Results for 'John Tienson'

991 found
Order:
  1.  16
    Reference and Essence.John Tienson - 1981 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 49 (4):1417-1419.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   81 citations  
  2.  17
    About competence.John L. Tienson - 1990 - Philosophical Papers 19 (1):19-36.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  3.  79
    Brains are not conscious.John L. Tienson - 1987 - Philosophical Papers 16 (November):187-93.
  4.  24
    Innate Ideas.John Tienson - 1978 - Noûs 12 (3):337-343.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  5.  2
    Oblique Contexts.John Tienson - 1986 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 51 (3):821-822.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  43
    An introduction to connectionism.John L. Tienson - 1988 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 26 (S1):1-16.
  7.  52
    On analysing knowledge.John Tienson - 1974 - Philosophical Studies 25 (4):289 - 293.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  8. Introduction to connectionism.John L. Tienson - 1987 - Southern Journal of Philosophy (Suppl.) 1:1-16.
  9.  72
    Hume on universals and general terms.John Tienson - 1984 - Noûs 18 (2):311-330.
  10.  8
    Questions for blobjectivism.John Tienson - 2002 - Facta Philosophica 2 (2):301-10.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  11. The Intentionality of Phenomenology and the Phenomenology of Intentionality.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 2002 - In David J. Chalmers (ed.), Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings. Oup Usa. pp. 520--533.
  12.  21
    A Conception of Metaphysics.John L. Tienson - 1989 - American Philosophical Quarterly 26 (1):63 - 71.
  13.  55
    Kasimir Twardowski on the content of presentations.John Tienson - 2013 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 12 (3):485-499.
    In On the Content and Object of Presentations, Kasimir Twardowski presents an interesting line of thought concerning the content of a presentation and its relation to the object of that presentation. This way of thinking about content is valuable for understanding phenomenal intentionality, and it should also be important for the project of “naturalizing” the mental (or at least for discovering the neural correlates of the phenomenal). According to this view, content is that by virtue of which a presentation of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14.  23
    An argument concerning quantification and propositional attitudes.John L. Tienson - 1987 - Philosophical Studies 51 (2):145 - 168.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  59
    An Observation on Common Names and Proper Names.John Tienson - 1986 - Analysis 46 (2):73 - 76.
    Common names, for Mill, have both connotation and denotation. Thus ‘horse’ connotes certain properties, and the name ‘horse’ denotes the things that have those properties. By contrast, proper names have no connotations; they do not denote in virtue of the possession of certain properties by their denotations, but so to speak, directly. Thus Socrates received his name by being dubbed ‘Socrates’; and he might just as well have been given any other name. This contrast is misleading. After all, we might (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  12
    An observation on common names and proper.John Tienson - 1986 - Analysis 46 (1):73-76.
    Common names, for Mill, have both connotation and denotation. Thus ‘horse’ connotes certain properties, and the name ‘horse’ denotes the things that have those properties. By contrast, proper names have no connotations; they do not denote in virtue of the possession of certain properties by their denotations, but so to speak, directly. Thus Socrates received his name by being dubbed ‘Socrates’; and he might just as well have been given any other name.This contrast is misleading. After all, we might have (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  73
    Can Things of Different Natural Kinds Be Exactly Alike?John Tienson - 1977 - Analysis 37 (4):190 - 197.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  18. Can things of different natural kinds be exactly alike?John Tienson - 1977 - Analysis 37 (4):190.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19.  33
    Entia successiva and ordinary things.John L. Tienson - 1985 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 23 (4):475-479.
  20.  8
    Entia Successiva and Ordinary Things.John L. Tienson - 2010 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 23 (4):475-479.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  15
    Hintikka's argument for the 'basic restriction'.John Tienson - 1975 - Philosophical Studies 28 (1):33 - 40.
  22.  53
    Hesperus and Phosphorus I.John Tienson - 1984 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 62:16.
  23.  63
    Higher-order causation.John Tienson - 2002 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 63 (1):89-101.
    We have a familiar idea of levels of description or levels of theory in science: microphysics, atomic physics, chemistry, biology, psychology, and the various social sciences. It is clear that philosophers - such as Terry Horgan - who want to be nonreductive materialists with regard to the mental must hold that this is not mere description; there must be genuine higher-level causes, and hence, genuine higher-level properties, in particular mental properties and causes. But there appears to be a deep problem (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24.  19
    Is this any way to be a realist?John L. Tienson - 1990 - Philosophical Psychology 3 (1):155-164.
    Andy Clark argues that the reality and causal efficacy of the folk psychological attitudes do not require in‐the‐head correlates of the that‐clauses by which they are attributed. The facts for which Fodor invokes a language of thought as empirical explanation—systemati‐city, for example—are, Clark argues, an a priori conceptual demand upon propositional attitude ascription, and hence not in need of empirical explanation. However, no such strategy can work. A priori demands imposed by our practices do not eliminate the need for empirical (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25.  83
    Resemblance and general terms.John L. Tienson - 1988 - Philosophical Studies 54 (1):87 - 108.
    Any successful account of general terms must explain our ability to apply terms correctly to new instances. Many philosophers have thought resemblance offers an ontologically sparse basis for such an account. However, Any natural and plausible account of general terms on the basis of resemblance requires quite a rich ontology, Including at least second order properties and relations. Given a sufficiently rich structure of resemblances, We can surely account for the application of many general terms. I argue, However, That our (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26.  59
    Synonyms and the objects of belief.John L. Tienson - 1982 - Philosophical Studies 42 (3):297 - 313.
  27.  33
    What Does a Deceived Cartesian Meditator Know?John Tienson - 2007 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 45 (S1):49-59.
  28.  19
    What the differences are: Reply to Hardcastle.John Tienson - 1997 - Philosophical Psychology 10 (3):385 – 389.
    Hardcastle argues that we make distinctions where there are no differences when we speak of (1) levels of description, (2) cognitive forces, and (3) soft laws in psychology. Concerning (1) and (2), the differences just are differences in description. The same state is referred to by three different descriptions, and talk of cognitive forces is appropriate and useful at the cognitive level of description. And concerning (3), if our view of cognition is correct, then the laws of psychology are importantly (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. Phenomenology, Intentionality, and the Unity of the Mind.George Graham, Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 2009 - In Brian McLaughlin, Ansgar Beckermann & Sven Walter (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind. Oxford University Press. pp. 512--537.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  30.  91
    Connectionism and the Philosophy of Psychology.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1996 - MIT Press.
    In Connectionism and the Philosophy of Psychology, Horgan and Tienson articulate and defend a new view of cognition.
  31. Phenomenal intentionality and the brain in a vat.Terence E. Horgan, John L. Tienson & George Graham - 2004 - In Richard Schantz (ed.), The Externalist Challenge. De Gruyter.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  32. Internal-World Skepticism and the Self-Presentational Nature of Phenomenal Consciousness.Terence Horgan, John Tienson & Graham George - 2006 - In Kriegel Uriah & Kenneth Williford (eds.), Self-representational Approaches to Consciousness. Bradford.
  33.  48
    Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind.Terence E. Horgan & John L. Tienson (eds.) - 1991 - Kluwer Academic Publishers.
    "A third of the papers in this volume originated at the 1987 Spindel Conference ... at Memphis State University"--Pref.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  34.  5
    Consciousness and Intentionality.George Graham, Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 2017 - In Susan Schneider & Max Velmans (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness. Chichester, UK: Wiley. pp. 519–535.
    Consciousness and intentionality help to define the mental qua mental. Consciousness and intentionality, insist some philosophers, although perhaps often co‐occurring, are mutually independent or separable. Consciousness and intentionality, insist others, are interdependent or inseparable. This chapter discusses an important aspect of inseparatism: the relation between phenomenal character and intentional content. The contemporary philosophers and theorists have developed inseparatist or nearly inseparatist theses in various ways. The chapter mentions some of this work, and the philosophers responsible for it. It discusses two (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. The phenomenology of first-person agency.Terence E. Horgan, John L. Tienson & George Graham - 2003 - In Sven Walter & Heinz-Dieter Heckmann (eds.), Physicalism and Mental Causation. Imprint Academic. pp. 323.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  36. Deconstructing new wave materialism.Terence E. Horgan & John L. Tienson - 2001 - In Carl Gillett & Barry M. Loewer (eds.), Physicalism and its Discontents. Cambridge University Press. pp. 307--318.
    In the first post World War II identity theories (e.g., Place 1956, Smart 1962), mind brain identities were held to be contingent. However, in work beginning in the late 1960's, Saul Kripke (1971, 1980) convinced the philosophical community that true identity statements involving names and natural kind terms are necessarily true and furthermore, that many such necessary identities can only be known a posteriori. Kripke also offered an explanation of the a posteriori nature of ordinary theoretical identities such as that (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  37.  51
    Soft laws.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1990 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 15 (1):256-279.
  38.  81
    Representations without Rules.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1989 - Philosophical Topics 17 (1):147-174.
  39.  67
    Representation without rules.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1989 - Philosophical Topics 17 (1):147-74.
  40. A nonclassical framework for cognitive science.Terence E. Horgan & John L. Tienson - 1994 - Synthese 101 (3):305-45.
    David Marr provided a useful framework for theorizing about cognition within classical, AI-style cognitive science, in terms of three levels of description: the levels of (i) cognitive function, (ii) algorithm and (iii) physical implementation. We generalize this framework: (i) cognitive state transitions, (ii) mathematical/functional design and (iii) physical implementation or realization. Specifying the middle, design level to be the theory of dynamical systems yields a nonclassical, alternative framework that suits (but is not committed to) connectionism. We consider how a brain's (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  41. The phenomenology of intentionality and the intentionality of phenomenology.Terry Horgan & John Tienson - 2002 - In David J. Chalmers (ed.), Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings. Oxford University Press. pp. 520--533.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  42. Cognitive systems as dynamic systems.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1992 - Topoi 11 (1):27-43.
  43.  24
    Representations without Rules.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1989 - Philosophical Topics 17 (1):147-174.
  44.  40
    Settling into a new paradigm.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1987 - Southern Journal of Philosophy Supplement 26 (S1):97-113.
  45.  70
    Connectionism and the commitments of folk psychology.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1995 - Philosophical Perspectives 9:127-52.
  46.  17
    Settling into a new paradigm.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1991 - Southern Journal of Philosophy Supplement 26 (S1):241--260.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  47. Leonard Linsky. Oblique contexts. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago and London1983, xxxvii + 175 pp. [REVIEW]John Tienson - 1986 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 51 (3):821-822.
  48.  8
    Nathan U. Salmon. Reference and essence. Princeton University Press, Princeton1981, xvi + 293 pp. [REVIEW]John Tienson - 1984 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 49 (4):1417-1419.
  49.  3
    Review: Leonard Linsky, Oblique Contexts. [REVIEW]John Tienson - 1986 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 51 (3):821-822.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  19
    Review: Nathan U. Salmon, Reference and Essence. [REVIEW]John Tienson - 1984 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 49 (4):1417-1419.
1 — 50 / 991