Results for 'Peter Milne'

979 found
Order:
  1.  55
    What price cheap food?Michael C. Appleby, Neil Cutler, John Gazzard, Peter Goddard, John A. Milne, Colin Morgan & Andrew Redfern - 2003 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 16 (4):395-408.
    This paper is the report of a meetingthat gathered many of the UK's most senioranimal scientists with representatives of thefarming industry, consumer groups, animalwelfare groups, and environmentalists. Therewas strong consensus that the current economicstructure of agriculture cannot adequatelyaddress major issues of concern to society:farm incomes, food security and safety, theneeds of developing countries, animal welfare,and the environment. This economic structure isbased primarily on competition betweenproducers and between retailers, driving foodprices down, combined with externalization ofmany costs. These issues must be addressed (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  2.  72
    II—Peter Milne: What is the Normative Role of Logic?Peter Milne - 2009 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 83 (1):269-298.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  3.  10
    Impressions of enforced disintegration and bursting in the visual perception of collision events.Peter A. White & Alan Milne - 1999 - Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 128 (4):499.
  4.  24
    Philosophy of Science in the Twentieth Century: Four Central Themes.Reading the Book of Nature: an Introduction to the Philosophy of Science.Common Sense, Science and Scepticism: a Historical Introduction to the Theory of Knowledge.Peter Milne - 1995 - Philosophical Quarterly 45 (180):379-384.
  5.  49
    On the completeness of non-philonian stoic logic.Peter Milne - 1995 - History and Philosophy of Logic 16 (1):39-64.
    The majority of formal accounts attribute to Stoic logicians the classical truth-functional understanding of the material conditional and exclusive disjunction.These interpretations were disputed,...
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  6.  21
    Minimal doxastic logic: probabilistic and other completeness theorems.Peter Milne - 1993 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 34 (4):499-526.
  7.  12
    Operations are punctuation marks'.Peter Milne - 2013 - In Peter M. Sullivan & Michael D. Potter (eds.), Wittgenstein's Tractatus: history and interpretation. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 97.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  15
    Inference to the Best Explanation. [REVIEW]Peter Milne - 1993 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53 (4):970-972.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  9. Log[p(h/eb)/p(h/b)] is the one true measure of confirmation.Peter Milne - 1996 - Philosophy of Science 63 (1):21-26.
    Plausibly, when we adopt a probabilistic standpoint any measure Cb of the degree to which evidence e confirms hypothesis h relative to background knowledge b should meet these five desiderata: Cb > 0 when P > P < 0 when P < P; Cb = 0 when P = P. Cb is some function of the values P and P assume on the at most sixteen truth-functional combinations of e and h. If P < P and P = P then (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   89 citations  
  10. Bruno de finetti and the logic of conditional events.Peter Milne - 1997 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 48 (2):195-232.
    This article begins by outlining some of the history—beginning with brief remarks of Quine's—of work on conditional assertions and conditional events. The upshot of the historical narrative is that diverse works from various starting points have circled around a nexus of ideas without convincingly tying them together. Section 3 shows how ideas contained in a neglected article of de Finetti's lead to a unified treatment of the topics based on the identification of conditional events as the objects of conditional bets. (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  11. Not every truth has a truthmaker.Peter Milne - 2005 - Analysis 65 (3):221–224.
    First paragraph: Truthmaker theory maintains that for every truth there is something, some thing, some entity, that makes it true. Balking at the prospect that logical truths are made true by any particular thing, a consequence that may in fact be hard to avoid (see Restall 1996, Read 2000), this principle of truthmaking is sometimes restricted to (logically) contingent truths. I aim to show that even in its restricted form, the principle is provably false.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  12. What is the Normative Role of Logic?Peter Milne - 2009 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 83 (1):269-298.
    In making assertions one takes on commitments to the consistency of what one asserts and to the logical consequences of what one asserts. Although there is no quick link between belief and assertion, the dialectical requirements on assertion feed back into normative constraints on those beliefs that constitute one's evidence. But if we are not certain of many of our beliefs and that uncertainty is modelled in terms of probabilities, then there is at least prima facie incoherence between the normative (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  13. Act and value: Expectation and the representability of moral theories.Graham Oddie & Peter Milne - 1991 - Theoria 57 (1-2):42-76.
    According to the axiologist the value concepts are basic and the deontic concepts are derivative. This paper addresses two fundamental problems that arise for the axiologist. Firstly, what ought the axiologist o understand by the value of an act? Second, what are the prospects in principle for an axiological representation of moral theories. Can the deontic concepts of any coherent moral theory be represented by an agent-netural axiology: (1) whatever structure those concepts have and (2) whatever the causal structure of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  14. Classical harmony: Rules of inference and the meaning of the logical constants.Peter Milne - 1994 - Synthese 100 (1):49 - 94.
    The thesis that, in a system of natural deduction, the meaning of a logical constant is given by some or all of its introduction and elimination rules has been developed recently in the work of Dummett, Prawitz, Tennant, and others, by the addition of harmony constraints. Introduction and elimination rules for a logical constant must be in harmony. By deploying harmony constraints, these authors have arrived at logics no stronger than intuitionist propositional logic. Classical logic, they maintain, cannot be justified (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  15.  93
    Harmony, Purity, Simplicity and a “Seemingly Magical Fact”.Peter Milne - 2002 - The Monist 85 (4):498-534.
    In his penetrating and thought-provoking article “What Is Logic?” Ian Hacking flags an issue that he leaves undiscussed.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  16. Not every truth has a truthmaker II.Peter Milne - 2013 - Analysis 73 (3):473-481.
    A proof employing no semantic terms is offered in support of the claim that there can be truths without truthmakers. The logical resources used in the proof are weak but do include the structural rule Contraction.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  17. On Gödel Sentences and What They Say.Peter Milne - 2007 - Philosophia Mathematica 15 (2):193-226.
    Proofs of Gödel's First Incompleteness Theorem are often accompanied by claims such as that the gödel sentence constructed in the course of the proof says of itself that it is unprovable and that it is true. The validity of such claims depends closely on how the sentence is constructed. Only by tightly constraining the means of construction can one obtain gödel sentences of which it is correct, without further ado, to say that they say of themselves that they are unprovable (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  18. Subformula and separation properties in natural deduction via small Kripke models: Subformula and separation properties.Peter Milne - 2010 - Review of Symbolic Logic 3 (2):175-227.
    Various natural deduction formulations of classical, minimal, intuitionist, and intermediate propositional and first-order logics are presented and investigated with respect to satisfaction of the separation and subformula properties. The technique employed is, for the most part, semantic, based on general versions of the Lindenbaum and Lindenbaum–Henkin constructions. Careful attention is paid to which properties of theories result in the presence of which rules of inference, and to restrictions on the sets of formulas to which the rules may be employed, restrictions (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  19.  45
    A dilemma for subjective bayesians — and how to resolve it.Peter Milne - 1991 - Philosophical Studies 62 (3):307 - 314.
  20.  90
    A Bayesian Defence of Popperian Science?Peter Milne - 1995 - Analysis 55 (3):213 - 215.
  21. The simplest Lewis-style triviality proof yet?Peter Milne - 2003 - Analysis 63 (4):300–303.
  22.  91
    Belief, Degrees of Belief, and Assertion.Peter Milne - 2012 - Dialectica 66 (3):331-349.
    Starting from John MacFarlane's recent survey of answers to the question ‘What is assertion?’, I defend an account of assertion that draws on elements of MacFarlane's and Robert Brandom's commitment accounts, Timothy Williamson's knowledge norm account, and my own previous work on the normative status of logic. I defend the knowledge norm from recent attacks. Indicative conditionals, however, pose a problem when read along the lines of Ernest Adams' account, an account supported by much work in the psychology of reasoning. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  23.  97
    Indicative conditionals, conditional probabilities, and the “defective truth-table”: A request for more experiments.Peter Milne - 2012 - Thinking and Reasoning 18 (2):196-224.
    While there is now considerable experimental evidence that, on the one hand, participants assign to the indicative conditional as probability the conditional probability of consequent given antecedent and, on the other, they assign to the indicative conditional the “defective truth-table” in which a conditional with false antecedent is deemed neither true nor false, these findings do not in themselves establish which multi-premise inferences involving conditionals participants endorse. A natural extension of the truth-table semantics pronounces as valid numerous inference patterns that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  24.  34
    Information, confirmation, and conditionals.Peter Milne - 2014 - Journal of Applied Logic 12 (3):252-262.
  25. Tarski, truth and model theory.Peter Milne - 1999 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 99 (2):141–167.
    As Wilfrid Hodges has observed, there is no mention of the notion truth-in-a-model in Tarski's article 'The Concept of Truth in Formalized Languages'; nor does truth make many appearances in his papers on model theory from the early 1950s. In later papers from the same decade, however, this reticence is cast aside. Why should Tarski, who defined truth for formalized languages and pretty much founded model theory, have been so reluctant to speak of truth in a model? What might explain (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  26.  70
    Can there be a realist single-case interpretation of probability?Peter Milne - 1986 - Erkenntnis 25 (2):129 - 132.
  27.  52
    Is there a logic of confirmation transfer?Peter Milne - 2000 - Erkenntnis 53 (3):309-335.
    This article begins by exploring a lost topic in the philosophy of science:the properties of the relations evidence confirming h confirmsh'' and, more generally, evidence confirming each ofh1, h2, ..., hm confirms at least one of h1, h2,ldots;, hn''.The Bayesian understanding of confirmation as positive evidential relevanceis employed throughout. The resulting formal system is, to say the least, oddlybehaved. Some aspects of this odd behaviour the system has in common withsome of the non-classical logics developed in the twentieth century. Oneaspect (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  28. Omniscient beings are dialetheists.Peter Milne - 2007 - Analysis 67 (3):250–251.
  29.  51
    Existence, freedom, identity, and the logic of abstractionist realism.Peter Milne - 2007 - Mind 116 (461):23-53.
    From the point of view of proof-theoretic semantics, we examine the logical background invoked by Neil Tennant's abstractionist realist account of mathematical existence. To prepare the way, we must first look closely at the rule of existential elimination familiar from classical and intuitionist logics and at rules governing identity. We then examine how well free logics meet the harmony and uniqueness constraints familiar from the proof-theoretic semantics project. Tennant assigns a special role to atomic formulas containing singular terms. This, we (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  30.  77
    A note on scale invariance.Peter Milne - 1983 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 34 (1):49-55.
  31.  72
    Scotching the dutch book argument.Peter Milne - 1990 - Erkenntnis 32 (1):105--26.
    Consistent application of coherece arguments shows that fair betting quotients are subject to constraints that are too stringent to allow their identification with either degrees of belief or probabilities. The pivotal role of fair betting quotients in the Dutch Book Argument, which is said to demonstrate that a rational agent's degrees of belief are probabilities, is thus undermined from both sides.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  32.  94
    The Physicalization of Mathematics.Peter Milne - 1994 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 45 (1):305-340.
  33.  56
    Hartry field on measurement and intrinsic explanation.Peter Milne - 1986 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 37 (3):340-346.
  34. Tarski on truth and its definition.Peter Milne - 1997 - In Timothy Childers, Petr Kolft & Vladimir Svoboda (eds.), Logica '96: Proceedings of the 10th International Symposium. Filosofia. pp. 198-210.
    Of his numerous investigations ... Tarski was most proud of two: his work on truth and his design of an algorithm in 1930 to decide the truth or falsity of any sentence of the elementary theory of the high school Euclidean geometry. [...] His mathematical treatment of the semantics of languages and the concept of truth has had revolutionary consequences for mathematics, linguistics, and philosophy, and Tarski is widely thought of as the man who "defined truth". The seeming simplicity of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  35. A note on Popper, propensities, and the two-slit experiment.Peter Milne - 1985 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 36 (1):66-70.
  36.  82
    Algebras of intervals and a logic of conditional assertions.Peter Milne - 2004 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 33 (5):497-548.
    Intervals in boolean algebras enter into the study of conditional assertions (or events) in two ways: directly, either from intuitive arguments or from Goodman, Nguyen and Walker's representation theorem, as suitable mathematical entities to bear conditional probabilities, or indirectly, via a representation theorem for the family of algebras associated with de Finetti's three-valued logic of conditional assertions/events. Further representation theorems forge a connection with rough sets. The representation theorems and an equivalent of the boolean prime ideal theorem yield an algebraic (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  37.  53
    Modal metaphysics and comparatives.Peter Milne - 1992 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 70 (3):248 – 262.
  38.  22
    Betting on Fuzzy and Many–valued Propositions.Peter Milne - unknown
    From Introduction: In a 1968 article, ‘Probability Measures of Fuzzy Events’, Lotfi Zadeh pro-posed accounts of absolute and conditional probability for fuzzy sets (Zadeh, 1968).
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  39. Bayesianism V. scientific realism.Peter Milne - 2003 - Analysis 63 (4):281–288.
  40.  68
    Frege's context principle.Peter Milne - 1986 - Mind 95 (380):491-495.
  41.  75
    The foundations of probability and quantum mechanics.Peter Milne - 1993 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 22 (2):129 - 168.
    Taking as starting point two familiar interpretations of probability, we develop these in a perhaps unfamiliar way to arrive ultimately at an improbable claim concerning the proper axiomatization of probability theory: the domain of definition of a point-valued probability distribution is an orthomodular partially ordered set. Similar claims have been made in the light of quantum mechanics but here the motivation is intrinsically probabilistic. This being so the main task is to investigate what light, if any, this sheds on quantum (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  42.  3
    VII*—Tarski, Truth and Model Theory.Peter Milne - 1999 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 99 (1):141-168.
    Peter Milne; VII*—Tarski, Truth and Model Theory, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 99, Issue 1, 1 June 1999, Pages 141–168, https://doi.org/10.11.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43.  75
    Frege, informative identities, and logicism.Peter Milne - 1989 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 40 (2):155-166.
  44.  86
    Intuitionistic Relevant Logic and Perfect Validity.Peter Milne - 1994 - Analysis 54 (3):140 - 142.
  45.  57
    Verification, falsification, and the logic of enquiry.Peter Milne - 1991 - Erkenntnis 34 (1):23 - 54.
    Our starting point is Michael Luntley's falsificationist semantics for the logical connectives and quantifiers: the details of his account are criticised but we provide an alternative falsificationist semantics that yields intuitionist logic, as Luntley surmises such a semantics ought. Next an account of the logical connectives and quantifiers that combines verificationist and falsificationist perspectives is proposed and evaluated. While the logic is again intuitionist there is, somewhat surprisingly, an unavoidable asymmetry between the verification and falsification conditions for negation, the conditional, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  46.  3
    Rewriting Lyotard: Figuration, Presentation, Resistance.Peter W. Milne - 2013 - Duke University Press.
    The visual arts operated as a touchstone for French philosopher Jean-François Lyotard, influencing his thinking on everything from epistemology to politics. Building on the recent publication of a bilingual, six-volume edition of his writings on contemporary art and artists, this special issue of_ Cultural Politics_ provides a focus on Lyotard’s aesthetics. The issue includes a review of Lyotard’s writings on art, a discussion of his early figural aesthetics, and an essay on Lyotard’s little-known work, _Pacific Wall_, as well as two (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. Sensibility and the Law: On Rancière's Reading of Lyotard.Peter Milne - 2011 - Symposium: Canadian Journal of Continental Philosophy/Revue canadienne de philosophie continentale 15 (2):95-119.
    This paper responds to Rancière’s reading of Lyotard’s analysis of the sublime by attempting to articulate what Lyotard would call a “differend” between the two. Sketching out Rancière’s criticisms, I show that Lyotard’s analysis of the Kantian sublime is more defensible than Rancière claims. I then provide an alternative reading, one that frees Lyotard’s sublime from Rancière’s central accusation that it signals nothing more than the mind’s perpetual enslavement to the law of the Other. Reading the sublime through the figure (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  93
    Probability as a Measure of Information Added.Peter Milne - 2012 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 21 (2):163-188.
    Some propositions add more information to bodies of propositions than do others. We start with intuitive considerations on qualitative comparisons of information added . Central to these are considerations bearing on conjunctions and on negations. We find that we can discern two distinct, incompatible, notions of information added. From the comparative notions we pass to quantitative measurement of information added. In this we borrow heavily from the literature on quantitative representations of qualitative, comparative conditional probability. We look at two ways (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49.  82
    Benenson, F. C. [1984]: Probability, Objectivity and Evidence. Routledge and Kegan Paul. Hardback £19.95. Pp. xii+284.Peter Milne - 1986 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 37 (1):123-126.
  50.  23
    Annabel and the bookmaker: An everyday tale of bayesian folk.Peter Milne - 1991 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 69 (1):98 – 102.
1 — 50 / 979