Results for 'David Rosenthal'

(not author) ( search as author name )
976 found
Order:
  1. Consciousness.David M. Rosenthal - unknown
    One phenomenon pertains roughly to being awake. A person or other creature is conscious when it's awake and mentally responsive to sensory input; otherwise it's unconscious. This kind of consciousness figures most often in everyday discourse.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  2. Intentionality.David M. Rosenthal - 1986 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 10 (1):151-184.
    At the level of our platitudinous background knowledge about things, speech is the expression of thought. And understanding what such expressing involves is central to understanding the relation between thinking and speaking. Part of what it is for a speech act to express a mental state is that the speech act accurately captures the mental state and can convey to others what mental state it is. And for this to occur, the speech act at least must have propositional content that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  3.  62
    Res Cogitans: An Essay in Rational Psychology. [REVIEW]David M. Rosenthal - 1976 - Journal of Philosophy 73 (9):240-252.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  4. The Higher-Order Model of Consciousness.David Rosenthal - 2002 - In Rita Carter (ed.), Consciousness. Weidenfeld & Nicolson.
    All mental states, including thoughts, feelings, perceptions, and sensations, often occur consciously. But they all occur also without being conscious. So the first thing a theory of consciousness must do is explain the difference between thoughts, feelings, perceptions, and sensations that are conscious and those which are not.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  5.  22
    Consciousness and Its Expression.David M. Rosenthal - 1998 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 22 (1):294-309.
  6. Consciousness and Mind.David M. Rosenthal - 2005 - New York: Oxford University Press UK.
    Consciousness and Mind presents David Rosenthal's influential work on the nature of consciousness. Central to that work is Rosenthal's higher-order-thought theory of consciousness, according to which a sensation, thought, or other mental state is conscious if one has a higher-order thought that one is in that state. The first four essays develop various aspects of that theory. The next three essays present Rosenthal's homomorphism theory of mental qualities and qualitative consciousness, and show how that theory fits (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   293 citations  
  7. Applied Ethics and Ethical Theory.David M. Rosenthal and Fadlou Shehadi - 1988
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  15
    The necessity of foreknowledge.David M. Rosenthal - 1976 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 1 (1):22-25.
  9. Two concepts of consciousness.David M. Rosenthal - 1986 - Philosophical Studies 49 (May):329-59.
    No mental phenomenon is more central than consciousness to an adequate understanding of the mind. Nor does any mental phenomenon seem more stubbornly to resist theoretical treatment. Consciousness is so basic to the way we think about the mind that it can be tempting to suppose that no mental states exist that are not conscious states. Indeed, it may even seem mysterious what sort of thing a mental state might be if it is not a conscious state. On this way (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   517 citations  
  10. A theory of consciousness.David M. Rosenthal - 1997 - In Ned Block, Owen J. Flanagan & Guven Guzeldere (eds.), The Nature of Consciousness. MIT Press.
  11. Sensory qualities, consciousness, and perception.David M. Rosenthal - 2005 - In Consciousness and Mind. Clarendon Press. pp. 175-226.
  12. Explaining Consciousness.David M. Rosenthal - 2002 - In David J. Chalmers (ed.), Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings. Oxford University Press. pp. 109-131.
  13.  20
    Simple reaction time as a function of the relative frequency of the preparatory interval.Theodore P. Zahn & David Rosenthal - 1966 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 72 (1):15.
  14. Thinking that one thinks.David M. Rosenthal - 1993 - In Martin Davies & Glyn W. Humphreys (eds.), Consciousness: Psychological and Philosophical Essays. Blackwell.
  15. Exaggerated reports: reply to Block.David Rosenthal - 2011 - Analysis 71 (3):431-437.
  16. The independence of consciousness and sensory quality.David M. Rosenthal - 1991 - Philosophical Issues 1:15-36.
  17. How to think about mental qualities.David Rosenthal - 2010 - Philosophical Issues 20 (1):368-393.
    It’s often held that undetectable inversion of mental qualities is, if not possible, at least conceivable. It’s thought to be conceivable that the mental quality your visual states exhibit when you see something red in standard conditions is literally of the same type as the mental quality my visual states exhibit when I see something green in such circumstances. It’s thought, moreover, to be conceivable that such inversion of mental qualities could be wholly undetectable by any third-person means. And since (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  18. The Nature of Mind.David M. Rosenthal (ed.) - 1991 - Oxford University Press.
    This anthology brings together readings mainly from contemporary philosophers, but also from writers of the past two centuries, on the philosophy of mind. Some of the main questions addressed are: is a human being really a mind in relation to a body; if so, what exactly is this mind and how it is related to the body; and are there any grounds for supposing that the mind survives the disintegration of the body?
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  19. Consciousness and its function.David Rosenthal - 2008
    MS, under submission, derived from a Powerpoint presentation at a Conference on Consciousness, Memory, and Perception, in honor of Larry Weiskrantz, City University, London, September 15, 2006.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  20. Varieties of higher-order theory.David Rosenthal - 2004 - In Rocco J. Gennaro (ed.), Higher-Order Theories of Consciousness: An Anthology. John Benjamins.
    A touchstone of much modern theorizing about the mind is the idea, still tac- itly accepted by many, that a state's being mental implies that it's conscious. This view is epitomized in the dictum, put forth by theorists as otherwise di-.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  21. Explaining consciousness.David M. Rosenthal - 1993 - In David J. Chalmers (ed.), Philosophy of Mind: Contemporary Readings. Oxford University Press. pp. 406--421.
  22. How many kinds of consciousness?David M. Rosenthal - 2002 - Consciousness and Cognition 11 (4):653-665.
    Ned BlockÕs influential distinction between phenomenal and access consciousness has become a staple of current discussions of consciousness. It is not often noted, however, that his distinction tacitly embodies unargued theoretical assumptions that favor some theoretical treatments at the expense of others. This is equally so for his less widely discussed distinction between phenomenal consciousness and what he calls reflexive consciousness. I argue that the distinction between phenomenal and access consciousness, as Block draws it, is untenable. Though mental states that (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  23. Materialism and the Mind-Body Problem.David M. Rosenthal (ed.) - 1971 - Englewood Cliffs, N.J.,: Prentice-Hall.
    An expanded and updated edition of this classic collection.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  24. Higher-order theories of consciousness.David Rosenthal & Josh Weisberg - 2008 - Scholarpedia 3 (5):4407.
  25. Higher-Order Awareness, Misrepresentation, and Function.David Rosenthal - 2012 - Higher-Order Awareness, Misrepresentation and Function 367 (1594):1424-1438.
    Conscious mental states are states we are in some way aware of. I compare higher-order theories of consciousness, which explain consciousness by appeal to such higher-order awareness (HOA), and first-order theories, which do not, and I argue that higher-order theories have substantial explanatory advantages. The higher-order nature of our awareness of our conscious states suggests an analogy with the metacognition that figures in the regulation of psychological processes and behaviour. I argue that, although both consciousness and metacognition involve higher-order psychological (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  26. Awareness and Identification of Self.David Rosenthal - 2011 - In JeeLoo Liu & John Perry (eds.), Consciousness and the Self: New Essays.
  27.  43
    The Nature of Consciousness.David M. Rosenthal - 2004 - Mind 113 (451):581-588.
  28. Concepts and definitions of consciousness.David Rosenthal - unknown - In P. W. Banks (ed.), Encyclopedia of Consciousness. Elsevier.
    in Encyclopedia of Consciousness, ed. William P. Banks, Amsterdam: Elsevier, forthcoming in 2009.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  29. Metacognition and higher-order thoughts.David M. Rosenthal - 2000 - Consciousness and Cognition 9 (2):231-242.
    Because there is a fair amount of overlap in the points by Balog and Rey, I will organize this response topically, referring specifically to each commentator as rele- vant. And, because much of the discussion focuses on my higher-order-thought hypothesis independent of questions about metacognition, I will begin by addressing a cluster of issues that have to do with the status, motivation, and exact formulation of that hypothesis.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  30.  56
    The colors and shapes of visual experiences.David M. Rosenthal - 1999 - In Denis Fisette (ed.), Consciousness and Intentionality: Models and Modalities of Attribution. Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 95--118.
    red and round. According to common sense, the red, round thing we see is the tomato itself. When we have a hallucinatory vision of a tomato, however, there may be present to us no red and round phys- ical object. Still, we use the words 'red' and 'round' to describe that situation as well, this time applying them to the visual experience itself. We say that we have a red, round visual image, or a visual experience of a red disk, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  31. State consciousness and transitive consciousness.David M. Rosenthal - 1994 - Consciousness and Cognition 2 (3):355-63.
  32.  7
    Memory. [REVIEW]David M. Rosenthal - 1969 - Journal of Philosophy 66 (1):17-22.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33. Consciousness and metacognition.David M. Rosenthal - 1998 - In Dan Sperber (ed.), Metarepresentations: A Multidisciplinary Perspective. Oxford University Press.
  34.  76
    Moore's paradox and consciousness.David M. Rosenthal - 1995 - Philosophical Perspectives 9:313-33.
  35.  19
    State Consciousness and Transitive Consciousness.David M. Rosenthal - 1993 - Consciousness and Cognition 2 (4):355-363.
  36. Self-knowledge and Moore's paradox.David M. Rosenthal - 1995 - Philosophical Studies 77 (2-3):195 - 209.
    As G. E. Moore famously observed, sentences such as 'It's raining but I don't think it is', though they aren't contradictory, cannot be used to make coherent assertions.' The trouble with such sentences is not a matter of their truth conditions; such sentences can readily be true. Indeed, it happens often enough with each of us that we think, for example, that it isn't raining even though it is. This shows that such sentences are not literally contradictory. But even though (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  37. Consciousness, content, and metacognitive judgments.David M. Rosenthal - 2000 - Consciousness and Cognition 9 (2):203-214.
    Because metacognition consists in our having mental access to our cognitive states and mental states are conscious only when we are conscious of them in some suitable way, metacognition and consciousness shed important theoretical light on one another. Thus, our having metacognitive access to information carried by states that are not conscious helps con?rm the hypothesis that a mental state.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  38. Expressing One’s Mind.David M. Rosenthal - 2010 - Acta Analytica 25 (1):21 - 34.
    Remarks such as ‘I am in pain’ and ‘I think that it’s raining’ are puzzling, since they seem to literally describe oneself as being in pain or having a particular thought, but their conditions of use tend to coincide with unequivocal expressions of pain or of that thought. This led Wittgenstein, among others, to treat such remarks as expressing, rather than as reporting, one’s mental states. Though such expressivism is widely recognized as untenable, Bar-On has recently advanced a neo-expressivist view, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  39. Introduction.Josh Weisberg & David Rosenthal - 2014 - In Consciousness. Polity.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  40. Consciousness, the self and bodily location.David M. Rosenthal - 2010 - Analysis 70 (2):270-276.
    (No abstract is available for this citation).
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  41. Being conscious of ourselves.David M. Rosenthal - 2004 - The Monist 87 (2):161-184.
    What is it that we are conscious of when we are conscious of ourselves? Hume famously despaired of finding self, as against simply finding various impressions and ideas, when, as he put it, “I enter most intimately into what I call myself.” “When I turn my reflexion on myself, I never can perceive this self without some one or more perceptions; nor can I ever perceive any thing but the perceptions.”.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  42. Unity of consciousness and the self.David M. Rosenthal - 2003 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 103 (3):325-352.
    The so-called unity of consciousness consists in the compelling sense we have that all our conscious mental states belong to a single conscious subject. Elsewhere I have argued that a mental state's being conscious is a matter of our being conscious of that state by having a higher-order thought (HOT) about it. Contrary to what is sometimes argued, this HOT model affords a natural explanation of our sense that our conscious states all belong to a single conscious subject. HOTs often (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  43.  44
    Misrepresentation and mental appearance.David Rosenthal - 2018 - Trans/Form/Ação 41 (s1):49-74.
    I begin by discussing an objection often lodged against higher-order theories of consciousness. The objection is that those theories do not preclude consciousness from misrepresenting the mental properties of our conscious states. I argue that there are several reasons why this objection cannot succeed. Sam Coleman agrees that the objection fails, but sees it as pointing to a related objection, which he argues poses difficulties the higher-order theorist cannot avoid. His solution is a variant theory of consciousness that invokes mental (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  44. The timing of conscious states.David M. Rosenthal - 2002 - Consciousness and Cognition 11 (2):215-20.
    Striking experimental results by Benjamin Libet and colleagues have had an impor- tant impact on much recent discussion of consciousness. Some investigators have sought to replicate or extend Libet’s results (Haggard, 1999; Haggard & Eimer, 1999; Haggard, Newman, & Magno, 1999; Trevena & Miller, 2002), while others have focused on how to interpret those findings (e.g., Gomes, 1998, 1999, 2002; Pockett, 2002), which many have seen as conflicting with our commonsense picture of mental functioning.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  45. Higher-order Theories of Consciousness.David Rosenthal - 2009 - In Brian McLaughlin, Ansgar Beckermann & Sven Walter (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind. Oxford University Press.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  46.  42
    Sensory Quality and the Relocation Story.David M. Rosenthal - 1999 - Philosophical Topics 26 (1-2):321-350.
  47.  7
    Compassion within conflict: Toward a computational theory of social groups informed by maternal brain physiology.S. Shaun Ho, Richard N. Rosenthal, Helen Fox, David Garry, Meroona Gopang, Mikaela J. Rollins, Sarah Soliman & James E. Swain - 2022 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 45.
    Benevolent intersubjectivity developed in parent–infant interactions and compassion toward friend and foe alike are non-violent interventions to group behavior in conflict. Based on a dyadic active inference framework rooted in specific parental brain mechanisms, we suggest that interventions promoting compassion and intersubjectivity can reduce stress, and that compassionate mediation may resolve conflicts.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  50
    Mentality and neutrality.David M. Rosenthal - 1976 - Journal of Philosophy 73 (13):386-415.
  49.  36
    On being accessible to consciousness.David M. Rosenthal - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):621-621.
  50.  44
    Phenomenological overflow and cognitive access.David M. Rosenthal - 2007 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 30 (5-6):522-523.
    I argue that the partial-report results Block cites do not establish that phenomenology overflows cognitive accessibility, as Block maintains. So, without additional argument, the mesh he sees between psychology and neuroscience is unsupported. I argue further that there is reason to hold, contra Block, that phenomenology does always involve some cognitive access to the relevant experience.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
1 — 50 / 976