Results for 'Tienson, J'

961 found
Order:
  1.  80
    Review. Connectionism and the philosophy of psychology. T Horgan, J Tienson.J. W. Garson - 1999 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 50 (2):319-323.
  2.  9
    Connectionism and the Philosophy of Psychology, by T. Horgan and J. Tienson.Robert J. Stainton - unknown
  3. Terence Horgan and John Tienson, Connectionism and the Philosophy of Psychology. [REVIEW]Robert J. Stainton - 1996 - Philosophy in Review 16 (6):413-414.
  4. Beginning a theoretician-practitioner dialogue about connectionism.Dianne D. Horgan & Douglas J. Hacker - 1999 - Acta Analytica 144:261-273.
  5. Horgan and Tienson on ceteris paribus laws.Marcello Guarini - 2000 - Philosophy of Science 67 (2):301-315.
    Terence Horgan and John Tienson claim that folk psychological laws are different in kind from basic physical laws in at least two ways: first, physical laws do not possess the kind of ceteris paribus qualifications possessed by folk psychological laws, which means the two types of laws have different logical forms; and second, applied physical laws are best thought of as being about an idealized world and folk psychological laws about the actual world. I argue that Horgan and Tienson have (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  6. In defense of new wave materialism: A response to Horgan and Tienson.Brian P. McLaughlin - 2001 - In Carl Gillett & Barry M. Loewer (eds.), Physicalism and its Discontents. Cambridge University Press.
  7. Horgan and Tienson on ceteris paribus laws.G. Marcello - 2000 - Philosophy of Science 67 (2):301-315.
  8.  16
    Reference and Essence.John Tienson - 1981 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 49 (4):1417-1419.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   81 citations  
  9.  17
    About competence.John L. Tienson - 1990 - Philosophical Papers 19 (1):19-36.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  10.  79
    Brains are not conscious.John L. Tienson - 1987 - Philosophical Papers 16 (November):187-93.
  11.  24
    Innate Ideas.John Tienson - 1978 - Noûs 12 (3):337-343.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  12.  2
    Oblique Contexts.John Tienson - 1986 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 51 (3):821-822.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  43
    An introduction to connectionism.John L. Tienson - 1988 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 26 (S1):1-16.
  14.  52
    On analysing knowledge.John Tienson - 1974 - Philosophical Studies 25 (4):289 - 293.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  15. Introduction to connectionism.John L. Tienson - 1987 - Southern Journal of Philosophy (Suppl.) 1:1-16.
  16. Special sciences (or: The disunity of science as a working hypothesis).J. A. Fodor - 1974 - Synthese 28 (2):97-115.
  17. Phenomenology, Intentionality, and the Unity of the Mind.George Graham, Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 2009 - In Brian McLaughlin, Ansgar Beckermann & Sven Walter (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind. Oxford University Press. pp. 512--537.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  18.  72
    Hume on universals and general terms.John Tienson - 1984 - Noûs 18 (2):311-330.
  19.  8
    Questions for blobjectivism.John Tienson - 2002 - Facta Philosophica 2 (2):301-10.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  20.  22
    Logical Pluralism.J. C. Beall & Greg Restall - 2005 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press. Edited by Greg Restall.
    Consequence is at the heart of logic, and an account of consequence offers a vital tool in the evaluation of arguments. This text presents what the authors term as 'logical pluralism' arguing that the notion of logical consequence doesn't pin down one deductive consequence relation; it allows for many of them.
  21. The Intentionality of Phenomenology and the Phenomenology of Intentionality.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 2002 - In David J. Chalmers (ed.), Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings. Oup Usa. pp. 520--533.
  22.  21
    A Conception of Metaphysics.John L. Tienson - 1989 - American Philosophical Quarterly 26 (1):63 - 71.
  23.  55
    Kasimir Twardowski on the content of presentations.John Tienson - 2013 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 12 (3):485-499.
    In On the Content and Object of Presentations, Kasimir Twardowski presents an interesting line of thought concerning the content of a presentation and its relation to the object of that presentation. This way of thinking about content is valuable for understanding phenomenal intentionality, and it should also be important for the project of “naturalizing” the mental (or at least for discovering the neural correlates of the phenomenal). According to this view, content is that by virtue of which a presentation of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24.  91
    Connectionism and the Philosophy of Psychology.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1996 - MIT Press.
    In Connectionism and the Philosophy of Psychology, Horgan and Tienson articulate and defend a new view of cognition.
  25.  23
    An argument concerning quantification and propositional attitudes.John L. Tienson - 1987 - Philosophical Studies 51 (2):145 - 168.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  59
    An Observation on Common Names and Proper Names.John Tienson - 1986 - Analysis 46 (2):73 - 76.
    Common names, for Mill, have both connotation and denotation. Thus ‘horse’ connotes certain properties, and the name ‘horse’ denotes the things that have those properties. By contrast, proper names have no connotations; they do not denote in virtue of the possession of certain properties by their denotations, but so to speak, directly. Thus Socrates received his name by being dubbed ‘Socrates’; and he might just as well have been given any other name. This contrast is misleading. After all, we might (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  12
    An observation on common names and proper.John Tienson - 1986 - Analysis 46 (1):73-76.
    Common names, for Mill, have both connotation and denotation. Thus ‘horse’ connotes certain properties, and the name ‘horse’ denotes the things that have those properties. By contrast, proper names have no connotations; they do not denote in virtue of the possession of certain properties by their denotations, but so to speak, directly. Thus Socrates received his name by being dubbed ‘Socrates’; and he might just as well have been given any other name.This contrast is misleading. After all, we might have (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  73
    Can Things of Different Natural Kinds Be Exactly Alike?John Tienson - 1977 - Analysis 37 (4):190 - 197.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  29. Can things of different natural kinds be exactly alike?John Tienson - 1977 - Analysis 37 (4):190.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30.  33
    Entia successiva and ordinary things.John L. Tienson - 1985 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 23 (4):475-479.
  31.  8
    Entia Successiva and Ordinary Things.John L. Tienson - 2010 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 23 (4):475-479.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  15
    Hintikka's argument for the 'basic restriction'.John Tienson - 1975 - Philosophical Studies 28 (1):33 - 40.
  33.  53
    Hesperus and Phosphorus I.John Tienson - 1984 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 62:16.
  34.  63
    Higher-order causation.John Tienson - 2002 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 63 (1):89-101.
    We have a familiar idea of levels of description or levels of theory in science: microphysics, atomic physics, chemistry, biology, psychology, and the various social sciences. It is clear that philosophers - such as Terry Horgan - who want to be nonreductive materialists with regard to the mental must hold that this is not mere description; there must be genuine higher-level causes, and hence, genuine higher-level properties, in particular mental properties and causes. But there appears to be a deep problem (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35.  19
    Is this any way to be a realist?John L. Tienson - 1990 - Philosophical Psychology 3 (1):155-164.
    Andy Clark argues that the reality and causal efficacy of the folk psychological attitudes do not require in‐the‐head correlates of the that‐clauses by which they are attributed. The facts for which Fodor invokes a language of thought as empirical explanation—systemati‐city, for example—are, Clark argues, an a priori conceptual demand upon propositional attitude ascription, and hence not in need of empirical explanation. However, no such strategy can work. A priori demands imposed by our practices do not eliminate the need for empirical (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36.  83
    Resemblance and general terms.John L. Tienson - 1988 - Philosophical Studies 54 (1):87 - 108.
    Any successful account of general terms must explain our ability to apply terms correctly to new instances. Many philosophers have thought resemblance offers an ontologically sparse basis for such an account. However, Any natural and plausible account of general terms on the basis of resemblance requires quite a rich ontology, Including at least second order properties and relations. Given a sufficiently rich structure of resemblances, We can surely account for the application of many general terms. I argue, However, That our (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37.  59
    Synonyms and the objects of belief.John L. Tienson - 1982 - Philosophical Studies 42 (3):297 - 313.
  38.  33
    What Does a Deceived Cartesian Meditator Know?John Tienson - 2007 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 45 (S1):49-59.
  39.  19
    What the differences are: Reply to Hardcastle.John Tienson - 1997 - Philosophical Psychology 10 (3):385 – 389.
    Hardcastle argues that we make distinctions where there are no differences when we speak of (1) levels of description, (2) cognitive forces, and (3) soft laws in psychology. Concerning (1) and (2), the differences just are differences in description. The same state is referred to by three different descriptions, and talk of cognitive forces is appropriate and useful at the cognitive level of description. And concerning (3), if our view of cognition is correct, then the laws of psychology are importantly (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. Prolegomena to a philosophy of religion.J. L. Schellenberg - 2005 - Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.
    Providing an original and systematic treatment of foundational issues in philosophy of religion, J. L. Schellenberg's new book addresses the structure of..
  41. What Happens When Someone Acts?J. David Velleman - 1992 - Mind 101 (403):461-481.
    What happens when someone acts? A familiar answer goes like this. There is something that the agent wants, and there is an action that he believes conducive to its attainment. His desire for the end, and his belief in the action as a means, justify taking the action, and they jointly cause an intention to take it, which in turn causes the corresponding movements of the agent's body. I think that the standard story is flawed in several respects. The flaw (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   197 citations  
  42.  5
    Consciousness and Intentionality.George Graham, Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 2017 - In Susan Schneider & Max Velmans (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness. Chichester, UK: Wiley. pp. 519–535.
    Consciousness and intentionality help to define the mental qua mental. Consciousness and intentionality, insist some philosophers, although perhaps often co‐occurring, are mutually independent or separable. Consciousness and intentionality, insist others, are interdependent or inseparable. This chapter discusses an important aspect of inseparatism: the relation between phenomenal character and intentional content. The contemporary philosophers and theorists have developed inseparatist or nearly inseparatist theses in various ways. The chapter mentions some of this work, and the philosophers responsible for it. It discusses two (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. Performative Utterances.J. L. Austin - 1961 - In John Langshaw Austin (ed.), Philosophical Papers. Oxford, England: Clarendon Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   79 citations  
  44. Truth.J. L. Austin - 2005-01-01 - In José Medina & David Wood (eds.), Truth. Blackwell.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   127 citations  
  45. Family History.J. David Velleman - 2005 - Philosophical Papers 34 (3):357-378.
    Abstract I argue that meaning in life is importantly influenced by bioloical ties. More specifically, I maintain that knowing one's relatives and especially one's parents provides a kind of self-knowledge that is of irreplaceable value in the life-task of identity formation. These claims lead me to the conclusion that it is immoral to create children with the intention that they be alienated from their bioloical relatives?for example, by donor conception.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  46. Phenomenal intentionality and the brain in a vat.Terence E. Horgan, John L. Tienson & George Graham - 2004 - In Richard Schantz (ed.), The Externalist Challenge. De Gruyter.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  47. Making Punishment Safe: Adding an Anti-Luck Condition to Retributivism and Rights Forfeiture.J. Spencer Atkins - 2024 - Law, Ethics and Philosophy:1-18.
    Retributive theories of punishment argue that punishing a criminal for a crime she committed is sufficient reason for a justified and morally permissible punishment. But what about when the state gets lucky in its decision to punish? I argue that retributive theories of punishment are subject to “Gettier” style cases from epistemology. Such cases demonstrate that the state needs more than to just get lucky, and as these retributive theories of punishment stand, there is no anti-luck condition. I’ll argue that (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. Degree supervaluational logic.J. Robert G. Williams - 2011 - Review of Symbolic Logic 4 (1):130-149.
    Supervaluationism is often described as the most popular semantic treatment of indeterminacy. There’s little consensus, however, about how to fill out the bare-bones idea to include a characterization of logical consequence. The paper explores one methodology for choosing between the logics: pick a logic thatnorms beliefas classical consequence is standardly thought to do. The main focus of the paper considers a variant of standard supervaluational, on which we can characterizedegrees of determinacy. It applies the methodology above to focus ondegree logic. (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  49.  37
    Evolutionary religion.J. L. Schellenberg - 2013 - Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
    J.L. Schellenberg offers a path to a new kind of religious outlook. Reflection on our early stage in the evolutionary process leads to skepticism about religion, but also offers a new answer to the problem of faith and reason, and the possibility of a new, evolutionary form of religion.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  50. Internal-World Skepticism and the Self-Presentational Nature of Phenomenal Consciousness.Terence Horgan, John Tienson & Graham George - 2006 - In Kriegel Uriah & Kenneth Williford (eds.), Self-representational Approaches to Consciousness. Bradford.
1 — 50 / 961