Results for 'Nicholas F. Stang'

(not author) ( search as author name )
995 found
Order:
  1. Hermann Cohen and Kant's Concept of Experience.Nicholas F. Stang - 2018 - In Christian Damböck (ed.), Philosophie und Wissenschaft bei Hermann Cohen. Springer. pp. 13–40.
    In this essay I offer a partial rehabilitation of Cohen’s Kant interpretation. In particular, I will focus on the center of Cohen’s interpretation in KTE, reflected in the title itself: his interpretation of Kant’s concept of experience. “Kant hat einen neuen Begriff der Erfahrung entdeckt,”7 Cohen writes at the opening of the first edition of KTE (henceforth, KTE1), and while the exact nature of that new concept of experience is hard to pin down in the 1871 edition, he states it (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2. Kant's Schematism of the categories: An interpretation and defence.Nicholas F. Stang - 2022 - European Journal of Philosophy 31 (1):30-64.
    The aim of the Schematism chapter of the Critique of Pure Reason is to solve the problem posed by the “inhomogeneity” of intuitions and categories: the sensible properties of objects represented in intuition are of a different kind than the properties represented by categories. Kant's solution is to introduce what he calls “transcendental schemata,” which mediate the subsumption of objects under categories. I reconstruct Kant's solution in terms of two substantive premises, which I call Subsumption Sufficiency (i.e., that subsuming an (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. A Kantian Response to Bolzano’s Critique of Kant’s Analytic-Synthetic Distinction.Nicholas F. Stang - 2012 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 85 (1):33-61.
    One of Bolzano’s objections to Kant’s way of drawing the analytic-synthetic distinction is that it only applies to judgments within a narrow range of syntactic forms, namely, universal affirmative judgments. According to Bolzano, Kant cannot account for judgments of other syntactic forms that, intuitively, are analytic. A recent paper by Ian Proops also attributes to Kant the view that analytic judgments beyond a limited range of syntactic forms are impossible. I argue that, correctly understood, Kant’s conception of analyticity allows for (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  4. Kant and the concept of an object.Nicholas F. Stang - 2020 - European Journal of Philosophy 29 (2):299-322.
    European Journal of Philosophy, EarlyView.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  5. Kant on Complete Determination and Infinite Judgement.Nicholas F. Stang - 2012 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 20 (6):1117-1139.
    In the Transcendental Ideal Kant discusses the principle of complete determination: for every object and every predicate A, the object is either determinately A or not-A. He claims this principle is synthetic, but it appears to follow from the principle of excluded middle, which is analytic. He also makes a puzzling claim in support of its syntheticity: that it represents individual objects as deriving their possibility from the whole of possibility. This raises a puzzle about why Kant regarded it as (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  6. Kant's Argument that Existence is not a Determination.Nicholas F. Stang - 2015 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 91 (1):583-626.
    In this paper, I examine Kant's famous objection to the ontological argument: existence is not a determination. Previous commentators have not adequately explained what this claim means, how it undermines the ontological argument, or how Kant argues for it. I argue that the claim that existence is not a determination means that it is not possible for there to be non-existent objects; necessarily, there are only existent objects. I argue further that Kant's target is not merely ontological arguments as such (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  7. Artworks Are Not Valuable for Their Own Sake.Nicholas F. Stang - 2012 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 70 (3):271-280.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  8. Did Kant Conflate the Necessary and the A Priori?Nicholas F. Stang - 2011 - Noûs 45 (3):443-471.
    It is commonly accepted by Kant scholars that Kant held that all necessary truths are a priori, and all a priori knowledge is knowledge of necessary truths. Against the prevailing interpretation, I argue that Kant was agnostic as to whether necessity and a priority are co-extensive. I focus on three kinds of modality Kant implicitly distinguishes: formal possibility and necessity, empirical possibility and necessity, and noumenal possibility and necessity. Formal possibility is compatibility with the forms of experience; empirical possibility is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  9.  51
    The Non-Identity of Appearances and Things in Themselves.Nicholas F. Stang - 2013 - Noûs 48 (1):106-136.
    According to the ‘One Object’ reading of Kant's transcendental idealism, the distinction between the appearance and the thing in itself is not a distinction between two objects, but between two ways of considering one and the same object. On the ‘Metaphysical’ version of the One Object reading, it is a distinction between two kinds of properties possessed by one and the same object. Consequently, the Metaphysical One Object view holds that a given appearance, an empirical object, is numerically identical to (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  10.  63
    Kant's Modal Metaphysics: A reply to my critics.Nicholas F. Stang - 2018 - European Journal of Philosophy 26 (3):1159-1167.
  11.  99
    Appearances and Things in Themselves: Actuality and Identity.Nicholas F. Stang - 2016 - Kantian Review 21 (2):283-292.
    Lucy Allais’s anti-phenomenalist interpretation of transcendental idealism is incomplete in two ways. First of all, like some phenomenalists, she is committed to denying the coherence of claims of numerical identity of appearances and things in themselves. Secondly, she fails to explain adequately what grounds the actuality of appearances. This opens the door to a phenomenalist understanding of appearances. View HTML Send article to KindleTo send this article to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  12.  95
    IX—How Is Metaphysics Possible?Nicholas F. Stang - 2023 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 123 (3):231-252.
    In the Introduction to the Critique of Pure Reason Kant raises a famous question: how is metaphysics possible as a science? Kant posed this question for his predecessors in early modern philosophy. I raise this question anew for the resurgence of metaphysics within analytic philosophy. I begin by dividing the question of the possibility of metaphysics into separate questions about its semantic and epistemic possibility, and translate them into contemporary terms as: (1) Why do terms in metaphysical theories refer? (2) (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  63
    Replies to Critics.Nicholas F. Stang - 2018 - Kantian Review 23 (3):473-487.
  14. Self-Consciousness and Objectivity, by Sebastian Rödl.Nicholas F. Stang - 2021 - Mind 131 (524):1339-1347.
    In his recent book, Self-Consciousness and Objectivity: An Introduction to Absolute Idealism, Sebastian Rödl aims to transform our understanding, not only of th.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  69
    Erratum to: The Force and Content of Judgment: A Critical Notice of Self-Consciousness and Objectivity, by Sebastian Rödl.Nicholas F. Stang - 2023 - Mind 132 (525):325-325.
    Mind, https://doi.org/10.1093/mind/fzab001.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. The Poverty of Conceptual Truth: Kant's Analytic/synthetic Distinction and the Limits of Metaphysics, by R. Lanier Anderson: Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015, pp. xviii + 408, US$70. [REVIEW]Nicholas F. Stang - 2017 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 95 (2):394-397.
  17.  58
    Review: Greenberg, Robert, Real Existence, Ideal Necessity: Kant’s Compromise and the Modalities without the Compromise[REVIEW]Nicholas F. Stang - 2014 - Kantian Review 19 (3):475-489.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  31
    Review Essay: Greenberg on Kant, Existence, and De Re Necessity - Robert Greenberg, Real Existence, Ideal Necessity: Kant’s Compromise and the Modalities without the Compromise. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 2008. Pp. xviii + 211, $119.00, hbk. 978-3-11-021013-2. [REVIEW]Nicholas F. Stang - 2014 - Kantian Review 19 (3):475-489.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. .NicholasF.Stang F. Stang - 2016
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  36
    Nicholas F. Stang, Kant’s Modal Metaphysics Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016 Pp. 352 ISBN 9780198712626 $74.00. [REVIEW]Jessica Leech - 2017 - Kantian Review 22 (2):341-346.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  35
    Nicholas F. Stang: Kant’s Modal Metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press 2016, 360 Seiten. ISBN 978-0-19-871262-6. [REVIEW]Jannis Pissis - 2019 - Kant Studien 110 (4):676-681.
  22.  14
    Wittgenstein and Phenomenology: A Comparative Study of the Later Wittgenstein, Husserl, Heidegger, and Merleau-Ponty.Nicholas F. Gier - 1981 - State University of New York Press.
    In the first in-depth philosophical study of the subject, Nicholas Gier examines the published and unpublished writings of Ludwig Wittgenstein, to show the striking parallels between Wittgenstein and phenomenology. Between 1929 and 1933, the philosopher proposed programs that bore a detailed resemblance to dominant themes in the phenomenology of Husserl and some “life-world” phenomenologists. This sound, thoroughly readable study examines how and why he eventually moved away from it. Gier demonstrates, however, that Wittgenstein’s phenomenology continues as his “grammar” of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  23.  75
    The dancing ru: A confucian aesthetics of virtue.Nicholas F. Gier - 2001 - Philosophy East and West 51 (2):280-305.
    The most constructive response to the crisis in moral theory has been the revival of virtue ethics, which has the advantages of being personal, contextual, and, as will be argued, normative as well. It is also proposed that the best way to refound virtue ethics is to return to the Greek concept of technē tou biou, literally "craft of life." The ancients did not distinguish between craft and fine art, and the meaning of technē, even in its Latin form, ars, (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  24.  28
    The dancing.Nicholas F. Gier - 2001 - Philosophy East and West 51 (2):280-305.
    The most constructive response to the crisis in moral theory has been the revival of virtue ethics, which has the advantages of being personal, contextual, and, as will be argued, normative as well. It is also proposed that the best way to refound virtue ethics is to return to the Greek concept of technē tou biou, literally "craft of life." The ancients did not distinguish between craft and fine art, and the meaning of technē, even in its Latin form, ars, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  25.  66
    Wittgenstein and forms of life.Nicholas F. Gier - 1980 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 10 (3):241-258.
  26. Wittgenstein and Phenomenology.Nicholas F. Gier - 1982 - Critica 14 (42):109-111.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  27.  4
    Spiritual Titanism: Indian, Chinese, and Western Perspectives.Nicholas F. Gier - 2000 - SUNY Press.
    A comparative philosophical consideration of the extremes of humanism, or "Titanism," this book critiques trends in Eastern and Western philosophy and examines solutions to them.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  28.  68
    Confucius, Gandhi and the aesthetics of virtue.Nicholas F. Gier - 2001 - Asian Philosophy 11 (1):41 – 54.
    Both Confucius and Gandhi were fervent political reformers and this paper argues that their views of human nature and the self-society-world relationship are instructively similar. Gandhi never accepted Shankara's doctrine of.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  29.  9
    The Virtue of Nonviolence: From Gautama to Gandhi.Nicholas F. Gier - 2005 - State University of New York Press.
  30.  15
    The Virtue of Nonviolence: From Gautama to Gandhi.Nicholas F. Gier - 2003 - State University of New York Press.
  31.  27
    Hindu titanism.Nicholas F. Gier - 1995 - Philosophy East and West 45 (1):73-96.
  32.  29
    Wittgenstein's Phenomenology Revisited.Nicholas F. Gier - 1990 - Philosophy Today 34 (3):273-288.
  33.  16
    A response to Shyam ranganathan's review of.Nicholas F. Gier - 2007 - Philosophy East and West 57 (4).
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  8
    A Response to Shyam Ranganathan's Review of The Virtue of Non-Violence: From Gautama to Gandhi.Nicholas F. Gier - 2007 - Philosophy East and West 57 (4):561-563.
  35.  28
    Ahimsa, the Self, and Postmodernism: Jain, Vedantist, and Buddhist Perspectives.Nicholas F. Gier - 1995 - International Philosophical Quarterly 35 (1):71-86.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  65
    Dharma Morality As Virtue Ethics.Nicholas F. Gier - unknown
    consequentialism."[2] Whereas it is virtually impossible to do the hedonic calculus for ordinary pains and pleasures, there is no question about the long term good consequences of the virtues and good character, as compared to the long term pain that the vices bring. This means that attempts, such as Michael Slote's gallant.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37. David Rubinstein, Marx and Wittgenstein: Social Praxis and Social Explanation Reviewed by.Nicholas F. Gier - 1983 - Philosophy in Review 3 (4):201-203.
  38.  47
    Gandhi, Deep Religious Pluralism, and Multiculturalism.Nicholas F. Gier - 2014 - Philosophy East and West 64 (2):319-339.
    I’ve advanced from tolerance to equal respect for all religions.1I’ve broadened my Hinduism by loving other religions as my own.2[Gandhi’s] doctrine of the equality of religions . . . did not move towards a single global religion, but enjoins us all to become better expressions of our own faith, being enriched in the process by influences from other faiths.3At first glance the religious philosophy of Mohandas K. Gandhi appears to be a version of the perennial philosophy, the main proponent of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  8
    God, Reason, and the Evangelicals: The Case Against Evangelical Rationalism.Nicholas F. Gier - 1987
  40.  36
    Hebrew and buddhist selves: A constructive postmodern study.Nicholas F. Gier & Johnson Petta - 2007 - Asian Philosophy 17 (1):47 – 64.
    Our task will be to demonstrate that there are instructive parallels between Hebrew and Buddhist concepts of self. There are at least five main constituents (skandhas in Sanskrit) of the Hebrew self: (1) nepe as living being; (2) rah as indwelling spirit; (3) lb as heart-mind; (4) bāār as flesh; and (5) dām as blood. We will compare these with the five Buddhist skandhas: disposition (samskāra), consciousness (vijñāna), feeling (vedanā), perception (samjñā), and body (rpa). Generally, what we will discover is (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  33
    Intentionality and Prehension.Nicholas F. Gier - 1976 - Process Studies 6 (3):197-213.
  42.  59
    Whitehead, confucius, and the aesthetics of virtue.Nicholas F. Gier - 2004 - Asian Philosophy 14 (2):171 – 190.
    The most constructive response to the crisis in moral theory has been the revival of virtue ethics, an ethics that has the advantages of being personal, contextual, and, as this paper will argue, normative as well. The first section offers a general comparative analysis of Confucian and Whiteheadian philosophies, showing their common process orientation and their views of a somatic self united in reason and passion. The second section contrasts rational with aesthetic order, demonstrating a parallel with analytic and synthetic (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  43.  49
    Wittgenstein, intentionality, and behaviorism.Nicholas F. Gier - 1982 - Metaphilosophy 13 (1):46–64.
  44.  14
    Marathon Fighters and Men of Maple: Ancient Acharnai by Danielle L. Kellogg.Nicholas F. Jones - 2014 - Classical World: A Quarterly Journal on Antiquity 108 (1):144-145.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  7
    Politics and society in ancient Greece.Nicholas F. Jones - 2008 - Westport, Conn.: Praeger.
    Every aspect of life (citizenship, business, literature, drama, art, sports, religion, and private life) in the ancient world was affected by political motives.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. Pliny the Younger's Vesuvius Letters (6.16 and 6.20).Nicholas F. Jones - 2001 - Classical World: A Quarterly Journal on Antiquity 95 (1).
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  10
    The Organization of the Kretan City in Plato's "Laws".Nicholas F. Jones - 1990 - Classical World: A Quarterly Journal on Antiquity 83 (6):473.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48.  4
    Imagining rotation of objects: Comment on Shepard and Metzler.Nicholas F. Skinner & Roger Stretch - 1976 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 7 (2):165-166.
  49.  7
    Personality characteristics of volunteers for painful experiments.Nicholas F. Skinner - 1982 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 20 (6):299-300.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  6
    University grades and time of day of instruction.Nicholas F. Skinner - 1985 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 23 (1):67-67.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 995