Results for 'Jonathan E. Adler'

(not author) ( search as author name )
989 found
Order:
  1. Akratic believing?Jonathan E. Adler - 2002 - Philosophical Studies 110 (1):1 - 27.
    Davidson's account of weakness of will dependsupon a parallel that he draws between practicaland theoretical reasoning. I argue that theparallel generates a misleading picture oftheoretical reasoning. Once the misleadingpicture is corrected, I conclude that theattempt to model akratic belief on Davidson'saccount of akratic action cannot work. Thearguments that deny the possibility of akraticbelief also undermine, more generally, variousattempts to assimilate theoretical to practicalreasoning.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  2.  9
    The Rationality of Science.Jonathan E. Adler - 1983 - Philosophical Quarterly 33 (130):90-92.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  3.  31
    More on race and crime: Levin's reply.Jonathan E. Adler - 1994 - Journal of Social Philosophy 25 (2):105-114.
  4. Epistemological problems of testimony.Jonathan E. Adler - 2006 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   74 citations  
  5. Lying, deceiving, or falsely implicating.Jonathan E. Adler - 1997 - Journal of Philosophy 94 (9):435-452.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   65 citations  
  6.  5
    The Logic of Scientific Inference: An Introduction.Jonathan E. Adler - 1982 - Philosophical Quarterly 32 (128):291-291.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  75
    Testimony, Trust, Knowing.Jonathan E. Adler - 1994 - Journal of Philosophy 91 (5):264-275.
  8.  65
    Review of Mark Johnson: Moral imagination: implications of cognitive science for ethics[REVIEW]Jonathan E. Adler - 1995 - Ethics 105 (2):401-404.
  9. Knowledge and Its Place in Nature.Hilary Kornblith & Jonathan E. Adler - 2004 - Philosophical Quarterly 54 (216):479-482.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   164 citations  
  10. Transmitting knowledge.Jonathan E. Adler - 1996 - Noûs 30 (1):99-111.
  11.  25
    Abstraction is uncooperative.Jonathan E. Adler - 1984 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 14 (2):165–181.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  12.  32
    Fallacies and alternative interpretations.Jonathan E. Adler - 1994 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 72 (3):271 – 282.
  13.  35
    Crime rates by race and causal relevance: A reply to Levin.Jonathan E. Adler - 1993 - Journal of Social Philosophy 24 (1):176-184.
  14. Another argument for the knowledge Norm.Jonathan E. Adler - 2009 - Analysis 69 (3):407-411.
    The knowledge norm of assertion is mainly in competition with a high probability or rational credibility norm. The argument for the knowledge norm that I offer turns on cases in which a hearer responds to a speaker's assertion by asserting another sentence that would lower the probability of the speaker's assertion, were its probability less than one. In cases like this, though with qualifications, is the hearer's contribution a challenge to the speaker's assertion or complementary to it? My answer is (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  15.  40
    Double Standards, Racial Equality and the Right Reference Class.Jonathan E. Adler - 1991 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 8 (1):69-82.
    ABSTRACT There is a popular way of appealing to consistency of judgment or principle whose result is to rule out relevant information. To avoid the danger of judging similar cases differently, relevantly different cases are treated alike. So the information distinguishing them is lost. I try to formulate, defend and apply a requirement upon determining whether situations are similar with respect to a principle. Adherence to the requirement is a way to prevent the loss of information through illicit appeals to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16. Moore's paradox and the transparency of belief.Jonathan E. Adler & Bradley Armour-Garb - 2007 - In Mitchell S. Green & John N. Williams (eds.), Moore's Paradox: New Essays on Belief, Rationality, and the First Person. Oxford University Press.
  17. Withdrawal and contextualism.Jonathan E. Adler - 2006 - Analysis 66 (4):280–285.
  18. Contextualism and fallibility: pragmatic encroachment, possibility, and strength of epistemic position.Jonathan E. Adler - 2012 - Synthese 188 (2):247-272.
    A critique of conversational epistemic contextualism focusing initially on why pragmatic encroachment for knowledge is to be avoided. The data for pragmatic encroachment by way of greater costs of error and the complementary means to raise standards of introducing counter-possibilities are argued to be accountable for by prudence, fallibility and pragmatics. This theme is sharpened by a contrast in recommendations: holding a number of factors constant, when allegedly higher standards for knowing hold, invariantists still recommend assertion (action), while contextualists do (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  19. The ethics of belief: Off the wrong track.Jonathan E. Adler - 1999 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 23 (1):267–285.
  20.  95
    Conservatism and tacit confirmation.Jonathan E. Adler - 1990 - Mind 99 (396):559-570.
  21. Reliabilist justification (or knowledge) as a good truth-ratio.Jonathan E. Adler - 2005 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 86 (4):445–458.
    Fair lotteries offer familiar ways to pose a number of epistemological problems, prominently those of closure and of scepticism. Although these problems apply to many epistemological positions, in this paper I develop a variant of a lottery case to raise a difficulty with the reliabilist's fundamental claim that justification or knowledge is to be analyzed as a high truth-ratio (of the relevant belief-forming processes). In developing the difficulty broader issues are joined including fallibility and the relation of reliability to understanding.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  22.  7
    Confidence in Argument.Jonathan E. Adler - 2006 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 36 (2):225-257.
    When someone presents an argument on a charged topic and it is (credibly) alleged that the arguer has a strong personal interest and investment in the conclusion, the allegation, directed to the reception or evaluation of the argument, typically gives rise to two seemingly conflicting reactions:I. The allegation is an unwarranted diversion (a species ofargumentum ad hominemorgenetie fallacy).The prejudices or biases of the arguer are irrelevant to thecogencyof the argument. ('Cogency’ is used broadly to refer both to correct support relations, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  23.  7
    Knowing, Betting and Cohering.Jonathan E. Adler - 1986 - Philosophical Topics 14 (1):243-257.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  24.  29
    Charity, Interpretation, Fallacy.Jonathan E. Adler - 1996 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 29 (4):329 - 343.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  25.  98
    Skepticism and universalizability.Jonathan E. Adler - 1981 - Journal of Philosophy 78 (3):143-156.
  26.  12
    Surprise.Jonathan E. Adler - 2008 - Educational Theory 58 (2):149-173.
    Surprise is of great value for learning, especially in cases where deep‐seated preconceptions and assumptions are upset by vivid demonstrations. In this essay, Jonathan Adler explores the ways in which surprise positively affects us and serves as a valuable tool for motivating learning. Adler considers how students’ attention is aroused and focused self‐critically when their subject matter–related expectations are not borne out. These “surprises” point students toward discoveries about gaps or weaknesses or false assumptions within their subject (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  8
    Knowledge, Truth, and Learning.Jonathan E. Adler - 2003 - In Randall Curren (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Education. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 285–304.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Epistemological Background Educational Applications On Not Addressing Epistemological Controversies.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  28.  10
    Constrained Belief and the Reactive Attitudes.Jonathan E. Adler - 1997 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 57 (4):891-905.
    Evidentialism implies that, for epistemic purposes, belief should be responsive only to evidence. Focusing on our reactive attitude such as resentment or indignation, I construct an argument that the beliefs or judgments accompanying those attitudes are constrained in advance by circumstances to be full, rather than being open to the whole range of partial beliefs. These judgments or beliefs imply strong claims to justification. But the circumstances in which those attitudes are formed allow only very limited evidence. Nevertheless, we cannot (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  9
    Conversation is the Folks’ Epistemology.Jonathan E. Adler - 2008 - Philosophical Forum 39 (3):337-348.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  14
    Conundrums of Belief Self-Control.Jonathan E. Adler - 2002 - The Monist 85 (3):456-467.
    A much disputed conceptual argument aims to show the impossibility of direct believing at will. Regardless of the success of this argument, it has been held to be impotent against indirect forms of belief-control, such as by developing oneself to be more careful or fair-minded in evaluating evidence. However, the shift to indirect forms inherits difficulties connected to the conceptual argument.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  10
    Hume’s “Of Miracles” (Part One).Jonathan E. Adler - 1994 - Inquiry: Critical Thinking Across the Disciplines 14 (2):1-10.
  32.  11
    Relevant Alternatives, Presuppositions, and Skepticism.Jonathan E. Adler - 1987 - Journal of Philosophy 84 (11):653-654.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  13
    Resisting the Force of Argument.Jonathan E. Adler - 2009 - Journal of Philosophy 106 (6):339-364.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  18
    William James and What Cannot be Believed.Jonathan E. Adler - 2005 - The Harvard Review of Philosophy 13 (1):65-79.
    My critical comments focus mainly on premises,, and. However, in treating these I will address other of James’s assumptions—particularly, the presupposition of his argument that it is possible to will to believe. Later I will try to accommodate existential aspects of James’s argument that retain value, even if my objections to his argument stand.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35.  21
    Review of Douglas N. Walton: Practical Reasoning: Goal-Driven, Knowledge-Based, Action-Guiding Argumentation[REVIEW]Jonathan E. Adler - 1991 - Ethics 102 (1):179-180.
  36. Luckless desert is different desert.Jonathan E. Adler - 1987 - Mind 96 (382):247-249.
  37. Presupposition, attention, and why questions.Jonathan E. Adler - 2008 - In Jonathan Eric Adler & Lance J. Rips (eds.), Reasoning: Studies of Human Inference and its Foundations. Cambridge University Press. pp. 748--764.
  38.  19
    Fallacies Not Fallacious: Not!Jonathan E. Adler - 1997 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 30 (4):333 - 350.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  39.  42
    Knowing, Betting and Cohering.Jonathan E. Adler - 1986 - Philosophical Topics 14 (1):243-257.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  40.  18
    In Defense of Radical Empiricism: Essays and Lectures.Jonathan E. Adler, Roderick Firth & John Troyer - 2000 - Philosophical Review 109 (3):453.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  41.  42
    Particullary, Gilligan, and the two-levels view: A reply.Jonathan E. Adler - 1989 - Ethics 100 (1):149-156.
  42.  57
    Why Be Charitable?Jonathan E. Adler - 1981 - Informal Logic 4 (2).
  43.  32
    Belief and Negation.Jonathan E. Adler & J. Anthony Blair - 2000 - Informal Logic 20 (3).
    This paper argues for the importance of the distinction between internal and external negation over expressions for belief. The common fallacy is to confuse statement like (1) and (2): (1) John believes that the school is not closed on Tuesday; (2) John does not believe that the school is closed on Tuesday. The fallacy has ramifications in teaching, reasoning, and argumentation. Analysis of the fallacy and suggestions for teaching are offered.
    Direct download (13 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  44.  82
    Stove on Hume's inductive scepticism.Jonathan E. Adler - 1975 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 53 (2):167 – 170.
  45. William James and What Cannot be Believed.Jonathan E. Adler - 2005 - The Harvard Review of Philosophy 13 (1):65-79.
    My critical comments focus mainly on premises,, and. However, in treating these I will address other of James’s assumptions—particularly, the presupposition of his argument that it is possible to will to believe. Later I will try to accommodate existential aspects of James’s argument that retain value, even if my objections to his argument stand.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  46.  76
    Constrained belief and the reactive attitudes.Jonathan E. Adler - 1997 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 57 (4):891-905.
    Evidentialism implies that, for epistemic purposes, belief should be responsive only to evidence. Focusing on our reactive attitude such as resentment or indignation, I construct an argument that the beliefs or judgments accompanying those attitudes are constrained in advance by circumstances to be full, rather than being open to the whole range of partial beliefs. These judgments or beliefs imply strong claims to justification. But the circumstances in which those attitudes are formed allow only very limited evidence. Nevertheless, we cannot (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  47.  23
    Critique of an epistemic account of fallacies.Jonathan E. Adler - 1993 - Argumentation 7 (3):263-272.
    An epistemic account of fallacies is one which takes it as a necessary condition for a fallacy that it has a tendency to produce false or unwarranted beliefs. The most sophisticated form of this account occurs in an article by Robert J. Fogelin and Timothy J. Duggan (“Fallacies,”Argumentation 1, 1987, pp. 255–262). I criticize the Fogelin and Duggan proposal, in particular, and epistemic accounts, more generally. Though an epistemic approach is attractive, it enlarges the class of fallacies, beyond what would (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  48.  96
    Epistemics and the total evidence requirement.Jonathan E. Adler - 1989 - Philosophia 19 (2-3):227-243.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  49.  54
    Reasonableness, bias, and the untapped power of procedure.Jonathan E. Adler - 1993 - Synthese 94 (1):105 - 125.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  50.  10
    Reply by Repetition and Reminder.Jonathan E. Adler - 1997 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 30 (4):367 - 375.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
1 — 50 / 989