encourage physicians to practice medicine in ways that promote their own interests or those of third parties. Because physicians’ clinical choices, referrals, and prescriptions affect the fortune of third parties, these third parties may offer physicians financial incentives to make income-driven clinical choices. In the past, physicians and scholars typically conceived of conflicts of interest as an (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  40.  23
    Review of Marc A. Hight, Idea and Ontology: An Essay in Early Modern Metaphysics of Ideas[REVIEW]Monte Cook - 2009 - Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2009 (1).
  41.  80
    Apology as Self-Repair.Marc A. Cohen - 2018 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 21 (3):585-598.
    Bernard Williams briefly discusses agent regret in his broader account of moral luck. The present paper first outlines one way to develop Williams’s notion with reference to the unintended harm; it then suggests that agent regret can be counteracted by externalizing the action that caused unintended harm, in Harry Frankfurt’s sense of externalization; and then the present paper argues that apology is a mechanism by which a person can externalize an offending action/effect—in that way counteracting agent regret. This function for (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  42.  13
    Five Un-Easy Pieces of Pharmaceutical Policy Reform.Marc A. Rodwin - 2013 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 41 (3):581-589.
    The federal government indirectly subsidizes the pharmaceutical industry by funding basic research, various tax credits and deductions, patent rules, grants of market exclusivity, and other means, in order to spur drug development, promote public health, and improve medical care. But today, the pharmaceutical industry often neglects these goals and sometimes even undermines them, due to what Lawrence Lessig refers to as institutional corruption — that is, widespread or systemic practices, usually legal, that undermine an institution’s objectives or integrity. A key (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  43. Moral and Amoral Conceptions of Trust, with an Application in Organizational Ethics.Marc A. Cohen & John Dienhart - 2013 - Journal of Business Ethics 112 (1):1-13.
    Across the management, social science, and business ethics literatures, and in much of the philosophy literature, trust is characterized as a disposition to act given epistemic states—beliefs and/or expectations about others and about the risks involved. This characterization of trust is best thought of as epistemological because epistemic states distinguish trust from other dispositions. The epistemological characterization of trust is the amoral one referred to in the title of this paper, and we argue that this characterization is conceptually inadequate. We (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  44.  32
    Five Un‐Easy Pieces of Pharmaceutical Policy Reform.Marc A. Rodwin - 2013 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 41 (3):581-589.
    Improper dependencies slant policy over a drug's life span, biasing the development of new drugs, the testing and marketing approval for new drugs, and the monitoring of patient safety after drugs are marketed. This article examines five ways in which the public improperly depends on pharmaceutical firms that compromise the integrity of pharmaceutical policy. Today the public relies on pharmaceutical firms: (1) to set priorities on drug research and development; (2) to conduct clinical trials to test whether drugs are safe (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  45.  54
    Drug Advertising, Continuing Medical Education, and Physician Prescribing: A Historical Review and Reform Proposal.Marc A. Rodwin - 2010 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 38 (4):807-815.
    Through the 1960s, many people claimed that drug advertising was educational and physicians often relied on it. Continuing Medical Education (CME) was developed to provide an alternative. However, because CME relied on grants, industry funders chose the subjects offered. Now policymakers worry that drug firms support CME to promote sales and that commercial support biases prescribing and fosters inappropriate drug use. A historical review reveals parallel problems between advertising and industry-funded CME. To preclude industry influence and improve CME, we should (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  46.  18
    Drug Advertising, Continuing Medical Education, and Physician Prescribing: A Historical Review and Reform Proposal.Marc A. Rodwin - 2010 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 38 (4):807-815.
    Public policy tries to promote appropriate drug use by allowing firms to market drugs in interstate commerce only for uses that the Food and Drug Administration has found to be safe and effective. Because of their medical knowledge, physicians are authorized to prescribe drugs even for uses unapproved by the FDA. Nevertheless, physicians have relied on drug firms for information on appropriate prescribing despite the inherent tension between drug firm dissemination of information to promote sales and rational prescribing. In the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  47.  21
    Rooting Out Institutional Corruption to Manage Inappropriate Off-Label Drug Use.Marc A. Rodwin - 2013 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 41 (3):654-664.
    The Food and Drug Administration authorizes the marketing of a drug only for uses that the manufacturer has demonstrated to be safe and effective, based on evidence from at least two clinical trials. However, the FDA does not regulate the practice of medicine, so physicians may prescribe drugs in any manner they choose. Prescribing drugs in ways that deviate from the uses specified in the FDA-approved drug label, package insert, and marketing authorization is referred to as off-label prescribing. This occurs (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  48.  30
    Rooting Out Institutional Corruption to Manage Inappropriate Off‐Label Drug Use.Marc A. Rodwin - 2013 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 41 (3):654-664.
    Prescribing drugs for uses that the FDA has not approved — off-label drug use — can sometimes be justified but is typically not supported by substantial evidence of effectiveness. At the root of inappropriate off-label drug use lie perverse incentives for pharmaceutical firms and flawed oversight of prescribing physicians. Typical reform proposals such as increased sanctions for manufacturers might reduce the incidence of unjustified off-label use, but they do not remove the source of the problem. Public policy should address the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  49.  26
    Conflicts of Interest and the Future of Medicine: The United States, France, and Japan.Marc A. Rodwin - 2010 - Oxford University Press.
    The heart of the matter -- The evolution of the French medicine -- Coping with physicians' conflicts of interest in France -- The rise of a protected medical market : the United States before 1950 -- The commercial transformation : the United States, 1950-1980 -- The logic of medical markets : the United States, 1980 to the present -- Coping with physicians' conflicts of interest in the United States -- The evolution of Japanese medicine -- Coping with physicians' conflicts of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  50.  22
    Constructing Attitudes.Marc A. Moffett - 2005 - ProtoSociology 21:105-128.
    The singular term theory maintains that that-clauses are complex singular terms which designate propositions. Though extremely well-supported, the theory is endangered by the existence of oblique that-clauses; that is, that-clauses occurring in what appear to be nonargument positions (e.g., ‘Lola was upset that Slick Willy had all the fun’). In this paper I argue that the best solution to the problem consistent with the singular term theory, invokes a construction-based grammatical theory. Such an approach challenges traditional views of semantic compositionality (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000