Results for 'Donald C. Ainslie'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  53
    Hume’s True Scepticism.Donald C. Ainslie - 2015 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK.
    David Hume is famous as a sceptical philosopher but the nature of his scepticism is difficult to pin down. Hume's True Scepticism provides the first sustained interpretation of Part 4 of Book 1 of Hume's Treatise: his deepest engagement with sceptical arguments, in which he notes that, while reason shows that we ought not to believe the verdicts of reason or the senses, we do so nonetheless. Donald C. Ainslie addresses Hume's theory of representation; his criticisms of Locke, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  2. Scepticism About Persons in Book II of Hume's Treatise.Donald C. Ainslie - 1999 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 37 (3):469-492.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Scepticism About Persons in Book II of Hume’s TreatiseDonald C. AinslieBook ii of Hume’s Treatise—especially its first two Parts on the “indirect passions” of pride, humility, love, and hatred—has mystified many of its interpreters.1 Hume clearly thinks these passions are important: Not only does he devote more space to them than to his treatment of causation, but in the “Abstract” to the Treatise, he tells us that Book II (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  3. Hume’s Reflections on the Identity and Simplicity of Mind.Donald C. Ainslie - 2001 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 62 (3):557-578.
    The article presents a new interpretation of Hume’s treatment of personal identity, and his later rejection of it in the “Appendix” to the Treatise. Hume’s project, on this interpretation, is to explain beliefs about persons that arise primarily within philosophical projects, not in everyday life. The belief in the identity and simplicity of the mind as a bundle of perceptions is an abstruse belief, not one held by the “vulgar” who rarely turn their minds on themselves so as to think (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  4. Adequate ideas and modest scepticism in Hume's metaphysics of space.Donald C. Ainslie - 2010 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 92 (1):39-67.
    In the Treatise of Human Nature , Hume argues that, because we have adequate ideas of the smallest parts of space, we can infer that space itself must conform to our representations of it. The paper examines two challenges to this argument based on Descartes's and Locke's treatments of adequate ideas, ideas that fully capture the objects they represent. The first challenge, posed by Arnauld in his Objections to the Meditations , asks how we can know that an idea is (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  5.  40
    Hume's Reflections on the Identity and Simplicity of Mind 1.Donald C. Ainslie - 2001 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 62 (3):557-578.
    The article presents a new interpretation of Hume's treatment of personal identity, and his later rejection of it in the “Appendix” to the Treatise. Hume's project, on this interpretation, is to explain beliefs about persons that arise primarily within philosophical projects, not in everyday life. the belief in the identity and simplicity of the mind as a bundle of perceptions is an abstruse belief, not one held by the “vulgar” who rarely turn their minds on themselves so as to think (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  6.  22
    Hume on Personal Identity.Donald C. Ainslie - 2008 - In Elizabeth S. Radcliffe (ed.), A Companion to Hume. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 140–156.
    This chapter contains section titled: Introduction Locke on Personal Identity Hume's Critique of Locke The Belief in Mental Unity Hume's Second Thoughts Some Interpretations Unity in Reflection References.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  7. Bioethics and the problem of pluralism.Donald C. Ainslie - 2002 - Social Philosophy and Policy 19 (2):1-28.
    The state that we inhabit plays a significant role in shaping our lives. For not only do its institutions constrain the kinds of lives we can lead, but it also claims the right to punish us if our choices take us beyond what it deems to be appropriate limits. Political philosophers have traditionally tried to justify the state's power by appealing to their preferred theories of justice, as articulated in complex and wide-ranging moral theories—utilitarianism, Kantianism, and the like. One of (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  8. The Cambridge Companion to Hume's Treatise.Donald C. Ainslie & Annemarie Butler (eds.) - 2014 - Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    Revered for his contributions to empiricism, skepticism and ethics, David Hume remains one of the most important figures in the history of Western philosophy. His first and broadest work, A Treatise of Human Nature, comprises three volumes, concerning the understanding, the passions and morals. He develops a naturalist and empiricist program, illustrating that the mind operates through the association of impressions and ideas. This Companion features essays by leading scholars that evaluate the philosophical content of the arguments in Hume's Treatise (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  9.  29
    Questioning Bioethics AIDS, Sexual Ethics, and the Duty to Warn.Donald C. Ainslie - 1999 - Hastings Center Report 29 (5):26-35.
    Bioethicists have virtually assumed that Tarasoff generated a duty to warn the sexual partners of an HIV‐positive man that they risked infection. Yet given the views of sex and of AIDS that have evolved in the gay community, in many cases the parallels to Tarasoff do not hold. Bioethicists should at the least attend to the community's views, and indeed should go beyond doing mere “professional ethics” to participate in the moral self‐exploration in which these views are located.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  10.  35
    AIDS and Sex: Is Warning a Moral Obligation?Donald C. Ainslie - 2002 - Health Care Analysis 10 (1):49-66.
    Common-sense holds that morality requirespeople who know that they are infected with theHuman Immunodeficiency Virus (HIV) to disclosethis fact to their sexual partners. But manygay men who are HIV-positive do not disclose,and AIDS Service Organizations (ASOs) promotepublic-health policies based on safer sex byall, rather than disclosure by those who knowthat they are infected. The paper shows thatthe common-sense view follows from a minimalsexual morality based on consent. ASOs'seeming rejection of the view follows fromtheir need to take seriously widespreadweakness of will (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  11.  33
    Hume, a Scottish Locke? Comments on Terence Penelhum’s Hume.Donald C. Ainslie - 2012 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 42 (S1):161-170.
    Where Terence Penelhum sees a deep continuity between John Locke's theory of ideas and David Hume's theory of perceptions, I argue that the two philosophers disagree over some fundamental issues in the philosophy of mind. While Locke treats ideas as imagistic objects that we recognize as such by a special kind of inner consciousness, Hume thinks that we do not normally recognize the imagistic content of our perceptions, and instead unselfconsciously take ourselves to sense a shared public world. My disagreement (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  33
    Hume's "life" and the virtues of the dying.Donald C. Ainslie - 2005 - In Thomas Mathien & D. G. Wright (eds.), Autobiography as Philosophy: The Philosophical Uses of Self-Presentation. Routledge.
  13. Principlism.Donald C. Ainslie - 1982 - In Warren T. Reich (ed.), Encyclopedia of Bioethics. Macmillan.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14.  15
    Précis of Hume's True Scepticism.Donald C. Ainslie - 2019 - Hume Studies 45 (1):95-99.
    In Hume's True Scepticism, I offer a new interpretation of David Hume's epistemology and philosophy of mind as presented in A Treatise of Human Nature.1 I approach this task by developing what I take to be the first comprehensive2 investigation of Part 4 of Book 1. The arguments Hume offers there have frequently been addressed by the secondary literature in a piecemeal fashion, especially his account of personal identity and of our belief in the external world. But I argue in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  22
    Reply to My Critics.Donald C. Ainslie - 2019 - Hume Studies 45 (1):129-141.
    I owe thanks to Annemarie Butler, Jonathan Cottrell, and Barry Stroud for their thoughtful criticism of my interpretation in Hume's True Scepticism of David Hume's epistemology and philosophy of mind as presented in A Treatise of Human Nature.1 Butler focuses on my account of the mental mechanisms Hume provides for our everyday beliefs about external objects. She also challenges my appeal to what Hume calls "secondary" ideas in my explanation of Humean introspection. Cottrell raises questions about my interpretation of perceptions (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. The Problem of the National Self in Hume's Theory of Justice.Donald C. Ainslie - 1995 - Hume Studies 21 (2):289-313.
  17.  63
    `Watching' medicine: Do bioethicists respect patients' privacy?Donald C. Ainslie - 2000 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 21 (6):537-552.
    Agich has identified `watching' – the formal orinformal observation of the medical setting – as oneof the four main roles of the clinical bioethicist. By an analysis of a case study involving a bioethicsstudent who engaged in watching at an HIV/AIDS clinicas part of his training, I raise questions about theethical justification of watching. I argue that theinvasion of privacy that watching entails makes theactivity unacceptable unless the watcher has receivedprior consent from the patients who are beingobserved. I conclude that, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. Consciousness and Personal Identity.Owen Ware & Donald C. Ainslie - 2014 - In Aaron Garrett (ed.), The Routledge Companion to Eighteenth Century Philosophy. Routledge. pp. 245-264.
    This paper offers an overview of consciousness and personal identity in eighteenth-century philosophy. Locke introduces the concept of persons as subjects of consciousness who also simultaneously recognize themselves as such subjects. Hume, however, argues that minds are nothing but bundles of perceptions, lacking intrinsic unity at a time or across time. Yet Hume thinks our emotional responses to one another mean that persons in everyday life are defined by their virtues, vices, bodily qualities, property, riches, and the like. Rousseau also (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19.  49
    Review: Hume, a Scottish Socrates? [REVIEW]Donald C. Ainslie - 2003 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 33 (1):133 - 154.
  20.  33
    Hume, a Scottish Socrates? [REVIEW]Donald C. Ainslie - 2003 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 33 (1):133-154.
  21. Projection and Realism in Hume's Philosophy. By P. J. E. Kail. [REVIEW]Donald C. Ainslie - 2009 - Metaphilosophy 40 (2):292-296.
    Peter Kail’s comprehensive, thoughtful, and challenging book focuses on Hume’s use of projectionFthe appeal to mental phenomena to explain manifest features of the worldFin his treatments of external objects, causation, and morality. Almost all interpreters of Hume acknowledge a role for projection, but Kail is the first to unpack the metaphor, and to show the different ways in which projection works in different domains.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  66
    Reason and Feeling in Hume's Action Theory and Moral Philosophy. [REVIEW]Donald C. Ainslie - 1999 - Hume Studies 25 (1-2):266-269.
    Generally speaking, there are two ways to oppose another philosopher's view. You can argue against it—for example, by finding counterexamples, showing that it entails various unpalatable or absurd conclusions, or by raising objections to the arguments offered in its support. Or you can offer an alternative account of the issue in question. These two sorts of responses are, of course, complementary, and Hume uses both in his attempt to reveal the errors of traditional approaches to ethics. While Hume's negative arguments (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  43
    Reason and Feeling in Hume's Action Theory and Moral Philosophy: Hume's Reasonable Passion (review). [REVIEW]Donald C. Ainslie - 1999 - Hume Studies 25 (1):266-269.
    Generally speaking, there are two ways to oppose another philosopher's view. You can argue against it—for example, by finding counterexamples, showing that it entails various unpalatable or absurd conclusions, or by raising objections to the arguments offered in its support. Or you can offer an alternative account of the issue in question. These two sorts of responses are, of course, complementary, and Hume uses both in his attempt to reveal the errors of traditional approaches to ethics. While Hume's negative arguments (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  58
    Review of Marina Frasca-spada, P. J. E. Kail (eds.), Impressions of Hume[REVIEW]Donald C. Ainslie - 2006 - Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2006 (4).
  25.  25
    Complexity, communication between cells, and identifying the functional components of living systems: Some observations.Donald C. Mikulecky - 1996 - Acta Biotheoretica 44 (3-4):179-208.
    The concept of complexity has become very important in theoretical biology. It is a many faceted concept and too new and ill defined to have a universally accepted meaning. This review examines the development of this concept from the point of view of its usefulness as a criteria for the study of living systems to see what it has to offer as a new approach. In particular, one definition of complexity has been put forth which has the necessary precision and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  26.  34
    Donald C. Ainslie, Hume's True Scepticism.Christopher A. Shrock - 2018 - Journal of Scottish Philosophy 16 (1):91-93.
  27. Donald C. Ainslie, Hume's True Scepticism (Oxford-New York: Oxford university Press, 2015). [REVIEW]Lorenzo Greco - 2017 - Rivista di Filosofia 108 (1):115-16.
  28. The myth of passage.Donald C. Williams - 1951 - Journal of Philosophy 48 (15):457-472.
  29. Hypothetical motivation.Donald C. Hubin - 1996 - Noûs 30 (1):31-54.
  30. Irrational desires.Donald C. Hubin - 1991 - Philosophical Studies 62 (1):23 - 44.
    Many believe that the rational evaluation of actions depends on the rational evaluation of even basic desires. Hume, though, viewed desires as "original existences" which cannot be contrary to either truth or reason. Contemporary critics of Hume, including Norman, Brandt and Parfit, have sought a basis for the rational evaluation of desires that would deny some basic desires reason-giving force. I side with Hume against these modern critics. Hume's concept of rational evaluation is admittedly too narrow; even basic desires are, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  31. Desires, Whims and Values.Donald C. Hubin - 2003 - The Journal of Ethics 7 (3):315-335.
    Neo-Humean instrumentalists hold that anagent's reasons for acting are grounded in theagent's desires. Numerous objections have beenleveled against this view, but the mostcompelling concerns the problem of ``aliendesires'' – desires with which the agent doesnot identify. The standard version ofneo-Humeanism holds that these desires, likeany others, generate reasons for acting. Avariant of neo-Humeanism that grounds anagent's reasons on her values, rather than allof her desires, avoids this implication, but atthe cost of denying that we have reasons to acton innocent whims. (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  32. What’s Special about Humeanism.Donald C. Hubin - 1999 - Noûs 33 (1):30-45.
    One of the attractions of the Humean instrumentalist theory of practical rationality is that it appears to offer a special connection between an agent's reasons and her motivation. The assumption that Humeanism is able to assert a strong connection between reason and motivation has been challenged, most notably by Christine Korsgaard. She argues that Humeanism is not special in the connection it allows to motivation. On the contrary, Humean theories of practical rationality do connect reasons and motivation in a unique (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  33. The groundless normativity of instrumental rationality.Donald C. Hubin - 2001 - Journal of Philosophy 98 (9):445-468.
    Neo-Humean instrumentalist theories of reasons for acting have been presented with a dilemma: either they are normatively trivial and, hence, inadequate as a normative theory or they covertly commit themselves to a noninstrumentalist normative principle. The claimed result is that no purely instrumentalist theory of reasons for acting can be normatively adequate. This dilemma dissolves when we understand what question neo-Humean instrumentalists are addressing. The dilemma presupposes that neo-Humeans are attempting to address the question of how to act, 'simpliciter'. Instead, (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  34.  15
    Wise Choices, Apt Feelings: A Theory of Normative Judgement.Donald C. Hubin - 1991 - Philosophical Quarterly 41 (163):252-256.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  35.  16
    The Groundless Normativity of Instrumental Rationality.Donald C. Hubin - 2001 - Journal of Philosophy 98 (9):445.
  36. On the Elements of Being: I.Donald C. Williams - 2004 - In Tim Crane & Katalin Farkas (eds.), Metaphysics: A Guide and Anthology. Oxford University Press UK.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   90 citations  
  37. The Moral Justification of Benefit/Cost Analysis.Donald C. Hubin - 1994 - Economics and Philosophy 10 (2):169-194.
    Benefit/cost analysis is a technique for evaluating programs, procedures, and actions; it is not a moral theory. There is significant controversy over the moral justification of benefit/cost analysis. When a procedure for evaluating social policy is challenged on moral grounds, defenders frequently seek a justification by construing the procedure as the practical embodiment of a correct moral theory. This has the apparent advantage of avoiding difficult empirical questions concerning such matters as the consequences of using the procedure. So, for example, (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  38. Universals and existents.Donald C. Williams - 1986 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 64 (1):1 – 14.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   64 citations  
  39. On the Elements of Being: I.Donald C. Williams - 1953 - In D. H. Mellor & Alex Oliver (eds.), Properties. Oxford University Press.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  40.  55
    On the Elements of Being: II.Donald C. Williams - 1953 - Review of Metaphysics 7 (2):171-192.
    If a bit of perceptual behavior is a trope, so is any response to a stimulus, and so is the stimulus, and so therefore, more generally, is every effect and its cause. When we say that the sunlight caused the blackening of the film we assert a connection between two tropes; when we say that Sunlight in general causes Blackening in general, we assert a corresponding relation between the corresponding universals. Causation is often said to relate events, and generally speaking (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  41. The Ground of Induction.Donald C. Williams - 1947 - Philosophy 24 (88):86-88.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  42.  16
    The Theory of Probability: An Inquiry Into the Logical and Mathematical Foundations of the Calculus of Probability.Donald C. Williams - 1950 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 11 (2):252-257.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  43.  13
    Probability and Induction.Donald C. Williams - 1950 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 10 (4):578-580.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  44.  81
    Dispensing with existence.Donald C. Williams - 1962 - Journal of Philosophy 59 (23):748-763.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  45. Non-Tuism.Donald C. Hubin - 1991 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 21 (4):441 - 468.
    Contractarians view justice as being defined by a contract made by rational individuals. No one supposes that this contract is actual, and the fact that it is merely hypothetical raises a number of questions both about the assumptions under which it would be actual and about the force of hypothetical agreement that is contingent on these assumptions.Particular contractarian theories must specify the circumstances of the agreement and the endowments, beliefs, desires, and degree and type of rationality of the agents. How (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  46. Malachi 3:1–12.Donald C. Polaski - 2000 - Interpretation: A Journal of Bible and Theology 54 (4):416-418.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. Parental Rights and Due Process.Donald C. Hubin - 1999 - The Journal of Law and Family Studies 1 (2):123-150.
    The U.S. Supreme Court regards parental rights as fundamental. Such a status should subject any legal procedure that directly and substantively interferes with the exercise of parental rights to strict scrutiny. On the contrary, though, despite their status as fundamental constitutional rights, parental rights are routinely suspended or revoked as a result of procedures that fail to meet even minimal standards of procedural and substantive due process. This routine and cavalier deprivation of parental rights takes place in the context of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  22
    Commentary.Donald C. Powell - 1984 - Business and Professional Ethics Journal 3 (2):23-23.
  49. Providing for Rights.Donald C. Hubin & Mark B. Lambeth - 1988 - Dialogue 27 (3):489-.
    Gauthier's version of the Lockean proviso (in Morals by Agreement) is inappropriate as the foundation for moral rights he takes it to be. This is so for a number of reasons. It lacks any proportionality test thus allowing arbitrarily severe harms to others to prevent trivial harms to oneself. It allows one to inflict any harm on another provided that if one did not do so, someone else would. And, by interpreting the notion of bettering or worsening one's position in (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  50.  62
    Necessary Facts.Donald C. Williams - 1963 - Review of Metaphysics 16 (4):601 - 626.
    My main thesis is that the necessary and its necessity are factual, or matters of fact, in the sense that they are realities on the same ontic plane or planes with any other beings there may be, physical, phenomenal, or Platonically transcendent, and are no more creatures of thought and speech than dogs and gravity are; if I think they are all physical actualities, this is only because I think everything is. I have a second thesis, however, which is that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000