Results for 'Simon P. Liversedge'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  86
    Saccadic eye movements and cognition.Simon P. Liversedge & John M. Findlay - 2000 - Trends in Cognitive Sciences 4 (1):6-14.
  2.  38
    Universality in eye movements and reading: A trilingual investigation.Simon P. Liversedge, Denis Drieghe, Xin Li, Guoli Yan, Xuejun Bai & Jukka Hyönä - 2016 - Cognition 147 (C):1-20.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  3.  5
    Universality in eye movements and reading: A replication with increased power.Simon P. Liversedge, Henri Olkoniemi, Chuanli Zang, Xin Li, Guoli Yan, Xuejun Bai & Jukka Hyönä - 2024 - Cognition 242 (C):105636.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  87
    Beyond isolated word recognition.Simon P. Liversedge, Hazel I. Blythe & Denis Drieghe - 2012 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 35 (5):31-32.
    In this commentary we concur with Frost's view of the centrality of universal principles in models of word identification. However, we argue that other processes in sentence comprehension also fundamentally constrain the nature of written word identification. Furthermore, these processes appear to be universal. We, therefore, argue that universality in word identification should not be considered in isolation, but instead in the context of other linguistic processes that occur during normal reading.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5.  41
    Psycholinguistic processes affect fixation durations and orthographic information affects fixation locations: Can e-z reader cope?Simon P. Liversedge & Sarah J. White - 2003 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26 (4):492-493.
    This commentary focuses on two aspects of eye movement behaviour that E-Z Reader 7 currently makes no attempt to explain: the influence of higher order psycholinguistic processes on fixation durations, and orthographic influences on initial and refixation locations on words. From our understanding of the current version of the model, it is not clear how it may be readily modified to account for existing empirical data.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  44
    Children's comprehension of sentences with focus particles.Kevin B. Paterson, Simon P. Liversedge, Caroline Rowland & Ruth Filik - 2003 - Cognition 89 (3):263-294.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  7.  7
    Vocal emotion recognition in attention-deficit hyperactivity disorder: a meta-analysis.Rohanna C. Sells, Simon P. Liversedge & Georgia Chronaki - forthcoming - Cognition and Emotion.
    There is debate within the literature as to whether emotion dysregulation (ED) in Attention-Deficit Hyperactivity Disorder (ADHD) reflects deviant attentional mechanisms or atypical perceptual emotion processing. Previous reviews have reliably examined the nature of facial, but not vocal, emotion recognition accuracy in ADHD. The present meta-analysis quantified vocal emotion recognition (VER) accuracy scores in ADHD and controls using robust variance estimation, gathered from 21 published and unpublished papers. Additional moderator analyses were carried out to determine whether the nature of VER (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  11
    The FVF framework and target prevalence effects.Tamaryn Menneer, Hayward J. Godwin, Simon P. Liversedge, Anne P. Hillstrom, Valerie Benson, Erik D. Reichle & Nick Donnelly - 2017 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 40.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  11
    Phonological parafoveal pre-processing in children reading English sentences.Sara V. Milledge, Chuanli Zang, Simon P. Liversedge & Hazel I. Blythe - 2022 - Cognition 225 (C):105141.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  27
    Against Relational Value.Simon P. James - 2022 - The Harvard Review of Philosophy 29:45-54.
    In some environmental circles, talk of relational values is very much in fashion. It is said that we must think in terms of such values if we are to understand how such things as canyons, mangroves, and coral reefs matter to people. But that is bad advice. Appeals to relational values are typically misleading in several respects. Granted, those who make such appeals often do so in order to make the important point that some values are neither intrinsic nor instrumental (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  11.  29
    Natural Meanings and Cultural Values.Simon P. James - 2019 - Environmental Ethics 41 (1):3-16.
    In many cases, rivers, mountains, forests, and other so-called natural entities have value for us because they contribute to our well-being. According to the standard model of such value, they have instrumental or “service” value for us on account of their causal powers. That model tends, however, to come up short when applied to cases when nature contributes to our well-being by virtue of the religious, political, historical, personal, or mythic meanings it bears. To make sense of such cases, a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  12.  25
    Why Old Things Matter.Simon P. James - 2015 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 12 (3):313-329.
    It is, I suggest, unclear whether any old inanimate objects deserve to be treated with respect simply because they are old. Yet this does not entail that an object’s age has no bearing at all on the question of how it may permissibly be treated. I defend the claim that those who fail to take seriously the histories of old inanimate objects typically deserve to be criticized on aretaic grounds. Such people, I argue, tend to lack the virtue of humility.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  13.  5
    Do microenvironmental changes disrupt multicellular organisation with ageing, enacting and favouring the cancer cell phenotype?Simon P. Castillo, Juan E. Keymer & Pablo A. Marquet - 2021 - Bioessays 43 (2):2000126.
    Cancer is a singular cellular state, the emergence of which destabilises the homeostasis reached through the evolution to multicellularity. We present the idea that the onset of the cellular disobedience to the metazoan functional and structural architecture, known as the cancer phenotype, is triggered by changes in the cell's external environment that occur with ageing: what ensues is a breach of the social contract of multicellular life characteristic of metazoans. By integrating old ideas with new evidence, we propose that with (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  14. Zen Buddhism and Environmental Ethics.Simon P. James - 2005 - Environmental Values 14 (2):281-283.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  15.  76
    Ecosystem Services and the Value of Places.Simon P. James - 2016 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 19 (1):101-113.
    In the US Environmental Protection Agency, the World Wide Fund for Nature and many other environmental organisations, it is standard practice to evaluate particular woods, wetlands and other such places on the basis of the ‘ecosystem services’ they are thought to provide. I argue that this practice cannot account for one important way in which places are of value to human beings. When they play integral roles in our lives, particular places have a kind of value which cannot be adequately (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  16.  26
    The Trouble with Environmental Values.Simon P. James - 2016 - Environmental Values 25 (2):131-144.
    If we are to assess whether our attitudes towards nature are morally, aesthetically or in any other way appropriate or inappropriate, then we will need to know what those attitudes are. Drawing on the works of Katie McShane, Alan Holland and Christine Swanton, I challenge the common assumption that to love, respect, honour, cherish or adopt any other sort of pro-attitude towards any natural X simply is to value X in some way and to some degree. Depending on how one (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  17.  48
    M erleau‐ P onty and metaphysical realism.Simon P. James - 2018 - European Journal of Philosophy 26 (4):1312-1323.
    Global metaphysical antirealism (or “antirealism”) is often thought to entail that the identity of each and every concrete entity in our world ultimately depends on us—on our adoption of certain social and linguistic conventions, for instance, or on our use of certain conceptual schemes. Drawing on the middle‐period works of Maurice Merleau‐Ponty, I contend that metaphysical antirealism entails nothing of the sort. For Merleau‐Ponty, I argue, entities do not ultimately owe their identities to us, even though—as he puts it—their “articulations (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  18.  7
    The presence of nature: a study in phenomenology and environmental philosophy.Simon P. James - 2009 - New York: Palgrave-Macmillan.
    Are any nonhuman animals conscious? Why, if at all, should we strive to conserve natural environments? In what sense are we parts of nature? In this book, Simon James draws on a range of philosophical and literary sources to develop original answers to these and other questions, setting out a refreshingly new approach to environmental philosophy"--Provided by publisher.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  19.  25
    Finding - and Failing to Find - Meaning in Nature.Simon P. James - 2013 - Environmental Values 22 (5):609-625.
    This paper is about how we should evaluate our tendencies to find - or fail to find - different meanings in the natural world. It has three aims: (1) to show that some virtues and vices can be exhibited in our tendencies to find or to overlook the meanings of natural things, even if it is unclear whether any can only be exhibited in our relations with such things; (2) to categorise some of the relevant virtues and vices; and (3) (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  20.  26
    Madhyamaka, Metaphysical Realism, and the Possibility of an Ancestral World.Simon P. James - 2019 - Philosophy East and West 68 (4):1116-1133.
    It is the evening of January 11, 1951. A. J. Ayer retires to a Parisian bar for a post-lecture drink, where he is joined by Georges Batailles, Maurice MerleauPonty, and the physicist Georges Ambrosino. They argue until 3 a.m. The point at issue: Was there a sun before human beings existed? Ayer says "yes," the other three say "no."1Now imagine that a fifth person joins the debate—a Mādhyamika. She argues that because nothing exists independently of conceptual imputation, since, as she (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  21.  40
    Protecting Nature for the Sake of Human Beings.Simon P. James - 2015 - Ratio 29 (2):213-227.
    It is often assumed that to say that nature should be protected for the sake of human beings just is to say that it should be protected because it is a means to one or more anthropocentric ends. I argue that this assumption is false. In some contexts, claims that a particular natural X should be protected for our sakes mean that X should be protected, not because it is a means to anthropocentric ends, but because it is part of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  22.  51
    Human virtues and natural values.Simon P. James - 2006 - Environmental Ethics 28 (4):339-353.
    In several works, Holmes Rolston, III has argued that a satisfactory environmental ethic cannot be built on a virtue ethical foundation. His first argument amounts to the charge that because virtue ethics is by nature “self-centered” or egoistic, it is also inherently “human-centered” and hence ill suited to treating environmental matters. According to his second argument, virtue ethics is perniciously human-centeredsince it “locates” the value of a thing, not in the thing itself, but in the agent who is “ennobled” by (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  23.  39
    Against Holism:Rethinking Buddhist Environmental Ethics.Simon P. James - 2007 - Environmental Values 16 (4):447-461.
    Environmental thinkers sympathetic to Buddhism sometimes reason as follows: (1) A holistic view of the world, according to which humans are regarded as being 'one' with nature, will necessarily engender environmental concern; (2) the Buddhist teaching of 'emptiness' represents such a view; therefore (3) Buddhism is an environmentally-friendly religion. In this paper, I argue that the first premise of this argument is false (a holistic view of the world can be reconciled with a markedly eco-unfriendly attitude) as is the second (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  24.  13
    Rarity and endangerment: Why do they matter?Simon P. James - forthcoming - Environmental Values.
    It is often supposed that valuable organisms are more valuable if they are rare. Likewise if they belong to endangered species. I consider what kinds of value rarity and endangerment can add in such cases. I argue that individual organisms of a valuable species typically have instrumental value as means to the end of preserving their species. This progenitive value, I suggest, tends to increase exponentially with rarity. Endlings, for their part, typically have little progenitive value; however, I argue that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  36
    Suffering and the primacy of virtue.Simon P. James - 2019 - Analysis 79 (4):605-613.
    Some people claim that some instances of suffering are intrinsically bad in an impersonal way. If it were true, that claim might seem to count against virtue ethics and for consequentialism. Drawing on the works of Jason Kawall, Christine Swanton and Nietzsche, I consider some reasons for thinking that it is, however, false. I argue, moreover, that even if it were true, a virtue ethicist could consistently acknowledge its truth.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26.  50
    Phenomenology and the Problem of Animal Minds.Simon P. James - 2009 - Environmental Values 18 (1):33 - 49.
    Attempts to determine whether nonhuman animals have minds are often thought to raise a particular sceptical concern; I call it the problem of animal minds. If there are such things as animal minds, the sceptic reasons, they will be private realms to which we humans do not have direct epistemological access. So how could one ever know for certain that animals are not mindless mechanisms? In this paper I use a phenomenological approach to show that this familiar sceptical problem presupposes (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  27.  89
    Merleau‐Ponty, Metaphysical Realism and the Natural World1.Simon P. James - 2007 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 15 (4):501 – 519.
    Environmental thinkers often suppose that the natural world (or some parts of it, at least) exists in its own right, independent of human concerns. The arguments developed in this paper suggest that it is possible to do justice to this thought without endorsing some form of metaphysical realism. Thus the early sections look to Merleau-Ponty's Phenomenology of Perception to develop an anti-realist account of the independent reality of the natural world, one, it is argued, that has certain advantages over the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  28.  50
    Buddhism and the Ethics of Species Conservation.Simon P. James - 2006 - Environmental Values 15 (1):85 - 97.
    Efforts to conserve endangered species of animal are, in some important respects, at odds with Buddhist ethics. On the one hand, being abstract entities, species cannot suffer, and so cannot be proper objects of compassion or similar moral virtues. On the other, Buddhist commitments to equanimity tend to militate against the idea that the individual members of endangered species have greater value than those of less-threatened ones. This paper suggests that the contribution of Buddhism to the issue of species conservation (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  29.  21
    Human Virtues and Natural Values.Simon P. James - 2006 - Environmental Ethics 28 (4):339-353.
    In several works, Holmes Rolston, III has argued that a satisfactory environmental ethic cannot be built on a virtue ethical foundation. His first argument amounts to the charge that because virtue ethics is by nature “self-centered” or egoistic, it is also inherently “human-centered” and hence ill suited to treating environmental matters. According to his second argument, virtue ethics is perniciously human-centeredsince it “locates” the value of a thing, not in the thing itself, but in the agent who is “ennobled” by (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  30.  7
    Zen Buddhism and Environmental Ethics.Simon P. James - 2004 - Routledge.
  31.  87
    “Thing-Centered” Holism in Buddhism, Heidegger, and Deep Ecology.Simon P. James - 2000 - Environmental Ethics 22 (4):359-375.
    I address the problem of reconciling environmental holism with the intrinsic value of individual beings. Drawing upon Madhyamaka Buddhism, the later philosophy of Martin Heidegger, and deep ecology, I present a distinctly holistic conception of nature that, nevertheless, retains a commitment to the intrinsic worth of individual beings. I conclude with an examination of the practical implications of this “thing-centered holism” for environmental ethics.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  32.  26
    “Nothing Truly Wild is Unclean”: Muir, Misanthropy, and the Aesthetics of Dirt.Simon P. James - 2014 - Environmental Ethics 36 (3):357-363.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33.  31
    Environmental Philosophy: An Introduction.Simon P. James - 2015 - Polity.
    Climate change, habitat loss, rising extinction rates - such problems call for more than just new policies and practices. They raise fundamental questions about the world and our place in it. What, for instance, is the natural world? Do we humans belong to it? Which parts of it are we morally obliged to protect? Drawing on an exceptionally wide range of sources, from virtue ethics to Buddhism, leading environmental philosopher Simon P. James sets out to answer these vitally important (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  6
    Buddhism and Environmental Ethics.Simon P. James - 2013 - In Steven M. Emmanuel (ed.), A Companion to Buddhist Philosophy. Chichester, UK: Wiley. pp. 599–612.
    Like Buddhism, environmental ethics encompasses a wide variety of approaches, positions, and traditions. The seminal works of the field most of which were written by North Americans, Scandinavians, and Australians often gave the impression that environmental ethics is primarily about our moral relations with the wilder parts of the biosphere. In certain respects, the ecological conception of the world chimes with the worldview of early Buddhism. First, that worldview of the Buddhism is in one sense of the term, naturalistic. Second, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35.  25
    Cherished Places and Ecosystem Services.Simon P. James - 2013 - Ethics, Policy and Environment 16 (3):264-266.
    Mark Sagoff claims that if we are to explain what moves people to protect the natural world, we will need to refer to their ‘cultural, aesthetic, and moral ties’ to the ‘places they cherish or love...
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36.  28
    An introduction to buddhist ethics by Peter Harvey cambridge university press, 2000, pp. XX + 478.Simon P. James - 2001 - Philosophy 76 (1):158-174.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  9
    Conflict and Resolution.Simon P. James - 2017 - Environmental Values 26 (5):535-538.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  52
    Cultural Ecosystem Services: A Critical Assessment.Simon P. James - 2015 - Ethics, Policy and Environment 18 (3):338-350.
    This paper is about the practice of evaluating ecosystems on the basis of the cultural services they provide. My first aim is to assess the various objections that have been made to this practice. My second is to argue that when particular places are integral to people’s lives, their value cannot be adequately conceived in terms of the provision of cultural ecosystem services. It follows, I conclude, that the ecosystem services framework can provide only a very limited account of the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  87
    For the Sake of a Stone? Inanimate Things and the Demands of Morality.Simon P. James - 2011 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 54 (4):384-397.
    Abstract Everyday inanimate things such as stones, teapots and bicycles are not objects to which moral agents could have direct duties; they do not have moral status. It is usually assumed that there is therefore no reason to think that a morally good person would, on account of her goodness, be disposed to treat them well for their own sakes. I challenge this assumption. I begin by showing that to act for the sake of an entity need not be to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40.  9
    Letting Nature Take its Course.Simon P. James - 2016 - Environmental Values 25 (4):381-384.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  34
    Nature’s Indifference.Simon P. James - 2019 - Environmental Ethics 41 (2):115-128.
    Contrary to what writers such as Hans Jonas and Val Plumwood suggest, much of nature is indifferent to human interests. Mountains, glaciers, sun-baked salt pans—such entities care neither about what interests us humans nor about what is objectively in our interests. It might be hard to see how the property of being indifferent, in this sense, could add value. But it can. For those of us who inhabit highly technological, user-friendly environments, entities such as mountains can have therapeutic value precisely (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  56
    Philistinism and the Preservation of Nature.Simon P. James - 2013 - Philosophy 88 (1):101-114.
    It is clear that natural entities can be preserved – they can be preserved because they can be harmed or destroyed, or in various other ways adversely affected. I argue that in light of the rise of scientism and other forms of philistinism, the political, religious, mythic, personal and historical meanings that people find in those entities can also be preserved. Against those who impugn disciplines such as fine arts, philosophy and sociology, I contend that this sort of preservation requires (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  5
    Calvin and the Whigs: A Study in Historical Political Theology, written by Ruben Alvarado.Simon P. Kennedy - 2018 - Philosophia Reformata 83 (1):141-142.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  12
    The Kingdom of Man: Genesis and Failure of the Modern Project.Simon P. Kennedy - 2020 - The European Legacy 26 (3-4):440-442.
    Modernity, that amorphous and perhaps unhappy creation of periodisation, is both a mystery and a problem (in the sense of providing exis...
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  23
    Planners or performers? Reflections on indigenous dryland farming in northern Burkina Faso.Simon P. J. Batterbury - 1996 - Agriculture and Human Values 13 (3):12-22.
    Indigenous agricultural practices in semiarid West Africa must be seen as dynamic operations that serve different ends. These ends are not only agricultural, but symbolic. By highlighting how farmers in the Central Plateau region of Burkina Faso organize their farming strategies, the “agriculture as performance” arguments developed by Richards (1987, 1993) can be both challenged and extended from the humid forest zone of West Africa. Farmers, it can be argued, are also keen “planners;” in order to meet their goals they (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. Paine, Jefferson, and revolutionary radicalism in early national America.Simon P. Newman - 2013 - In Simon P. Newman & Peter S. Onuf (eds.), Paine and Jefferson in the Age of Revolutions. University of Virginia Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  3
    Cancer progression: A journey through the past (with the same stops)?Simon P. Castillo - 2021 - Bioessays 43 (7):2100088.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  19
    Freedom of Information Act: scalpel or just a sharp knife?: Table 1.Simon P. Hammond, Jane L. Cross, Fiona M. Poland, Martyn Patel, Bridget Penhale, Toby O. Smith & Chris Fox - 2017 - Journal of Medical Ethics 43 (1):60-62.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  39
    Carthage and Sicily.Simon P. Ellis - 1988 - The Classical Review 38 (01):89-.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  16
    The Role of Notation and Knowledge Representation in the Determination of Programming Strategy: A Framework for Integrating Models of Programming Behavior.Simon P. Davies - 1991 - Cognitive Science 15 (4):547-572.
    A number of accounts of expert programming behavior have been advanced. These models of the programming activity have served to highlight the range of factors that are thought to underpin programming strategy. However, such accounts have tended to emphasize either the effects of the organization of the programmer's knowledge representation or the role played by features of the notation of the task language on the emergence, development, and support of particular forms of strategy. Such work has neglected to (a) provide (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 1000