Results for 'Bruce Bridgeman'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  7
    Metacontrast and lateral inhibition.Bruce Bridgeman - 1971 - Psychological Review 78 (6):528-539.
  2.  50
    A theory of visual stability across saccadic eye movements.Bruce Bridgeman, A. H. C. Van der Heijden & Boris M. Velichkovsky - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):247-258.
    We identify two aspects of the problem of maintaining perceptual stability despite an observer's eye movements. The first, visual direction constancy, is the (egocentric) stability of apparent positions of objects in the visual world relative to the perceiver. The second, visual position constancy, is the (exocentric) stability of positions of objects relative to each other. We analyze the constancy of visual direction despite saccadic eye movements.Three information sources have been proposed to enable the visual system to achieve stability: the structure (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  3. Failure to detect displacements of the visual world during saccadic eye movements.Bruce Bridgeman, David Hendry & L. Stark - 1975 - Vision Research 15:719-22.
  4.  23
    Free will and the functions of consciousness.Bruce Bridgeman - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):540-540.
  5.  6
    Modeling separate processing pathways for spatial and object vision.Bruce Bridgeman - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):398-398.
  6.  13
    Failure to integrate visual information from successive fixations.Bruce Bridgeman & Melanie Mayer - 1983 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 21 (4):285-286.
  7.  10
    A correlational model applied to metacontrast: Reply to Weisstein, Ozog, and Szoc.Bruce Bridgeman - 1977 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 10 (2):85-88.
  8. Attention and memory-driven effects in action studies.Philip Tseng, Timothy Lane & Bruce Bridgeman - 2016 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 39.
    : We provide empirical examples to conceptually clarify some items on Firestone & Scholl’s (F&S’s) checklist, and to explain perceptual effects from an attentional and memory perspective. We also note that action and embodied cognition studies seem to be most susceptible to misattributing attentional and memory effects as perceptual, and identify four characteristics unique to action studies and possibly responsible for misattributions.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9. Conscious vs unconscious processes: The case of vision.Bruce Bridgeman - 1992 - Theory and Psychology 2:73-88.
  10.  29
    A spatially oriented decision does not induce consciousness in a motor task.Bruce Bridgeman & Valerie Huemer - 1998 - Consciousness and Cognition 7 (3):454-464.
    Visual information follows at least two branches in the human nervous system, following a common input stage: a cognitive ''what'' branch governs perception and experience, while a sensorimotor ''how'' branch handles visually guided behavior though its outputs are unconscious. The sensorimotor system is probed with an isomorphic task, requiring a 1:1 relationship between target position and motor response. The cognitive system, in contrast, is probed with a forced qualitative decision, expressed verbally, about the location of a target. Normally, the cognitive (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  11.  38
    It is not evolutionary models, but models in general that social science needs.Bruce Bridgeman - 2006 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 29 (4):351-352.
    Mathematical models are potentially as useful for culture as for evolution, but cultural models must have different designs from genetic models. Social sciences must borrow from biology the idea of modeling, rather than the structure of models, because copying the product is fundamentally different from copying the design. Transfer of most cultural information from brains to artificial media increases the differences between cultural and biological information. (Published Online November 9 2006).
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  12.  36
    The grand illusion and Petit illusions: Interactions of perception and sensory coding.Bruce Bridgeman - 2002 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 9 (5-6):29-34.
    The Grand Illusion, the experience of a rich phenomenal visual world supported by a poor internal representation of that world, is echoed by petit illusions of the same sort. We can be aware of several aspects of an object or pattern, even when they are inconsistent with one another, because different neurological mechanisms code the various aspects separately. They are bound not by an internal linkage, but by the structure of the world itself. Illusions exploit this principle by introducing inconsistencies (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  13.  12
    Applications of predictive control in neuroscience.Bruce Bridgeman - 2013 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 36 (3):208-208.
  14.  39
    Action planning supplements mirror systems in language evolution.Bruce Bridgeman - 2005 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 28 (2):129-130.
    Mirror systems must be supplemented by a planning capability to allow language to evolve. A capability for creating, storing, and executing plans for sequences of actions, having evolved in primates, was applied to sequences of communicatory acts. Language could exploit this already-existing capability. Further steps in language evolution may parallel steps seen in the development of modern children.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  15. On the evolution of consciousness and language.Bruce Bridgeman - 1992 - Psycoloquy 3 (15).
    Psychology can be based on plans, internally held images of achievement that organize the stimulus-response links of traditional psychology. The hierarchical structure of plans must be produced, held, assigned priorities, and monitored. Consciousness is the operation of the plan-executing mechanism, enabling behavior to be driven by plans rather than immediate environmental contingencies. The mechanism unpacks a single internally held idea into a series of actions. New in this paper is the proposal that language uses this mechanism for communication, unpacking an (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  16.  21
    Theories of visual masking.Bruce Bridgeman - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):25-26.
  17.  41
    Brains + programs = minds.Bruce Bridgeman - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):427-428.
  18. Interactions between vision for perception and vision for behavior.Bruce Bridgeman - 2000 - In Yves Rossetti & Antti Revonsuo (eds.), Beyond Dissociation: Interaction Between Dissociated Implicit and Explicit Processing. John Benjamins.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  19.  14
    Iconic storage and saccadic eye movements.Bruce Bridgeman & Melanie Mayer - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):16-17.
  20.  35
    The dynamical model is a perceptron.Bruce Bridgeman - 1998 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 21 (5):631-632.
    Van Gelder's example of a dynamical model is a Perceptron. The similarity of dynamical models and Perceptrons in turn exemplifies the close relationship between dynamical and algorithmic models. Both are models, not literal descriptions of brains. The brain states of standard modeling are better conceived as processes in the dynamical sense, but algorithmic models remain useful.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  21.  16
    Artifacts and cognition: Evolution or cultural progress?Bruce Bridgeman - 2002 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 25 (3):403-403.
    Lack of symmetry of stone tools does not require that hominids making asymmetric tools are incapable of doing better. By analogy, differences between stone tools of early humans and modern technology arose without genetic change. A conservative assumption is that symmetry of stone artifacts may have arisen simply because symmetrical tools work better when used for striking and chopping rather than scraping.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  16
    Adaptation and the two-visual-systems hypothesis.Bruce Bridgeman - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (1):64-65.
  23.  9
    Attention shuts out irrelevant stimuli.Bruce Bridgeman - 1997 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 20 (4):769-769.
    Express saccade experiments imply that attention shifts take time. We extend this result with new experiments on manual reaction times. Reaction to a cued target is always slower than reaction to an uncued control, even when the cue is correct, if control trials are blocked to prevent interference from cued trials. Attention functions not to speed response, but to prevent responses at irrelevant locations.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. Consciousness and memory.Bruce Bridgeman - 1992 - Psycoloquy.
    Rosenthal makes assertions about what can and cannot happen without being conscious. Although his distinctions are informative, they do not substitute for data. We have little precise information that differentiates the immediate feeling of awareness, such as that possible for Korsakoff patients, from the later episodic memory of conscious experience. Appeals to introspection are useful starting points, but they are clearly are not to be trusted in this context. Rosenthal also asks why conscious thinking would be more efficacious than thinking (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25.  1
    Consciousness around the time of saccadic eye movements.Bruce Bridgeman - 2016 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 39.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  31
    Cortical models and the neurological gap.Bruce Bridgeman - 1998 - Consciousness and Cognition 7 (2):157-158.
  27. Commentary on: A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness. Authors' reply.Bruce Bridgeman, Naoyuki Osaka, Stephen E. Robbins, Peter D. Sparks & Ee Krieckhaus - 2004 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 27 (6):904-908.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  15
    Direct perception and a call for primary perception.Bruce Bridgeman - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):382-383.
  29.  23
    Defining visuomotor dissociations and an application to the oculomotor system.Bruce Bridgeman - 2004 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 27 (1):27-28.
    The perception/planning–control conception has a direct predecessor in a cognitive/sensorimotor scheme, where the cognitive branch includes Glover's perception and planning functions. The sensorimotor branch corresponds to Glover's control function. The cognitive/sensorimotor scheme, like the perception/planning–control scheme, differentiates between motor planning and direct motor control, which is inaccessible to awareness or to long-term memory.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  12
    Events and processes in neural stimulus coding: Some limitations and an applicaton to metacontrast.Bruce Bridgeman - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (2):257-258.
  31.  12
    Extending reference signal theory to rapid movements.Bruce Bridgeman & Jean Blouin - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):315-316.
  32.  44
    Grammar originates in action planning, not in cognitive and sensorimotor visual systems.Bruce Bridgeman - 2003 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26 (3):287-287.
    While the PREDICATE(x) structure requires close coordination of subject and predicate, both represented in consciousness, the cognitive (ventral), and sensorimotor (dorsal) pathways operate in parallel. Sensorimotor information is unconscious and can contradict cognitive spatial information. A more likely origin of linguistic grammar lies in the mammalian action planning process. Neurological machinery evolved for planning of action sequences becomes applied to planning communicatory sequences.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  50
    Hyperbolas and hyperbole: The free will problem remains.Bruce Bridgeman - 2005 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 28 (5):652-653.
    Hyperbolic theories have the fatal flaw that because of their vertical asymptote they predict irresistible choice of immediate rewards, regardless of future contingencies. They work only for simple situations. Theories incorporating intermediate unconscious choices are more flexible, but are neither exponential nor hyperbolic in their predictions. They don't solve the free will paradox, which may be just a consistent illusion.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  18
    How our world remains stable despite disturbing influences.Bruce Bridgeman, A. H. C. Van der Heijden & Boris M. Velichkovsky - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):282-292.
  35.  33
    Implicit and explicit representations of visual space.Bruce Bridgeman - 1999 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 22 (5):759-760.
    The visual system captures a unique contrast between implicit and explicit representation where the same event (location of a visible object) is coded in both ways in parallel. A method of differentiating the two representations is described using an illusion that affects only the explicit representation. Consistent with predictions, implicit information is available only from targets presently visible, but, surprisingly, a two-alternative decision does not disturb the implicit representation.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36.  12
    Independent evidence for neural systems mediating blindsight.Bruce Bridgeman - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):450.
  37.  14
    Isomorphism is where you find it.Bruce Bridgeman - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (4):658.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38.  21
    Intention itself will disappear when its mechanisms are known.Bruce Bridgeman - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):598-599.
  39.  19
    Is the dual-route theory possible in phonetically regular languages?Bruce Bridgeman - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):331-332.
  40.  15
    Mimetic culture and modern sports: A synthesis.Bruce Bridgeman & Margarita Azmitia - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):751-752.
  41.  39
    Neuroanatomy and function in two visual systems.Bruce Bridgeman - 2000 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 23 (4):535-536.
    Neuroanatomy and neurophysiology are insufficient to specify function. Modeling is essential to elucidate function, but psychophysics is also required. An example is the cognitive and sensorimotor branches of the visual system: anatomy shows direct cross talk between the branches. Psychophysics in normal humans shows links from cognitive to sensorimotor, but the reverse link is excluded by visual illusions affecting the cognitive system but not the sensorimotor system.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  25
    Neurologizing mental imagery: the physiological optics of the mind's eye.Bruce Bridgeman - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):550-550.
  43.  22
    Neural reuse implies distributed coding.Bruce Bridgeman - 2010 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 33 (4):269-270.
    Both distributed coding, with its implication of neural reuse, and more specialized function have been recognized since the beginning of brain science. A controversy over imageless thought threw introspection into disrepute as a scientific method, making more objective methods dominate. It is known in information science that one element, such as a bit in a computer, can participate in coding many independent states; in this commentary, an example is given.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  10
    One-generation lamarckism: The role of environment in genetic development.Bruce Bridgeman - 2007 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 30 (4):367-368.
    Environment can provide information used in development – information that can appear to be genetically given and that was previously assumed to be so. Examples include growth of the eye until it achieves good focus, and structuring of receptive fields in the visual cortex by environmental information. The process can be called one-generation Lamarckism because information acquired from the environment is used to structure the organism and because the capacity to acquire this information is inherited.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  63
    Relations between the physiology of attention and the physiology of consciousness.Bruce Bridgeman - 1986 - Psychological Research 48:259-266.
  46.  8
    Relationship of saccadic suppression to space constancy.Bruce Bridgeman, A. H. C. Van der Heijden & Boris M. Velichkovsky - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (3):553-554.
  47.  11
    Spatial and cognitive vision differentiate at low levels, but not in language.Bruce Bridgeman - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):240-240.
  48.  8
    Skeletal and oculomotor control systems compared.Bruce Bridgeman - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):212-212.
  49.  17
    Toward a neurological theory of eidetic imagery.Bruce Bridgeman - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):598-598.
  50. Taking distributed coding seriously.Bruce Bridgeman - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (4):717-717.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 1000