Results for 'Nagarjuna'

472 found
Order:
  1.  6
    Hundert Strophen von der Lebensklugheit Nāgarjunas Prajñāśatka, Tibetisch und Deutsch. Nāgārjuna & Michael Hahn - 1990 - Bonn: Indica et Tibetica Verlag. Edited by Michael Hahn & Nāgārjuna.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  3
    Die Philosophie der Leere: Nāgārjunas Mūlamadhyamaka-Kārikās: Übersetzung des buddhistischen Basistextes mit kommentierenden Einführungen. Nāgārjuna, Bernhard Weber-Brosamer & Dieter Michael Back - 1997 - Wiesbaden: Harrassowitz Verlag. Edited by Bernhard Weber-Brosamer & Dieter Michael Back.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. The philosophy of Nāgārjuna, as contained in the Ratnāvalī.Nagarjuna - 1977 - Calcutta: Saraswat Library. Edited by Heramba Nath Chatterji.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. 34. dr. K. padmanabha.Nagarjuna Nagar - 2005 - In G. Kamalakar & M. Veerender (eds.), Buddhism: Art, Architecture, Literature & Philosophy. Sharada Pub. House. pp. 1--249.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. 50. prof. Nh samtani.Nagarjuna Nagar - 2005 - In G. Kamalakar & M. Veerender (eds.), Buddhism: Art, Architecture, Literature & Philosophy. Sharada Pub. House. pp. 2--249.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  31
    Spectroscopic investigations on PbO–As2O3glasses crystallized with TiO2.G. Nagarjuna, T. Satyanarayana, V. Ravi Kumar, N. Venkatramaiah, P. V. V. Satyanarayana & N. Veeraiah - 2009 - Philosophical Magazine 89 (26):2255-2270.
  7.  38
    Refined concept maps for science education: A feasibility study.Meena Kharatmal & G. Nagarjuna - 2009 - Proceedings of Conference epiSTEME 3:76-80.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  8. Nāgārjuna's Critique of Language.Chien-Hsing Ho - 2010 - Asian Philosophy 20 (2):159-174.
    This essay attempts to provide a systematic reconstruction of Nāgārjuna's philosophical thought by understanding it as a critique of the attachment to linguistic expressions and their referents. We first present an outline of Nāgārjuna's philosophy, centering on such notions as 'dependent origination', 'emptiness' and 'self-nature'. Then we discuss Nāgārjuna's dismissal of a metaphysical use of language, particularly his contention that language can function well without assuming the reality of its referents. We also consider his statement that he has no assertion (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  9. Nāgārjuna and Vasubandhu on the principle of sufficient reason.Allison Aitken - 2024 - Asian Journal of Philosophy 3 (1):1-28.
    Canonical defenders of the principle of sufficient reason (PSR), such as Leibniz and Spinoza, are metaphysical foundationalists of one stripe or another. This is curious since the PSR—which says that everything has a ground, cause, or explanation—in effect, denies fundamental entities. In this paper, I explore the apparent inconsistency between metaphysical foundationalism and approaches to metaphysical system building that are driven by a commitment to the PSR. I do so by analyzing how Indian Buddhist philosophers arrive at foundationalist and anti-foundationalist (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  57
    Nāgārjuna’s Pañcakoṭi, Agrippa’s Trilemma, and the Uses of Skepticism.Ethan A. Mills - 2016 - Comparative Philosophy 7 (2):44-66.
    While the contemporary problem of the criterion raises similar epistemological issues as Agrippa’s Trilemma in ancient Pyrrhonian skepticism, the consideration of such epistemological questions has served two different purposes. On one hand, there is the purely practical purpose of Pyrrhonism, in which such questions are a means to reach suspension of judgment, and on the other hand, there is the theoretical purpose of contemporary epistemologists, in which these issues raise theoretical problems that drive the search for theoretical resolution. In classical (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  11.  8
    Nagarjuna's Philosophy: As Presented in the Maha-Prajnaparamita-Sastra.K. Venkata Ramanan - 2016 - Motilal Banarsidass.
    This work is an exposition of the philosophic conceptions basic to Mahayana Buddhism as found in the Maha-prajnaparamita-sastra a commentary on the Prajnaparamita-sutras and traditionally attributed to Nagarjuna. The sastra the earliest and most extensive work in this field is lost in its Sanskrit original and preserved only in a Chinese translation. Meaning of Sanskrit and Chinese terms are expounded concepts are made clear and supplementary materials are supplied in the notes. The study is prefixed with a short historical (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  12.  81
    Nāgārjuna.Jan Christoph Westerhoff - 2010 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    There is unanimous agreement that Nāgārjuna (ca 150–250 AD) is the most important Buddhist philosopher after the historical Buddha himself and one of the most original and influential thinkers in the history of Indian philosophy. His philosophy of the “middle way” (madhyamaka) based around the central notion of “emptiness” (śūnyatā) influenced the Indian philosophical debate for a thousand years after his death; with the spread of Buddhism to Tibet, China, Japan and other Asian countries the writings of Nāgārjuna became an (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  13.  37
    Nāgārjuna’s Negation.Chris Rahlwes - 2022 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 50 (2):307-344.
    The logical analysis of Nāgārjuna’s catuṣkoṭi has remained a heated topic for logicians in Western academia for nearly a century. At the heart of the catuṣkoṭi, the four corners’ formalization typically appears as: A, Not A, Both, and Neither. The pulse of the controversy is the repetition of negations in the catuṣkoṭi. Westerhoff argues that Nāgārjuna in the Mūlamadhyamakakārikā uses two different negations: paryudāsa and prasajya-pratiṣedha. This paper builds off Westerhoff’s account and presents some subtleties of Nāgārjuna’s use of these (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  14. Nagarjuna and the limits of thought.Jay L. Garfield & Graham Priest - 2003 - Philosophy East and West 53 (1):1-21.
    : Nagarjuna seems willing to embrace contradictions while at the same time making use of classic reductio arguments. He asserts that he rejects all philosophical views including his own-that he asserts nothing-and appears to mean it. It is argued here that he, like many philosophers in the West and, indeed, like many of his Buddhist colleagues, discovers and explores true contradictions arising at the limits of thought. For those who share a dialetheist's comfort with the possibility of true contradictions (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  15.  93
    Nāgārjuna's fundamental doctrine of pratītyasamutpāda.Ewing Chinn - 2001 - Philosophy East and West 51 (1):54-72.
    Nāgārjuna contends that the doctrine of Pratītyasamutpāda (dependent origination), properly understood, constitutes the philosophical basis for the rejection and avoidance of all metaphysical theories and concepts (including causation). The companion doctrine of "śūnyatā" constitutes the denial of metaphysical realism (or "essentialism") but does not imply an anti-realist, conventionalist view of reality (as Jay Garfield maintains). "Pratītyasamutpāda," the true doctrine or, literally, "the exact or real nature of the case," is really two-sided: it is (1) a "causal" principle explaining the origin (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  16.  7
    Nagarjuna in China. A Translation of the Middle Treatise. Brian Bocking.T. H. Barrett - 1996 - Buddhist Studies Review 13 (2):177-179.
    Nagarjuna in China. A Translation of the Middle Treatise. Brian Bocking. The Edwin Mellor Press, Lewiston/Queenston/Lampeter 1994. iv, 499 pp. £59.95, US$119.95.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  12
    Nāgārjuna, Madhyamaka, and truth.Chris Rahlwes - 2023 - Asian Journal of Philosophy 2 (2):1-24.
    In reading Nāgārjuna’s Mūlamadhyamakakārikā, one is struck by Nāgārjuna’s separation of conventional truth and ultimate truth. At the most basic level, these two truths deal with emptiness and the appearance of fundamental existence, but the meaning of “conventional” lends itself to two key senses: concealing and socially agreed-upon norms and practices. The tension between these two senses and how they relate to truth leads Nāgārjuna’s Tibetan commentators in different directions in their exegesis on conventional truth. Based on the debate between (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. Nāgārjuna’s Arguments on Motion Revisited.Jan Westerhoff - 2008 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 36 (4):455-479.
    This paper discusses a somewhat neglected reading of the second chapter of Nāgārjuna’s Mūlamadhyamakakārikā, arguing that the main focus of a crucial part is a particular theory of properties and their relation to individuals they instantiate, rather than the refutation of specific assumptions about the nature of space and time. Some of Nāgārjuna’s key arguments about motion should be understood as argument templates in which notions other than mover, motion, and so forth could be substituted. The remainder of the discussion (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  19. Nāgārjuna’s Scepticism about Philosophy.Ethan A. Mills - 2020 - In Oren Hanner (ed.), Buddhism and Scepticism: Historical, Philosophical, and Comparative Perspectives. Freiburg/Bochum: ProjektVerlag. pp. 55-81.
  20. Nāgārjuna and Madhyāmaka Ethics (Ethics-1, M32).Shyam Ranganathan - 2016 - In A. Raghuramaraju (ed.), Philosophy, E-PG Pathshala. Delhi: India, Department of Higher Education (NMEICT).
    Nāgārjuna’s “middle path” charts a course between two extremes: Nihilism, and Absolutism, not unlike earlier Buddhism. However, as early Buddhists countinanced constituents of reality as characterizable by essences while macroscopic objects lack such essences, Nāgārjuna argues that all things lack what he calls svabhāva – “own being” – the Sanskrit term for essence. Since everything lacks an essence, it is Empty (śūnya). To lack an essence is to lack autonomy. The corollary of this is that all things are interrelated. The (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. Nagarjuna's theory of causality: Implications sacred and profane.Jay L. Garfield - 2001 - Philosophy East and West 51 (4):507-524.
    Nāgārjuna argues for the fundamental importance of causality, and dependence more generally, to our understanding of reality and of human life: his account of these matters is generally correct. First, his account of interdependence shows how we can clearly understand the nature of scientific explanation, the relationship between distinct levels of theoretical analysis in the sciences (with particular attention to cognitive science), and how we can sidestep difficulties in understanding the relations between apparently competing ontologies induced by levels of description (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  22.  19
    Nāgārjuna and the Philosophy of Language.Jan Westerhoff - 2019 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 47 (4):779-793.
    The purpose of this paper is to examine some of the key points of Nāgārjuna’s discussion of problems relating to the philosophy of language. We will focus on two works from Nāgārjuna’s yukti-corpus that address these matters most explicitly, the Vigrahavyāvartanī and the Vaidalyaprakaraṇa. The discussion will concentrate on four topics: Nāgārjuna’s views on semantics, the problem of empty names, the relation between language and momentariness, and the implications of Madhyamaka views on parts and wholes for the existence of language.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  23.  58
    Nāgārjuna and the Philosophy of Language.Jan Westerhoff - 2019 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 47 (4):779-793.
    The purpose of this paper is to examine some of the key points of Nāgārjuna’s discussion of problems relating to the philosophy of language. We will focus on two works from Nāgārjuna’s yukti-corpus that address these matters most explicitly, the Vigrahavyāvartanī and the Vaidalyaprakaraṇa. The discussion will concentrate on four topics: Nāgārjuna’s views on semantics, the problem of empty names, the relation between language and momentariness, and the implications of Madhyamaka views on parts and wholes for the existence of language.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  24.  98
    The Dispeller of Disputes: Nāgārjuna's Vigrahavyāvartanī.Jan Westerhoff - 2010 - Oup Usa.
    Nagarjuna's Vigrahavyavartani is one of the most important Madhyamaka Buddhist philosophical texts. Jan Westerhoff offers a new translation, reflecting the best current philological research and all available editions, and adds his own philosophical commentary on the text. His nuanced, philosophically sophisticated commentary explains Nagarjuna's arguments in a way that is both grounded in historical and textual scholarship and connected explicitly to contemporary philosophical concerns.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  25.  51
    Nāgārjuna and the concept of time.A. K. Jayesh - 2021 - Asian Philosophy 31 (2):121-142.
    The paper focuses on Nāgārjuna, the founder of the middle way school of Mahāyāna Buddhism. It argues that while Nāgārjuna’s rejection of the notion of ontological independence is justified and corr...
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  26. Nāgārjuna and the doctrine of "skillful means".John Schroeder - 2000 - Philosophy East and West 50 (4):559-583.
    The role of "skillful means" is examined in relation to the important Mahāyāna philosopher Nāgārjuna, and it is argued that the doctrine of "emptiness" is best understood as a critical reflection on the nature of Buddhist praxis. Whereas traditional Western scholarship sees Nāgārjuna as struggling with certain metaphysical problems, a "skillful means" reading situates his philosophy within a debate about the nature and efficacy of Buddhist practice. Thus, a "skillful means" reading of Nāgārjuna does not ask what it means for (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  27.  31
    Nagarjuna's fundamental principle of.Ewing Chinn - 2001 - Philosophy East and West 51 (1):54-72.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Nāgārjuna's Fundamental Doctrine of PratītyasamutpādaEwing ChinnIt seems fitting that the very last verse of Nāgārjuna's challenging work, Mūlamadhyamakakārikā (Fundamental Verses of the Middle Way), would present the reader with what seems to be a riddle: "I prostrate to Gautama, who through compassion, taught the true doctrine, which leads to the relinquishing of all views" (27 :30). This should be read with an earlier verse (13 : 8): "The victorious (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. Nagarjuna's Madhyamaka.Jan Westerhoff - 2010 - Oxford University Press USA.
    The Indian philosopher Acharya Nagarjuna was the founder of the Madhyamaka school of Mahayana Buddhism and arguably the most influential Buddhist thinker after Buddha himself. Indeed, in the Tibetan and East Asian traditions, Nagarjuna is often referred to as the 'second Buddha.' His primary contribution to Buddhist thought lies is in the further development of the concept of sunyata or 'emptiness.' For Nagarjuna, all phenomena are without any svabhaba, literally 'own-nature' or 'self-nature', and thus without any underlying (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  29.  8
    Nāgārjuna's Affective Account of Misknowing.Roshni Patel - 2019 - Journal of Buddhist Philosophy 5 (1):44-64.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Nāgārjuna's Affective Account of MisknowingRoshni PatelIt is maintained that all beings and (their) qualitiesAre the fuel for the fire of awareness.Having been incinerated by brilliantTrue analysis, they are (all) pacified.—Ratnāvalī (RV)1.971In Nāgārjuna's formulation, ignorance about the nature of existents is scorching and thereby needs the alleviation that true analysis offers. This article explores what ignorance feels like from the subjective side of a knower in the Madhyamaka Buddhist tradition (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  32
    Nagarjuna's Fundamental Principle of Pratityasamutpada.Ewing Chinn - 2001 - Philosophy East and West 51 (1):54-72.
    Nāgārjuna contends that the doctrine of Pratītyasamutpāda , properly understood, constitutes the philosophical basis for the rejection and avoidance of all metaphysical theories and concepts . The companion doctrine of "śūnyatā" constitutes the denial of metaphysical realism but does not imply an anti-realist, conventionalist view of reality . "Pratītyasamutpāda," the true doctrine or, literally, "the exact or real nature of the case," is really two-sided: it is a "causal" principle explaining the origin of all that exists, and a semantic principle (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  31.  59
    Nāgārjuna's “Middle Way”: A non-eliminative understanding of selflessness.Dan Arnold - 2010 - Revue Internationale de Philosophie 253 (3):367-395.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  32.  8
    Nāgārjuna, le milieu et la vacuité.Alain Petit - 2022 - Les Etudes Philosophiques 142 (3):41-52.
    On a tenté, à partir des Stances du milieu par excellence, de ressaisir le sens de la vacuité selon Nāgārjuna : cela supposait que l’on suspendît les croyances fondant l’attachement de l’ego à un « soi-même » tout autant qu’aux « choses ». Par là, on entrevoyait l’idée d’un milieu absolu, par lequel les phénomènes, vides de « nature propre », seraient interconnectés sans être assujettis aux formes conventionnelles de l’espace et du temps.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  2
    Nagarjuna's Sutrasamuccaya: A Critical edition of the mDo kun las btus pa. Bhikkhu Pasadika.D. Seyfort Ruegg - 2000 - Buddhist Studies Review 17 (2):222-224.
    Nagarjuna's Sutrasamuccaya: A Critical edition of the mDo kun las btus pa. Bhikkhu Pasadika. Akademisk Forlag i Kommission, Copenhagen 1989. xix, 252 pp. ISBN 87-500-2889-8.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  21
    Nāgārjuna.Akira Saito - 2008 - Proceedings of the Xxii World Congress of Philosophy 6:229-235.
    Was Nāgārjuna a thinker of philosophy or religion? This must be a question of the kind to which the answer depends heavily on the definition of “philosophy” and “religion”. Therefore, we may prefer to rephrase this question as: “Can Nāgārjuna legitimately be called a thinker of philosophy or religion?” Although it has been and may still be defined by its method or the objects of “philosophical thinking”, philosophy is, in most cases, expected to have the following characteristics: (1) Philosophy is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  9
    Nāgārjuna.Akira Saito - 2008 - Proceedings of the Xxii World Congress of Philosophy 6:229-235.
    Was Nāgārjuna a thinker of philosophy or religion? This must be a question of the kind to which the answer depends heavily on the definition of “philosophy” and “religion”. Therefore, we may prefer to rephrase this question as: “Can Nāgārjuna legitimately be called a thinker of philosophy or religion?” Although it has been and may still be defined by its method or the objects of “philosophical thinking”, philosophy is, in most cases, expected to have the following characteristics: (1) Philosophy is (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  19
    Nagarjuna: The Philosophy of the Middle Way.Frank E. Reynolds, John Holt, John Strong, Heinz Bechert, Richard Gombrich, Garma C. C. Chang, Yang Hsuanchih, Yi-T'ung Wang & David J. Kalupahana - 1986 - Buddhist-Christian Studies 6:163.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  37. Did nāgārjuna really refute all philosophical views?Richard H. Robinson - 1972 - Philosophy East and West 22 (3):325-331.
  38.  48
    Nagarjuna and the Naiyayikas.Johannes Bronkhorst - 1985 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 13:107.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  39. On Nāgārjuna's Ontological and Semantic Paradox.Koji Tanaka - 2016 - Philosophy East and West 66 (4):1292-1306.
    In one of his key texts, the Mūlamadhyamakakārikā, Nāgārjuna famously sets out to refute the ontology of essence.1 He presents numerous arguments to show that things don’t exist essentially—that is, that things are empty of essence or inherent existence. The doctrine of emptiness has been variously understood by traditional and contemporary commentators. Most radical is the recent interpretation presented by Garfield and Priest. They have rationally reconstructed Nāgārjuna’s doctrine of emptiness as an endorsement of the contradictory nature of reality. According (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. Nägarjuna's Appeal.Richard P. Hayes - 1994 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 22 (4):311.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  41.  12
    Nagarjuna and the Doctrine of "Skillful Means".John Schroeder - 2000 - Philosophy East and West 50 (4):559-583.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Nāgārjuna and the Doctrine of "Skillful Means"John SchroederAlthough a number of Buddhist scholars have examined the doctrine of "skill-in-means" (upāya-kauśalya) in Mahāyāna Buddhist literature, it is surprising that no one has yet developed this important concept in relation to Nāgārjuna. Given that upāya is a central doctrine in the early Mahāyāna texts, and given that Nāgārjuna is a central philosopher of this tradition, it is unfortunate that scholars pay (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  78
    The Deceptive Simplicity of Nāgārjuna's Arguments Against Motion: Another Look at Mūlamadhyamakakārikā Chapter 2.Dan Arnold - 2012 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 40 (5):553-591.
    This article – which includes a complete translation of Mūlamadhyamakakārikā chapter 2 together with Candrakīrti’s commentary thereon – argues that notwithstanding the many different and often arcane interpretations that have been offered of Nāgārjuna’s arguments against motion, there is really just one straightforward kind of argument on offer in this vexed chapter. It is further argued that this basic argument can be understood as a philosophically interesting one if it is kept in mind that the argument essentially has to do (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  43. Nagarjuna: The Philosophy of the Middle Way.David J. Kalupahana - 1988 - Religious Studies 24 (4):529-533.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  44. Nāgārjuna’s Catuṣkoṭi.Jan Westerhoff - 2006 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 34 (4):367-395.
    The catuṣkoṭi or tetralemma is an argumentative figure familiar to any reader of Buddhist philosophical literature. Roughly speaking it consists of the enumeration of four alternatives: that some propositions holds, that it fails to hold, that it both holds and fails to hold, that it neither holds nor fails to hold. The tetralemma also constitutes one of the more puzzling features of Buddhist philosophy as the use to which it is put in arguments is not immediately obvious and certainly not (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  45.  93
    Nāgārjuna as anti-realist.Mark Siderits - 1988 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 16 (4):311-325.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  46.  4
    Nagarjuna's "Seventy Stanzas". A Buddhist Psychology of Emptiness. David Ross Komito.Martin Boord - 1990 - Buddhist Studies Review 7 (1-2):121-122.
    Nagarjuna's "Seventy Stanzas". A Buddhist Psychology of Emptiness. David Ross Komito. Snow Lion Publications, Ithaca, NY 1987. 226pp. £9.95.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  27
    Nāgārjuna, A Translation of his Mūlamadhyamakakārikā.Dale Riepe - 1971 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 32 (1):124.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  48.  29
    Nāgārjuna and Schelling: Outlines of a dialogue on self, world, and viewpoints.Leonardo Alves Vieira - 2016 - Kriterion: Journal of Philosophy 57 (133):283-322.
    ABSTRACT The paper intends to build a dialogue between Nāgārjuna and Schelling on Self, world, and standpoints, taking as main references Nāgārjuna's The Fundamental Verses of the Middle Way and Schelling's Philosophical Letters on Dogmatism and Criticism. Whereas Nāgārjuna criticizes the substantialization of beings by resorting to the discourse of the dependent co-origination in order to overcome suffering, Schelling, on his turn, refutes the fanaticism based on dogmatism's tenets in favor of the criticism interpreted according to its spirit, and not (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49. Nāgārjuna’s Tetralemma in Yamauchi Tokuryū’s Philosophy.Romaric Jannel - 2022 - The Eastern Buddhist. Third Series 2.
  50.  17
    Nagarjuna's Philosophy as Presented in the Maha-Prajnaparamita-Sastra.Lewis Lancaster & K. Venkata Ramanan - 1968 - Philosophy East and West 18 (1/2):97.
1 — 50 / 472