Results for 'Kripke, S'

(not author) ( search as author name )
915 found
Order:
  1.  39
    A note on Kripke's distinction between rigid designators and nonrigid designators.Sitansu S. Chakravarti - 1979 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 20 (2):309-313.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  95
    Kripke, crusoe and Wittgenstein.S. Davies - 1988 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 66 (1):52-66.
  3. On misunderstanding Wittgenstein: Kripke's private language argument.Gordon P. Baker & P. M. S. Hacker - 1984 - Synthese 58 (3):407-450.
  4. Kripke and Putnam on natural kind terms.Keith S. Donnellan - 1983 - In C. Ginet & S. Shoemaker (eds.), Knowledge and Mind. Oxford Univresity Press. pp. 84-104.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   73 citations  
  5.  35
    The Hintikka-Kripke problem.S. K. Lehmann - 1978 - Philosophia 8 (1):59-70.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  6.  2
    Vitgenshteĭn i Kripke: sledovanie pravilu, skepticheskiĭ argument i tochka zrenii︠a︡ soobshchestva.V. A. Surovt︠s︡ev - 2008 - Tomsk: Izd-vo Tomskogo universiteta. Edited by V. A. Ladov.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. Reply to Critics.S. Soames - 2006 - Philosophical Studies 128 (3):711-738.
    Linsky’s central point is correct; Kripke’s distinction between rigid and nonrigid designators can be extended in a straightforward way from singular terms to general terms. In both cases, for an expression to rigidly designate its extension is for it to designate the same extension with respect to every possible world-state (in which it has an extension at all). On this account, simple natural kind terms like water, gold, electricity, blue, and tiger – as well as ordinary general terms like bachelor, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  8.  60
    A New Semantics for Positive Modal Logic.S. Celani & R. Jansana - 1997 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 38 (1):1-18.
    The paper provides a new semantics for positive modal logic using Kripke frames having a quasi ordering on the set of possible worlds and an accessibility relation connected to the quasi ordering by the conditions (1) that the composition of with is included in the composition of with and (2) the analogous for the inverse of and . This semantics has an advantage over the one used by Dunn in "Positive modal logic," Studia Logica (1995) and works fine for extensions (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  9.  24
    A short introduction to intuitionistic logic.G. E. Mint︠s︡ - 2000 - New York: Kluwer Academic / Plenum Publishers.
    Intuitionistic logic is presented here as part of familiar classical logic which allows mechanical extraction of programs from proofs. to make the material more accessible, basic techniques are presented first for propositional logic; Part II contains extensions to predicate logic. This material provides an introduction and a safe background for reading research literature in logic and computer science as well as advanced monographs. Readers are assumed to be familiar with basic notions of first order logic. One device for making this (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  10.  98
    Kripke and "quus".David S. Oderberg - 1987 - Theoria 53 (2-3):115-20.
  11. The Essentialism of Kripke and Madden and Metaphysical Necessity.Jane S. Zembaty - 1976 - Dissertation, Georgetown University
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  9
    Kripke-Armstrongov argument protiv temporalnih delova.Nikola S. Stamenkovic - 2022 - Theoria: Beograd 65 (1):87-101.
    Kripke-Armstrongovim argumentom tvrdi se da branilac postojanja temporalnih delova materijalnih objekata ne može da utvrdi da li usamljeni homogeni disk sačinjen od kontinuirane materije rotira oko svoje ose ili miruje. Perdurantista ne može da razlikuje dve mogućnosti pozivajući se na različite trenutne brzine trenutnih temporalnih delova diska, zbog toga što bi time prekršio tezu hjumovske supervenijencije. U ovom radu ću, sledeći Džeremija Baterfilda, pokazati kako se na KripkeArmstrongov izazov može odgovoriti zadržavajući hjumovsku supervenijenciju: pozivanjem na različite trenutne brzine netrenutnih temporalnih (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13. Imaginability, conceivability, possibility and the mind-body problem.Christopher S. Hill - 1997 - Philosophical Studies 87 (1):61-85.
  14.  63
    Kripke on contingent a priori truths.Sitansu S. Chakravarti - 1979 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 20 (4):773-776.
  15.  75
    Dynamic topological logic.S. Artemov - unknown
    Dynamic topological logic provides a context for studying the confluence of the topological semantics for S4, topological dynamics, and temporal logic. The topological semantics for S4 is based on topological spaces rather than Kripke frames. In this semantics, is interpreted as topological interior. Thus S4 can be understood as the logic of topological spaces, and can be understood as a topological modality. Topological dynamics studies the asymptotic properties of continuous maps on topological spaces. Let a dynamic topological system be a (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  25
    Introducing Philosophy: Knowledge and Reality.Jack S. Crumley Ii - 2016 - Peterborough, CA: Broadview Press.
    This book introduces the central issues of metaphysics and epistemology, from skepticism, justification, and perception to universals, personal identity, and free will. Though topically organized, the book integrates positions and examples from the history of philosophy. Plato, Descartes, and Leibniz are discussed alongside Quine, Kripke, and Haslanger. Peripheral ideas and related historical asides are offered in boxes interspersed within the text, providing further depth without disrupting the author’s lucid explanations of central themes and arguments. Original illustrations by Gillian Wilson are (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. Logics for epistemic programs.Alexandru Baltag & Lawrence S. Moss - 2004 - Synthese 139 (2):165 - 224.
    We construct logical languages which allow one to represent a variety of possible types of changes affecting the information states of agents in a multi-agent setting. We formalize these changes by defining a notion of epistemic program. The languages are two-sorted sets that contain not only sentences but also actions or programs. This is as in dynamic logic, and indeed our languages are not significantly more complicated than dynamic logics. But the semantics is more complicated. In general, the semantics of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   117 citations  
  18. Rigid designation.Hugh S. Chandler - 1975 - Journal of Philosophy 72 (13):363-369.
    I have been told that for some twenty minutes after reading this paper Kripke believed I had shown that proper names could be non-rigid designators. (Then, apparently, he found a crucial error in the set-up.) I take great pride in this (alleged) fact.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  19. Kripke's knowledge argument against materialism.Adriana Renero - 2023 - Philosophical Perspectives 37 (1):370-387.
    In his unpublished 1979 Lectures on the Philosophy of Mind, Saul Kripke offers a knowledge argument against materialism focusing on deaf people who lack knowledge of auditory experience. Kripke's argument is a precursor of Frank Jackson's better‐known knowledge argument against materialism (1982). The paper sets out Kripke's argument, brings out its interest and philosophical importance, and explores some similarities and differences between Kripke's knowledge argument and Jackson's.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20.  14
    Independence results around constructive ZF.Robert S. Lubarsky - 2005 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 132 (2-3):209-225.
    CZF is an intuitionistic set theory that does not contain Power Set, substituting instead a weaker version, Subset Collection. In this paper a Kripke model of CZF is presented in which Power Set is false. In addition, another Kripke model is presented of CZF with Subset Collection replaced by Exponentiation, in which Subset Collection fails.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  21. Consciousness and the limits of our imaginations.Eric Dietrich & Anthony S. Gillies - 2001 - Synthese 126 (3):361-381.
    Chalmers' anti-materialist arguments are an interesting twist on a well-known argument form, and his naturalistic dualism is exciting to contemplate. Nevertheless, we think we can save materialism from the Chalmerian attack. This is what we do in the present paper.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  22.  78
    On the Non-Necessity of Origin.M. S. Price - 1982 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 12 (1):33 - 45.
    In ‘Naming and Necessity,’ Saul Kripke defends a number of essentialist claims. One of them is that having a certain origin is a necessary property of a material thing. Used in connection with a human being or, presumably, a living thing of another kind whose members sexually reproduce, ‘necessity of origin’ means that the organism must have been born of those individuals who are its parents, i.e., whose body tissues are sources of the sperm and egg from which it issued, (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  23.  66
    On the constructive Dedekind reals.Robert S. Lubarsky & Michael Rathjen - 2008 - Logic and Analysis 1 (2):131-152.
    In order to build the collection of Cauchy reals as a set in constructive set theory, the only power set-like principle needed is exponentiation. In contrast, the proof that the Dedekind reals form a set has seemed to require more than that. The main purpose here is to show that exponentiation alone does not suffice for the latter, by furnishing a Kripke model of constructive set theory, Constructive Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with subset collection replaced by exponentiation, in which the Cauchy (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  24.  22
    Separating the Fan theorem and its weakenings.Robert S. Lubarsky & Hannes Diener - 2014 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 79 (3):792-813.
    Varieties of the Fan Theorem have recently been developed in reverse constructive mathematics, corresponding to different continuity principles. They form a natural implicational hierarchy. Some of the implications have been shown to be strict, others strict in a weak context, and yet others not at all, using disparate techniques. Here we present a family of related Kripke models which separates all of the as yet identified fan theorems.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  25.  7
    Analytical Thomism: Traditions in Dialogue.Matthew S. Pugh & Craig Paterson - 2006 - Routledge.
    Analytical Thomism is a recent label for a newer kind of approach to the philosophical and natural theology of St Thomas Aquinas. It illuminates the meaning of Aquinas's work for contemporary problems by drawing on the resources of contemporary Anglo-Saxon analytical philosophy, the work of Frege, Wittgenstein, and Kripke proving particularly significant. This book expands the discourse in contemporary debate, exploring crucial philosophical, theological and ethical issues such as: metaphysics and epistemology, the nature of God, personhood, action and meta-ethics. All (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26. Kripke's proof is ad hominem not two-dimensional.David Papineau - 2007 - Philosophical Perspectives 21 (1):475–494.
    Identity theorists make claims like ‘pain = C-fibre stimulation’. These claims must be necessary if true, given that terms like ‘pain’ and ‘C-fibre stimulation’ are rigid. Yet there is no doubt that such claims appear contingent. It certainly seems that there could have been C-fibre stimulation without pains or vice versa. So identity theorists owe us an explanation of why such claims should appear contingent if they are in fact necessary.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  27.  79
    Necessity and rigidly designating kind terms.Ben S. Cordry - 2004 - Philosophical Studies 119 (3):243-264.
    Kripke claims that certainkind terms, particularly natural kind terms,are, like names, rigid designators. However,kind terms are more complicated than names aseach is connected both to a principle ofinclusion and an extension. So, there is aquestion regarding what it is that rigidlydesignating kind terms rigidly designate. Inthis paper, I assume that there are rigidlydesignating kind terms and attempt to answerthe question as to what it is that they rigidlydesignate. I then use this analysis of rigidlydesignating kind terms to show how Kripke''sreasoning (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  28. Kripke's Wittgenstein, on certainty, and epistemic relativism.Martin Kusch - 2009 - In Daniel Whiting (ed.), The later Wittgenstein on language. New York: Palgrave-Macmillan.
  29.  5
    Modality, reference, and sense: an essay in the philosophy of language.Sitansu S. Chakravarti - 2001 - New Delhi: Munshiram Manoharlal Publishers.
    Description: The book points to a new logic of singular designators based upon a close analysis of work in the area by contemporary philosophers of language. The philosophers range from Frege, Russell, Quine, Strawson and Dummett to Kripke, Hintikka, Plantinga, Kaplan, Donnellan, Searle and Burge. It is generally taken for granted that proper names are rigid designators, having no meaning content, which explains their intranslatability into other languages. However, they do have their modes of presentation that must constitute their sense. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30. Causality, referring, and proper names.David S. Schwarz - 1978 - Linguistics and Philosophy 2 (2):225 - 233.
    I argue that (a) the causal theory of proper names and (b) Kripke's chain of references thesis are logically independent of each other, and that the case for (a) is very weak. I observe that rejecting (a) we lose one powerful reason for treating proper names as rigid designators. I then consider reasons for subscribing to (b), and I argue that (b) is compatible with either a rigid or a non-rigid (descriptive) semantic treatment of proper names.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  21
    Completeness of intermediate logics with doubly negated axioms.Mohammad Ardeshir & S. Mojtaba Mojtahedi - 2014 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 60 (1-2):6-11.
    Let denote a first‐order logic in a language that contains infinitely many constant symbols and also containing intuitionistic logic. By, we mean the associated logic axiomatized by the double negation of the universal closure of the axioms of plus. We shall show that if is strongly complete for a class of Kripke models, then is strongly complete for the class of Kripke models that are ultimately in.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  11
    Separating the Fan theorem and its weakenings II.Robert S. Lubarsky - 2019 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 84 (4):1484-1509.
    Varieties of the Fan Theorem have recently been developed in reverse constructive mathematics, corresponding to different continuity principles. They form a natural implicational hierarchy. Earlier work showed all of these implications to be strict. Here we reprove one of the strictness results, using very different arguments. The technique used is a mixture of realizability, forcing in the guise of Heyting-valued models, and Kripke models.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  4
    Kripke's Argument for Mind–Body Property Dualism.Dale Jacquette - 2011-09-16 - In Michael Bruce & Steven Barbone (eds.), Just the Arguments. Wiley‐Blackwell. pp. 301–303.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  35
    Naming and Necessity By Saul Kripke Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1980, 172 pp., £7.95. [REVIEW]T. L. S. Sprigge - 1981 - Philosophy 56 (217):431-.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  16
    Naming and Necessity By Saul Kripke Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1980, 172 pp., £7.95. [REVIEW]T. L. S. Sprigge - 1981 - Philosophy 56 (217):431-433.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36. Kripke’s Normativity Argument.José L. Zalabardo - 1997 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 27 (4):467-488.
    In Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language, Saul Kripke rejects some of the most popular accounts of what meaning facts consist in on the grounds that they fail to accommodate the normative character of meaning. I argue that a widespread interpretation of Kripke's argument is incorrect. I contend that the argument does not rest on the contrast between descriptive and normative facts, but on the thought that speakers' uses of linguistic expressions have to be justified. I suggest that the line (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  37. Attitudes Towards Reference and Replaceability.Christopher Grau & Cynthia L. S. Pury - 2014 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 5 (2):155-168.
    Robert Kraut has proposed an analogy between valuing a loved one as irreplaceable and the sort of “rigid” attachment that (according to Saul Kripke’s account) occurs with the reference of proper names. We wanted to see if individuals with Kripkean intuitions were indeed more likely to value loved ones (and other persons and things) as irreplaceable. In this empirical study, 162 participants completed an online questionnaire asking them to consider how appropriate it would be to feel the same way about (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  38. Axiomatizing Kripke’s Theory of Truth.Volker Halbach & Leon Horsten - 2006 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 71 (2):677 - 712.
    We investigate axiomatizations of Kripke's theory of truth based on the Strong Kleene evaluation scheme for treating sentences lacking a truth value. Feferman's axiomatization KF formulated in classical logic is an indirect approach, because it is not sound with respect to Kripke's semantics in the straightforward sense: only the sentences that can be proved to be true in KF are valid in Kripke's partial models. Reinhardt proposed to focus just on the sentences that can be proved to be true in (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   74 citations  
  39.  1
    Kripke’s Newton/George Smith problem and a naming-using-practice-based theory. 이풍실 - 2018 - Cheolhak-Korean Journal of Philosophy 137:185-217.
    본 논고에서는 크립키가 『명명과 필연(Naming and Necessity)』에서 논의했던 두 사례를 소개한다. 이 사례들에서 문제가 되는 것은 특정인을 지칭하는 고유명을 알고 있는 사람이 그렇지 못한 사람에게 처음으로 그 이름을 사용하는 발화이다. 여기서 크립키가 주목하는 현상은 어떤 고유명의 사용은 명백한 오정보와 결합됨에도 불구하고 그 지시체에 대한 거짓 믿음을 성공적으로 야기하는 반면에, 다른 고유명의 사용은 오정보와 결합되어 발화될 경우에 청자로 하여금 그 고유명의 지시체에 대한 거짓 믿음을 야기하는 데 실패할 수 있는 것처럼 보인다는 것이다. 만일 이러한 믿음의 야기가 실패한다면 왜 동일한 인과적 체인의 (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. Kripke's account of the argument against private language.Crispin Wright - 1984 - Journal of Philosophy 81 (12):759-78.
  41. On Kripke’s and Goodman’s Uses of ”Grue’.Ian Hacking - 1993 - Philosophy 68 (265):269-295.
    Kripke's lectures, published as Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language , posed a sceptical problem about following a rule, which he cautiously attributed to Wittgenstein. He briefly noticed an analogy between his new kind of scepticism and Goodman's riddle of induction. ‘Grue’, he said, could be used to formulate a question not about induction but about meaning: the problem would not be Goodman's about induction—‘Why not predict that grass, which has been grue in the past, will be grue in the (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  42. Kripke’s Revenge.Theodore Sider & David Braun - 2006 - Philosophical Studies 128 (3):669-682.
    Kripke's objections to descriptivism may be modified to apply to Scott Soames's pragmatic account from his book Beyond Rigidity. Further, intuitions about argument-validity threaten any theory in the vicinity of Soames's.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  43.  90
    Kripke’s Wittgenstein’s Sceptical Paradox: A Trilemma for Davidson.Ali Hossein Khani - 2019 - International Journal for the Study of Skepticism 9 (1):21–37.
    Davidson’s later philosophy of language has been inspired by Wittgenstein’s Investigations, but Davidson by no means sympathizes with the sceptical problem and solution Kripke attributes to Wittgenstein. Davidson criticizes the sceptical argument for relying on the rule-following conception of meaning, which is, for him, a highly problematic view. He also casts doubt on the plausibility of the sceptical solution as unjustifiably bringing in shared practices of a speech community. According to Davidson, it is rather success in mutual interpretation that explains (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  44. Kripke's transcendental realist fantasy, and Wittgenstein's transcendental idealism, after all.Avner Baz - 2023 - In Martin Gustafsson, Oskari Kuusela & Jakub Mácha (eds.), Engaging Kripke with Wittgenstein: The Standard Meter, Contingent Apriori, and Beyond. New York: Routledge.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. Kripke's Wittgenstein and Kripke's causal-historical picture of reference.Alexander Miller - 2023 - In Martin Gustafsson, Oskari Kuusela & Jakub Mácha (eds.), Engaging Kripke with Wittgenstein: The Standard Meter, Contingent Apriori, and Beyond. New York: Routledge.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. Kripke's standard meter : a religious dream?Christian Helmut Wenzel - 2023 - In Martin Gustafsson, Oskari Kuusela & Jakub Mácha (eds.), Engaging Kripke with Wittgenstein: The Standard Meter, Contingent Apriori, and Beyond. New York: Routledge.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. Kripke's account of the rule‐following considerations.Andrea Guardo - 2012 - European Journal of Philosophy 20 (3):366-388.
    This paper argues that most of the alleged straight solutions to the sceptical paradox which Kripke ascribed to Wittgenstein can be regarded as the first horn of a dilemma whose second horn is the paradox itself. The dilemma is proved to be a by‐product of a foundationalist assumption on the notion of justification, as applied to linguistic behaviour. It is maintained that the assumption is unnecessary and that the dilemma is therefore spurious. To this end, an alternative conception of the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  48. Kripke’s Wittgenstein and Ginsborg’s Reductive Dispositionalism (In Persian).Ali Hossein Khani - forthcoming - Metaphysics (University of Isfahan).
    Kripke in his famous book on Wittgenstein’s later philosophy argues, on behalf of Wittgenstein, that there can be no fact of the matter as to what a speaker means by her words, that is, no fact that can meet the Constitution Demand and the Normativity Demand. He particularly argues against the dispositional view, according to which meaning facts are constituted by facts about the speaker's dispositions to respond in a certain way on certain occasions. He argues that facts about dispositions (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. Kripke's Objections to Description Theories of Names.Michael McKinsey - 1978 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 8 (3):485 - 497.
    In “Naming and Necessity” Saul Kripke describes some cases which, he claims, provide counterexamples both to cluster theories and, more generally, to description theories of proper names. My view of these cases is that while they do not provide counterexamples to cluster theories, they can be used to provide evidence against single-description theories. In this paper I shall defend both of the claims involved in my view.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  50.  78
    Applying Kripke's Theory of Truth.Vann McGee - 1989 - Journal of Philosophy 86 (10):530-539.
1 — 50 / 915