Results for 'D. Westerstahl'

986 found
Order:
  1. Generalized Quantifiers in Linguistics and Logic.D. Keenan & D. Westerstahl - 2011 - In Johan Van Benthem & Alice Ter Meulen (eds.), Handbook of Logic and Language. Elsevier. pp. 837--893.
  2. Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science. Proceedings of the 13th International Congress.C. Glymour, D. Westerstahl & W. Wang (eds.) - 2009 - King’s College.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science. Proceedings of the Thirteenth International Congress.C. Glymour, W. Wei & D. Westerstahl (eds.) - 2009 - King’s College Publications.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Dept. of Philosophy University of California at San Diego La Jolla, CA 92093 USA.J. Corcoran, A. Tarski, Waikoe W. J. Jr & D. Westerstahl - 1990 - Linguistics and Philosophy 13:423-475.
  5.  49
    Some Results on Quantifiers.Dag Westerståhl - 1984 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 25 (2):152--169.
  6.  5
    Sameness.Dag Westerståhl - 2017 - In Gerhard Jäger & Wilfried Sieg (eds.), Feferman on Foundations: Logic, Mathematics, Philosophy. Cham: Springer.
    I attempt an explication of what it means for an operation across domains to be the same on all domains, an issue that ) took to be central for a successful delimitation of the logical operations. Some properties that seem strongly related to sameness are examined, notably isomorphism invariance, and sameness under extensions of the domain. The conclusion is that although no precise criterion can satisfy all intuitions about sameness, combining the two properties just mentioned yields a reasonably robust and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  7. Quantifiers in Language and Logic.Stanley Peters & Dag Westerståhl - 2006 - Oxford, England: Clarendon Press.
    Quantification is a topic which brings together linguistics, logic, and philosophy. Quantifiers are the essential tools with which, in language or logic, we refer to quantity of things or amount of stuff. In English they include such expressions as no, some, all, both, many. Peters and Westerstahl present the definitive interdisciplinary exploration of how they work - their syntax, semantics, and inferential role.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   107 citations  
  8.  19
    Quantifiers in Language and Logic.Stanley Peters & Dag Westerståhl - 2006 - Oxford, England: Oxford University Press UK.
    Quantification is a topic which brings together linguistics, logic, and philosophy. Quantifiers are the essential tools with which, in language or logic, we refer to quantity of things or amount of stuff. In English they include such expressions as no, some, all, both, many. Peters and Westerstahl present the definitive interdisciplinary exploration of how they work - their syntax, semantics, and inferential role.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   107 citations  
  9. Determiners and context sets.Dag Westerståhl - 1985 - In Generalized Quantifiers in Natural Language. Foris Publications. pp. 45--71.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   74 citations  
  10.  45
    Quantifiers in formal and natural languages.Dag Westerståhl - 1983 - In Dov M. Gabbay & Franz Guenthner (eds.), Handbook of Philosophical Logic. Dordrecht, Netherland: Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 1--131.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  11. Logical constants in quantifier languages.Dag Westerståhl - 1985 - Linguistics and Philosophy 8 (4):387 - 413.
  12. Compositionality Solves Carnap’s Problem.Denis Bonnay & Dag Westerståhl - 2016 - Erkenntnis 81 (4):721-739.
    The standard relation of logical consequence allows for non-standard interpretations of logical constants, as was shown early on by Carnap. But then how can we learn the interpretations of logical constants, if not from the rules which govern their use? Answers in the literature have mostly consisted in devising clever rule formats going beyond the familiar what follows from what. A more conservative answer is possible. We may be able to learn the correct interpretations from the standard rules, because the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  13.  4
    Quantifiers.Dag Westerståhl - 2017 - In Lou Goble (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Philosophical Logic. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 437–460.
    There are two main routes to a concept of (generalized) quantifier. The first starts from first‐order logic, FO, and generalizes from the familiar ∀ and ∃ occurring there. The second route begins with real languages, and notes that many so‐called noun phrases, a kind of phrase which occurs abundantly in most languages, can be interpreted in a natural and uniform way using quantifiers.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  14.  85
    On mathematical proofs of the vacuity of compositionality.dag westerståhl - 1998 - Linguistics and Philosophy 21 (6):635-643.
  15. Consequence Mining: Constans Versus Consequence Relations.Denis Bonnay & Dag Westerståhl - 2012 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 41 (4):671-709.
    The standard semantic definition of consequence with respect to a selected set X of symbols, in terms of truth preservation under replacement (Bolzano) or reinterpretation (Tarski) of symbols outside X, yields a function mapping X to a consequence relation ⇒x. We investigate a function going in the other direction, thus extracting the constants of a given consequence relation, and we show that this function (a) retrieves the usual logical constants from the usual logical consequence relations, and (b) is an inverse (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  16.  95
    Generalized quantifiers.Dag Westerståhl - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  17.  17
    Branching generalized quantifiers and natural language.Dag Westerståhl - 1987 - In Peter Gärdenfors (ed.), Generalized Quantifiers. Reidel Publishing Company. pp. 269--298.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  18. Compositionality I: Definitions and Variants.Peter Pagin & Dag Westerståhl - 2010 - Philosophy Compass 5 (3):250-264.
    This is the first part of a two-part article on semantic compositionality, that is, the principle that the meaning of a complex expression is determined by the meanings of its parts and the way they are put together. Here we provide a brief historical background, a formal framework for syntax and semantics, precise definitions, and a survey of variants of compositionality. Stronger and weaker forms are distinguished, as well as generalized forms that cover extra-linguistic context dependence as well as linguistic (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   71 citations  
  19.  27
    Editorial Introduction.Juha Kontinen, Jouko Väänänen & Dag Westerståhl - 2013 - Studia Logica 101 (2):233-236.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20.  93
    Aristotelian syllogisms and generalized quantifiers.Dag Westerståhl - 1989 - Studia Logica 48 (4):577-585.
    The paper elaborates two points: i) There is no principal opposition between predicate logic and adherence to subject-predicate form, ii) Aristotle's treatment of quantifiers fits well into a modern study of generalized quantifiers.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  21. On the expressive power of monotone natural language quantifiers over finite models.Jouko Väänänen & Dag Westerståhl - 2002 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 31 (4):327-358.
    We study definability in terms of monotone generalized quantifiers satisfying Isomorphism Closure, Conservativity and Extension. Among the quantifiers with the latter three properties - here called CE quantifiers - one finds the interpretations of determiner phrases in natural languages. The property of monotonicity is also linguistically ubiquitous, though some determiners like an even number of are highly non-monotone. They are nevertheless definable in terms of monotone CE quantifiers: we give a necessary and sufficient condition for such definability. We further identify (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  22.  88
    Definability of polyadic lifts of generalized quantifiers.Lauri Hella, Jouko Väänänen & Dag Westerståhl - 1997 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 6 (3):305-335.
    We study generalized quantifiers on finite structures.With every function : we associate a quantifier Q by letting Q x say there are at least (n) elementsx satisfying , where n is the sizeof the universe. This is the general form ofwhat is known as a monotone quantifier of type .We study so called polyadic liftsof such quantifiers. The particular lifts we considerare Ramseyfication, branching and resumption.In each case we get exact criteria fordefinability of the lift in terms of simpler quantifiers.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  23. Compositionality II: Arguments and Problems.Peter Pagin & Dag Westerståhl - 2010 - Philosophy Compass 5 (3):265-282.
    This is the second part of a two-part article on compositionality, i.e. the principle that the meaning of a complex expression is determined by the meanings of its parts and the way they are put together. In the first, Pagin and Westerståhl (2010), we provide a general historical background, a formal framework, definitions, and a survey of variants of compositionality. It will be referred to as Part I. Here we discuss arguments for and against the claim that natural languages have (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  24.  39
    On the compositional extension problem.Dag Westerståhl - 2004 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 33 (6):549-582.
    A semantics may be compositional and yet partial, in the sense that not all well-formed expressions are assigned meanings by it. Examples come from both natural and formal languages. When can such a semantics be extended to a total one, preserving compositionality? This sort of extension problem was formulated by Hodges, and solved there in a particular case, in which the total extension respects a precise version of the fregean dictum that the meaning of an expression is the contribution it (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  25.  79
    Self-commuting quantifiers.Dag Westerståhl - 1996 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 61 (1):212-224.
    We characterize the generalized quantifiers Q which satisfy the scheme $QxQy\phi \leftrightarrow QyQx\phi$ , the so-called self-commuting quantifiers, or quantifiers with the Fubini property.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  26.  70
    Explaining Quantifier Restriction: Reply to Ben-Yami.Dag Westerståhl - 2012 - Logique Et Analyse 55 (217):109-120.
    This is a reply to H. Ben-Yami, 'Generalized quantifiers, and beyond' (this journal, 2009), where he argues that standard GQ theory does not explain why natural language quantifiers have a restricted domain of quantification. I argue, on the other hand, that although GQ theory gives no deep explanation of this fact, it does give a sort of explanation, whereas Ben-Yami's suggested alternative is no improvement.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  27. From constants to consequence, and back.Dag Westerståhl - 2012 - Synthese 187 (3):957-971.
    Bolzano’s definition of consequence in effect associates with each set X of symbols (in a given interpreted language) a consequence relation X . We present this in a precise and abstract form, in particular studying minimal sets of symbols generating X . Then we present a method for going in the other direction: extracting from an arbitrary consequence relation its associated set C of constants. We show that this returns the expected logical constants from familiar consequence relations, and that, restricting (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  28. Pure quotation and general compositionality.Peter Pagin & Dag Westerståhl - 2010 - Linguistics and Philosophy 33 (5):381-415.
    Starting from the familiar observation that no straightforward treatment of pure quotation can be compositional in the standard (homomorphism) sense, we introduce general compositionality, which can be described as compositionality that takes linguistic context into account. A formal notion of linguistic context type is developed, allowing the context type of a complex expression to be distinct from those of its constituents. We formulate natural conditions under which an ordinary meaning assignment can be non-trivially extended to one that is sensitive to (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  29. A World of States of Affairs.D. M. Armstrong - 1997 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    In this important study D. M. Armstrong offers a comprehensive system of analytical metaphysics that synthesises but also develops his thinking over the last twenty years. Armstrong's analysis, which acknowledges the 'logical atomism' of Russell and Wittgenstein, makes facts the fundamental constituents of the world, examining properties, relations, numbers, classes, possibility and necessity, dispositions, causes and laws. All these, it is argued, find their place and can be understood inside a scheme of states of affairs. This is a comprehensive and (...)
  30.  60
    Decomposing generalized quantifiers.Dag Westerståhl - 2008 - Review of Symbolic Logic 1 (3):355-371.
    This note explains the circumstances under which a type 1 quantifier can be decomposed into a type 1, 1 quantifier and a set, by fixing the first argument of the former to the latter. The motivation comes from the semantics of Noun Phrases (also called Determiner Phrases) in natural languages, but in this article, I focus on the logical facts. However, my examples are taken among quantifiers appearing in natural languages, and at the end, I sketch two more principled linguistic (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  31. In memoriam: Per Lindström.Jouko Väänänen & Dag Westerståhl - 2010 - Theoria 76 (2):100-107.
  32. On the Aristotelian Square of Opposition.Dag Westerståhl - 2005 - In Felix Larsson (ed.), Kapten Mnemos Kolumbarium. Philosophical Communications.
    A common misunderstanding is that there is something logically amiss with the classical square of opposition, and that the problem is related to Aristotle’s and medieval philosophers’ rejection of empty terms. But [Parsons 2004] convincingly shows that most of these philosophers did not in fact reject empty terms, and that, when properly understood, there are no logical problems with the classical square. Instead, the classical square, compared to its modern version, raises the issue of the existential import of words like (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  33.  79
    Introduction: The philosophy of logical consequence and inference.Sten Lindström, Erik Palmgren & Dag Westerståhl - 2012 - Synthese 187 (3):817-820.
  34.  11
    Quantifiers in Natural Language A Survey of Some Recent Work.Dag Westerståhl - 1995 - In M. Krynicki, M. Mostowski & L. Szczerba (eds.), Quantifiers: Logics, Models and Computation. Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 359--408.
  35.  63
    Carnap’s Problem for Modal Logic.Denis Bonnay & Dag Westerståhl - 2023 - Review of Symbolic Logic 16 (2):578-602.
    We take Carnap’s problem to be to what extent standard consequence relations in various formal languages fix the meaning of their logical vocabulary, alone or together with additional constraints on the form of the semantics. This paper studies Carnap’s problem for basic modal logic. Setting the stage, we show that neighborhood semantics is the most general form of compositional possible worlds semantics, and proceed to ask which standard modal logics (if any) constrain the box operator to be interpreted as in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36. Parametric Types and Propositions in First-Order Situation Theory.Dag Westerståhl - 1990 - In Robin Cooper, Kuniaki Mukai & John Perry (eds.), Situation Theory and its Applications Vol. 1. CSLI Publications.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  37.  14
    Compositionality.Peter Pagin & Dag Westerståhl - 2011 - In Klaus von Heusinger, Claudia Maienborn & Paul Portner (eds.), Semantics: An International Handbook of Natural Language Meaning. Berlin, Germany: De Gruyter. pp. 96-123.
    This article is concerned with the principle of compositionality, i.e. the principle that the meaning of a complex expression is a function of the meanings of its parts and its mode of composition. After a brief historical background, a formal algebraic framework for syntax and semantics is presented. In this framework, both syntactic operations and semantic functions are partial. Using 20 the framework, the basic idea of compositionality is given a precise statement, and several variants, both weaker and stronger, as (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  38. Language, Logic, and Computation: the 1994 Moraga Proceedings.Dag Westerstahl & Jeremy Seligman (eds.) - 1996 - CSLI.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  14
    A situation-theoretic representations of text meaning: anaphora, quantification, and negation'.Dag Westerståhl, Björn Haglund & Torbjörn Lager - 1993 - In Peter Aczel, David Israel, Yosuhiro Katagiri & Stanley Peters (eds.), Situation Theory and its Applications Vol. CSLI Publications. pp. 375--408.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  31
    Compositionality in context.Dag Westerståhl, Alexandru Baltag & Johan van Benthem - 2021 - In A. Palmigiano & M. Zadrzadeh (eds.), Outstanding Contributions to Logic: Samson Abramsky. Springer.
    Compositionality is a principle used in logic, philosophy, mathematics, linguistics, and computer science for assigning meanings to language expressions in a systematic manner following syntactic construction, thereby allowing for a perspicuous algebraic view of the syntax-semantics interface. Yet the status of the principle remains under debate, with positions ranging from compositionality always being achievable to its having genuine empirical content. This paper attempts to sort out some major issues in all this from a logical perspective. First, we stress the fundamental (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  18
    Editorial.Dag Westerståhl - 1996 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 5 (1):V-V.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  22
    Generalized Quantifiers Meet Modal Neighborhood Semantics.Dag Westerståhl & Johan van Benthem - 2021 - In Judit Madarász & Gergely Székely (eds.), Hajnal Andréka and István Németi on Unity of Science: From Computing to Relativity Theory Through Algebraic Logic. Springer. pp. 187-206.
    In a mathematical perspective, neighborhood models for modal logic are generalized quantifiers, parametrized to points in the domain of objects/worlds. We explore this analogy further, connecting generalized quantifier theory and modal neighborhood logic. In particular, we find interesting analogies between conservativity for linguistic quantifiers and the locality of modal logic, and between the role of invariances in both fields. Moreover, we present some new completeness results for modal neighborhood logics of linguistically motivated classes of generalized quantifiers, and raise new types (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. Mening och logik.Dag Westerståhl - 1994 - Norsk Filosofisk Tidsskrift 1.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. Perspectives on the dispute between intuitionistic and classical mathematics.Dag Westerståhl - 2004 - In Christer Svennerlind (ed.), Ursus Philosophicus. Essays dedicated to Björn Haglund on his sixtieth birthday. Philosophical Communications.
    It is not unreasonable to think that the dispute between classical and intuitionistic mathematics might be unresolvable or 'faultless', in the sense of there being no objective way to settle it. If so, we would have a pretty case of relativism. In this note I argue, however, that there is in fact not even disagreement in any interesting sense, let alone a faultless one, in spite of appearances and claims to the contrary. A position I call classical pluralism is sketched, (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. Scope of the Journal.Dag Westerståhl - 1999 - Journal of Logic, Language, and Information 8:129-134.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. Svar till Bo Dahlin.Dag Westerståhl - 1981 - Norsk Filosofisk Tidsskrift 2 (4):39.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. Tal till Solomon Feferman.Dag Westerståhl - 2004 - Norsk Filosofisk Tidsskrift 1.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  66
    Logic, Language and Computation.Jerry Seligman & Dag Westerstahl (eds.) - 1996 - Center for the Study of Language and Inf.
    This volume presents work that evolved out of the Third Conference on Situation Theory and Its Applications, held at Oiso, Japan, in November of 1991. The chapters presented in this volume continue the mathematical development of situation theory, including the introduction of a graphical notation; and the applications of situation theory discussed are wide-ranging, including topics in natural language semantics and philosophical logic, and exploring the use of information theory in the social sciences. The research presented in this volume reflects (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49. ¸ Iteprawitz1994.Dag Prawitz, Brian Skyrms & Dag Westerståhl (eds.) - 1991 - Elsevier.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  11
    Logic and Philosophy of Science in Uppsala: Papers From the 9th International Congress of Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science.Dag Prawitz & Dag Westerståhl (eds.) - 1994 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
    This collection of 38 papers gives a cross-section of ongoing research in philosophy of science and philosophical logic. The papers, written by active researchers in the field and published here for the first time, are drawn from around 650 papers that were contributed to the 9th International Congress of Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science in Uppsala, Sweden, 1991. Some of the speakers whose contributions attracted special interest were invited to contribute their papers to this volume. A few papers appear (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 986