Results for 'Terence E. Horgan'

(not author) ( search as author name )
998 found
Order:
  1. From supervenience to superdupervenience: Meeting the demands of a material world.Terence E. Horgan - 1993 - Mind 102 (408):555-86.
  2.  48
    Austere Realism: Contextual Semantics Meets Minimal Ontology.Terence E. Horgan & Matjaž Potrc - 2008 - MIT Press.
    The authors of Austere Realism describe and defend a provocative ontological-cum-semantic position, asserting that the right ontology is minimal or austere, in that it excludes numerous common-sense posits, and that statements employing such posits are nonetheless true, when truth is understood to be semantic correctness under contextually operative semantic standards. Terence Horgan and Matjaz [hacek over z] Potrc [hacek over c] argue that austere realism emerges naturally from consideration of the deep problems within the naive common-sense approach to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  3. Jackson on physical information and qualia.Terence E. Horgan - 1984 - Philosophical Quarterly 34 (April):147-52.
  4. Phenomenal intentionality and the brain in a vat.Terence E. Horgan, John L. Tienson & George Graham - 2004 - In Richard Schantz (ed.), The Externalist Challenge. De Gruyter.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  5. Nonreductive materialism and the explanatory autonomy of psychology.Terence E. Horgan - 1993 - In Steven J. Wagner & Richard Warner (eds.), Naturalism: A Critical Appraisal. University of Notre Dame Press.
  6. Kim on mental causation and causal exclusion.Terence E. Horgan - 1997 - Philosophical Perspectives 11:165-84.
  7.  48
    Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind.Terence E. Horgan & John L. Tienson (eds.) - 1991 - Kluwer Academic Publishers.
    "A third of the papers in this volume originated at the 1987 Spindel Conference ... at Memphis State University"--Pref.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  8. The phenomenology of first-person agency.Terence E. Horgan, John L. Tienson & George Graham - 2003 - In Sven Walter & Heinz-Dieter Heckmann (eds.), Physicalism and Mental Causation. Imprint Academic. pp. 323.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  9. Deconstructing new wave materialism.Terence E. Horgan & John L. Tienson - 2001 - In Carl Gillett & Barry M. Loewer (eds.), Physicalism and its Discontents. Cambridge University Press. pp. 307--318.
    In the first post World War II identity theories (e.g., Place 1956, Smart 1962), mind brain identities were held to be contingent. However, in work beginning in the late 1960's, Saul Kripke (1971, 1980) convinced the philosophical community that true identity statements involving names and natural kind terms are necessarily true and furthermore, that many such necessary identities can only be known a posteriori. Kripke also offered an explanation of the a posteriori nature of ordinary theoretical identities such as that (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  10. A nonclassical framework for cognitive science.Terence E. Horgan & John L. Tienson - 1994 - Synthese 101 (3):305-45.
    David Marr provided a useful framework for theorizing about cognition within classical, AI-style cognitive science, in terms of three levels of description: the levels of (i) cognitive function, (ii) algorithm and (iii) physical implementation. We generalize this framework: (i) cognitive state transitions, (ii) mathematical/functional design and (iii) physical implementation or realization. Specifying the middle, design level to be the theory of dynamical systems yields a nonclassical, alternative framework that suits (but is not committed to) connectionism. We consider how a brain's (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  11. Actions, reasons, and the explanatory role of content.Terence E. Horgan - 1991 - In Brian P. McLaughlin (ed.), Dretske and His Critics. Blackwell.
  12.  57
    Supervenient bridge laws.Terence E. Horgan - 1978 - Philosophy of Science 45 (2):227-249.
    I invoke the conceptual machinery of contemporary possible-world semantics to provide an account of the metaphysical status of "bridge laws" in intertheoretic reductions. I argue that although bridge laws are not definitions, and although they do not necessarily reflect attribute-identities, they are supervenient. I.e., they are true in all possible worlds in which the reducing theory is true.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  13. Consciousness and intentionality.George Graham, Terence E. Horgan & John L. Tienson - 2007 - In Max Velmans & Susan Schneider (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness. Blackwell. pp. 468--484.
  14.  37
    Lehrer on 'could'-statements.Terence E. Horgan - 1977 - Philosophical Studies 32 (4):403 - 411.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  15. Structured representations in connectionist systems?Terence E. Horgan & John L. Tienson - 1991 - In S. Davis (ed.), Connectionism: Theorye and Practice. Oxford University Press.
  16. Mary Mary, quite contrary.George Graham & Terence E. Horgan - 2000 - Philosophical Studies 99 (1):59-87.
  17. Against the token identity theory.Terence E. Horgan & Michael Tye - 1985 - In Brian P. McLaughlin & Ernest LePore (eds.), Actions and Events: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson. Blackwell.
  18. Multiple reference, multiple realization, and the reduction of mind.Terence E. Horgan - 2001 - In Reality and Humean Supervenience: Essays on the Philosophy of David Lewis. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.
  19. Southern fundamentalism and the end of philosophy.George Graham & Terence E. Horgan - 1994 - Philosophical Issues 5:219-247.
  20. Internal-world skepticism and mental self-presentation.Terence E. Horgan, John L. Tienson & George Graham - 2006 - In Uriah Kriegel & Kenneth Williford (eds.), Self-Representational Approaches to Consciousness. MIT Press. pp. 41-61.
  21. What does it take to be a true believer? Against the opulent ideology of eliminative materialism.Terence E. Horgan & David K. Henderson - 2005 - In Christina E. Erneling & D. Johnson (eds.), Mind As a Scientific Object. Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  26
    Modelling the noncomputational mind: Reply to Litch.Terence E. Horgan - 1997 - Philosophical Psychology 10 (3):365-371.
    I explain why, within the nonclassical framework for cognitive science we describe in the book, cognitive-state transitions can fail to be tractably computable even if they are subserved by a discrete dynamical system whose mathematical-state transitions are tractably computable. I distinguish two ways that cognitive processing might conform to programmable rules in which all operations that apply to representation-level structure are primitive, and two corresponding constraints on models of cognition. Although Litch is correct in maintaining that classical cognitive science is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  23. Nonreductive materialism.Terence E. Horgan - 1994 - In Richard Warner & Tadeusz Szubka (eds.), The Mind-Body Problem: A Guide to the Current Debate. Blackwell.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  24. Authors' replies.Terence E. Horgan & John L. Tienson - 1999 - Acta Analytica 144:275-287.
  25. Cognition is real.Terence E. Horgan - 1987 - Behaviorism 15 (1):13-25.
  26. Short prcis of connectionism and the philosophy of psychology.Terence E. Horgan - 1999 - Acta Analytica 144:9-21.
  27. Themes in my philosophical work.Terence E. Horgan - 2002 - In Johannes L. Brandl (ed.), Essays on the Philosophy of Terence Horgan. Atlanta: Rodopi. pp. 1-26.
    I invoked the notion of supervenience in my doctoral disseration, Microreduction and the Mind-Body Problem, completed at the University of Michigan in 1974 under the direction of Jaegwon Kim. I had been struck by the appeal to supervenience in Hare (1952), a classic work in twentieth century metaethics that I studied at Michigan in a course on metaethics taught by William Frankena; and I also had been struck by the brief appeal to supervenience in Davidson (1970). Kim was already, in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. Cognition needs syntax but not rules.Terence E. Horgan & John L. Tienson - 2006 - In Robert J. Stainton (ed.), Contemporary Debates in Cognitive Science. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 147--158.
    Human cognition is rich, varied, and complex. In this Chapter we argue that because of the richness of human cognition (and human mental life generally), there must be a syntax of cognitive states, but because of this very richness, cognitive processes cannot be describable by exceptionless rules. The argument for syntax, in Section 1, has to do with being able to get around in any number of possible environments in a complex world. Since nature did not know where in the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. Reality and Humean Supervenience: Essays on the Philosophy of David Lewis.Terence E. Horgan - 2001 - Lanham: Rowman &Amp; Littlefield.
    Reality and Humean Supervenience confronts the reader with central aspects in the philosophy of David Lewis, whose work in ontology, metaphysics, logic, probability, philosophy of mind, and language articulates a unique and systematic foundation for modern physicalism.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30. Recognitional concepts and the compositionality of concept possession.Terence E. Horgan - 1998 - Philosophical Issues 9:27-33.
  31.  84
    Sensations and grain processes.George Graham & Terence E. Horgan - 1998 - In Gregory R. Mulhauser (ed.), Evolving Consciousness. John Benjamins.
  32.  80
    Practicing safe epistemology.David Henderson & Terence E. Horgan - 2001 - Philosophical Studies 102 (3):227 - 258.
    Reliablists have argued that the important evaluative epistemic concept of being justified in holding a belief, at least to the extent that that concept is associated with knowledge, is best understood as concerned with the objective appropriateness of the processes by which a given belief is generated and sustained. In particular, they hold that a belief is justified only when it is fostered by processes that are reliable (at least minimally so) in the believer’s actual world.[1] Of course, reliablists typically (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  33. Simulation and epistemic competence.David K. Henderson & Terence E. Horgan - 2000 - In H. Kobler & K. Steuber (eds.), Empathy and Agency: The Problem of Understanding in the Social Sciences. Westview.
    Epistemology has recently come to more and more take the articulate form of an investigation into how we do, and perhaps might better, manage the cognitive chores of producing, modifying, and generally maintaining belief-sets with a view to having a true and systematic understanding of the world. While this approach has continuities with earlier philosophy, it admittedly makes a departure from the tradition of epistemology as first philosophy.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  34.  50
    Review of Levine's Purple Haze[REVIEW]Terence E. Horgan - 2006 - Noûs 40 (3).
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. Robust vagueness and the forced-March sorites paradox.Terence Horgan - 1994 - Philosophical Perspectives 8:159-188.
    I distinguish two broad approaches to vagueness that I call "robust" and "wimpy". Wimpy construals explain vagueness as robust (i.e., does not manifest arbitrary precision); that standard approaches to vagueness, like supervaluationism or appeals to degrees of truth, wrongly treat vagueness as wimpy; that vagueness harbors an underlying logical incoherence; that vagueness in the world is therefore impossible; and that the kind of logical incoherence nascent in vague terms and concepts is benign rather than malignant. I describe some implications for (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  36. Causal compatibilism and the exclusion problem.Terence Horgan - 2001 - Theoria 16 (40):95-116.
    Terry Horgan University of Memphis In this paper I address the problem of causal exclusion, specifically as it arises for mental properties (although the scope of the discussion is more general, being applicable to other kinds of putatively causal properties that are not identical to narrowly physical causal properties, i.e., causal properties posited by physics). I summarize my own current position on the matter, and I offer a defense of this position. I draw upon and synthesize relevant discussions in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  37. Themes from G.e. Moore: New essays in epistemology and ethics • by Susana Nuccetelli and Gary Seay.Terence Cuneo - 2009 - Analysis 69 (1):167-169.
    G.E. Moore's philosophical legacy is ambiguous. On the one hand, Moore has a special place in the hearts of many contemporary analytic philosophers. He is, after all, one of the fathers of the movement, his broadly commonsensical methodology informing how many contemporary analytic philosophers practise their craft. On the other hand, many contemporary philosophers keep Moore's own substantive positions at arm's distance. According to many epistemologists, one can find no finer example of how to beg the question than Moore's case (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  42
    Drawing out culture: productive methods to measure cognition and resonance.Terence E. McDonnell - 2014 - Theory and Society 43 (3):247-274.
    Theories of culture and action, especially after the cognitive turn, have developed more complex understandings of how unconscious, embodied, internalized culture motivates action. As our theories have become more sophisticated, our methods for capturing these internal processes have not kept up and we struggle to adjudicate among theories of how culture shapes action. This article discusses what I call “productive” methods: methods that observe people creating a cultural object. Productive methods, I argue, are well suited for drawing out moments of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  39. God and World In the Old Testament: A Relational Theology of Creation.Terence E. Fretheim - 2005
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  40. The Suffering of God: An Old Testament Perspective.Terence E. Fretheim - 1984
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  41. Exodus.Terence E. Fretheim - 1991
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  42.  45
    Xenophobia and other reasons to wonder about the domain specificity of folk-biological classification.Terence E. Hays - 1998 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 21 (4):575-576.
    Atran adds a synthesis of much of the literature on folk-biological classification to important new experimental data relevant to long-standing inferences about the structure of folk taxonomies. What we know about such systems is somewhat overstated, and key issues remain unresolved, especially concerning the centrality of “generic species,” the primacy of “general purpose” taxonomies, and domain specificity.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. Creation, Fall, and Flood.Terence E. Fretheim - 1969
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  44. Abraham: Trials of Family and Faith.Terence E. Fretheim - 2007
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. First and Second Kings.Terence E. Fretheim - 1999
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46.  14
    Old Testament Commentaries: Their Selection and Use.Terence E. Fretheim - 1982 - Interpretation 36 (4):356-371.
    Criteria which will assist users in determining which commentaries will be most helpful to them are necessary in view of the wide variety of volumes available.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. Some Reflections on Brueggemann's God.”.Terence E. Fretheim - 1998 - In T. Linafelt & T. K. Beal (eds.), God in the Fray. Fortress Press. pp. 24--37.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  16
    The Jacob Traditions: Theology and Hermeneutic.Terence E. Fretheim - 1972 - Interpretation 26 (4):419-436.
    Every layer of interpretation in the biblical materials must be sought out and recognized by the church as a basis for speaking to the contemporary world.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  43
    The Reclamation of Creation: Redemption and Law in Exodus.Terence E. Fretheim - 1991 - Interpretation: A Journal of Bible and Theology 45 (4):354-365.
    Whereas in modern times Genesis has been read in the light of Exodus, and creation has been understood in the light of redemption and the giving of the law at Mount Sinai, it now seems clear that one must reverse the order Exodus is to be understood in the light of Genesis and redemption and law in the light of creation.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. Rousseau and enlightenment.Terence E. Marshall - 1978 - Political Theory 6 (4):421-455.
1 — 50 / 998