Results for 'Jeanne Peijnenburg'

(not author) ( search as author name )
933 found
Order:
  1.  49
    Shaping your past selves.Peijnenburg Jeanne - 2005 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 28 (5):657-658.
    I propose to complement Ainslie's idea of “bargaining with your future selves” with that of “shaping your past selves.” The result of such a complementation is that an action can work in two ways: (1) as a predecent for future behavior and (2) as a shaper of past behavior. I argue that this diminishes the unwanted effects of hyperbolic discounting even further.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. Fading Foundations: Probability and the Regress Problem.Jeanne Peijnenburg - 2017 - Cham, Switzerland: Springer. Edited by Jeanne Peijnenburg.
    This Open Access book addresses the age-old problem of infinite regresses in epistemology. How can we ever come to know something if knowing requires having good reasons, and reasons can only be good if they are backed by good reasons in turn? The problem has puzzled philosophers ever since antiquity, giving rise to what is often called Agrippa's Trilemma. The current volume approaches the old problem in a provocative and thoroughly contemporary way. Taking seriously the idea that good reasons are (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  3.  12
    Identity and Difference: A Hundred Years of Analytic Philosophy.Jeanne Peijnenburg - 2000 - Metaphilosophy 31 (4):365-381.
    At its origins, analytic philosophy is an interest in language, science, logic, analysis, and a systematic rather than a historical approach to philosophical problems. Early analytic philosophers were famous for making clear conceptual distinctions and for couching them in comprehensible and lucid sentences. It is argued that this situation is changing, that analytic philosophy is turning into its mirror image and is thereby becoming more like the kind of philosophy that it used to oppose.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  4.  98
    The Emergence of Justification.Jeanne Peijnenburg & David Atkinson - 2013 - Philosophical Quarterly 63 (252):546-564.
    A major objection to epistemic infinitism is that it seems to make justification impossible. For if there is an infinite chain of reasons, each receiving its justification from its neighbour, then there is no justification to inherit in the first place. Some have argued that the objection arises from misunderstanding the character of justification. Justification is not something that one reason inherits from another; rather it gradually emerges from the chain as a whole. Nowhere however is it made clear what (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  5. When are thought experiments poor ones?Jeanne Peijnenburg & David Atkinson - 2003 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 34 (2):305-322.
    A characteristic of contemporary analytic philosophy is its ample use of thought experiments. We formulate two features that can lead one to suspect that a given thought experiment is a poor one. Although these features are especially in evidence within the philosophy of mind, they can, surprisingly enough, also be discerned in some celebrated scientific thought experiments. Yet in the latter case the consequences appear to be less disastrous. We conclude that the use of thought experiments is more successful in (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  6.  82
    Lamps, cubes, balls and walls: Zeno problems and solutions.Jeanne Peijnenburg & David Atkinson - 2010 - Philosophical Studies 150 (1):49 - 59.
    Various arguments have been put forward to show that Zeno-like paradoxes are still with us. A particularly interesting one involves a cube composed of colored slabs that geometrically decrease in thickness. We first point out that this argument has already been nullified by Paul Benacerraf. Then we show that nevertheless a further problem remains, one that withstands Benacerraf s critique. We explain that the new problem is isomorphic to two other Zeno-like predicaments: a problem described by Alper and Bridger in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  7. Probabilistic Justification and the Regress Problem.Jeanne Peijnenburg & David Atkinson - 2008 - Studia Logica 89 (3):333-341.
    We discuss two objections that foundationalists have raised against infinite chains of probabilistic justification. We demonstrate that neither of the objections can be maintained.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  8.  34
    Lamps, cubes, balls and walls: Zeno problems and solutions.Jeanne Peijnenburg & David Atkinson - 2010 - Philosophical Studies 150 (1):49-59.
    Various arguments have been put forward to show that Zeno-like paradoxes are still with us. A particularly interesting one involves a cube composed of colored slabs that geometrically decrease in thickness. We first point out that this argument has already been nullified by Paul Benacerraf. Then we show that nevertheless a further problem remains, one that withstands Benacerraf’s critique. We explain that the new problem is isomorphic to two other Zeno-like predicaments: a problem described by Alper and Bridger in 1998 (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  9. Grounds and limits: Reichenbach and foundationalist epistemology.Jeanne Peijnenburg & David Atkinson - 2011 - Synthese 181 (1):113 - 124.
    From 1929 onwards, C. I. Lewis defended the foundationalist claim that judgements of the form 'x is probable' only make sense if one assumes there to be a ground y that is certain (where x and y may be beliefs, propositions, or events). Without this assumption, Lewis argues, the probability of x could not be anything other than zero. Hans Reichenbach repeatedly contested Lewis's idea, calling it "a remnant of rationalism". The last move in this debate was a challenge by (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  10.  42
    Ineffectual Foundations: Reply to Gwiazda: Discussions.Jeanne Peijnenburg - 2010 - Mind 119 (476):1125-1133.
    In an earlier paper I argued that there are cases in which an infinite probabilistic chain can be completed. According to Jeremy Gwiazda, however, I have merely shown that the chain in question can be computed, not that it can be completed. Gwiazda thereby discriminates between two terms that I used as synonyms. In the present paper I discuss to what extent computability and completability can be meaningfully distinguished.
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  11.  94
    The Need for Justification.Jeanne Peijnenburg & David Atkinson - 2014 - Metaphilosophy 45 (2):201-210.
    Some series can go on indefinitely, others cannot, and epistemologists want to know in which class to place epistemic chains. Is it sensible or nonsensical to speak of a proposition or belief that is justified by another proposition or belief, ad infinitum? In large part the answer depends on what we mean by “justification.” Epistemologists have failed to find a definition on which everybody agrees, and some have even advised us to stop looking altogether. In spite of this, the present (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  12. Achilles, the Tortoise, and Colliding Balls.Jeanne Peijnenburg & David Atkinson - 2008 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 25 (3):187 - 201.
    It is widely held that the paradox of Achilles and the Tortoise, introduced by Zeno of Elea around 460 B.C., was solved by mathematical advances in the nineteenth century. The techniques of Weierstrass, Dedekind and Cantor made it clear, according to this view, that Achilles’ difficulty in traversing an infinite number of intervals while trying to catch up with the tortoise does not involve a contradiction, let alone a logical absurdity. Yet ever since the nineteenth century there have been dissidents (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  13.  25
    Probabilistic Justification and the Regress Problem.Jeanne Peijnenburg & David Atkinson - 2008 - Studia Logica 83 (3):333-341.
    We discuss two objections that foundationalists have raised against infinite chains of probabilistic justification. We demonstrate that neither of the objections can be maintained.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  14. Introduction: Women in the History of Analytic Philosophy.Sander Verhaegh & Jeanne Peijnenburg - 2022 - In Jeanne Peijnenburg & Sander Verhaegh (eds.), Women in the History of Analytic Philosophy. Cham: Springer. pp. 1-21.
  15.  61
    Akrasia, dispositions and degrees.Jeanne Peijnenburg - 2000 - Erkenntnis 53 (3):285-308.
    It is argued that the recent revival of theakrasia problem in the philosophy of mind is adirect, albeit unforeseen result of the debate onaction explanation in the philosophy of science. Asolution of the problem is put forward that takesaccount of the intimate links between the problem ofakrasia and this debate. This solution is basedon the idea that beliefs and desires have degrees ofstrength, and it suggests a way of giving a precisemeaning to that idea. Finally, it is pointed out thatthe (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  16.  35
    Translations and theories: On the difference between indeterminacy and underdetermination.Jeanne Peijnenburg & Ronald Hunneman - 2001 - Ratio 14 (1):18–32.
    Despite Quine's recurrent claims to the contrary, the idea is still widespread that indeterminacy of translation is a special case of underdetermination of theories. In this paper we explain how indeterminacy differs from underdetermination, and in what ways such gifted Quine scholars as Gemes and Bergström went astray.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  17. On poor and not so poor thought experiments. A reply to Daniel Cohnitz.Jeanne Peijnenburg & David Atkinson - 2007 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 38 (1):159 - 161.
    We have never entirely agreed with Daniel Cohnitz on the status and rôle of thought experiments. Several years ago, enjoying a splendid lunch together in the city of Ghent, we cheerfully agreed to disagree on the matter; and now that Cohnitz has published his considered opinion of our views, we are glad that we have the opportunity to write a rejoinder and to explicate some of our disagreements. We choose not to deal here with all the issues that Cohnitz raises, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  18.  97
    A case of confusing probability and confirmation.Jeanne Peijnenburg - 2012 - Synthese 184 (1):101-107.
    Tom Stoneham put forward an argument purporting to show that coherentists are, under certain conditions, committed to the conjunction fallacy. Stoneham considers this argument a reductio ad absurdum of any coherence theory of justification. I argue that Stoneham neglects the distinction between degrees of confirmation and degrees of probability. Once the distinction is in place, it becomes clear that no conjunction fallacy has been committed.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  19.  82
    Shaping your own life.Jeanne Peijnenburg - 2006 - Metaphilosophy 37 (2):240–253.
    A distinction is made between imagination in the narrow sense and in the broad sense. Narrow imagination is characterised as the ability to "see" pictures in the mind's eye or to "hear" melodies in the head. Broad imagination is taken to be the faculty of creating, either in the strict sense of making something ex nihilo or in the looser sense of seeing patterns in some data. The article focuses on a particular sort of broad imagination, the kind that has (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  20. Women in the History of Analytic Philosophy.Jeanne Peijnenburg & Sander Verhaegh (eds.) - 2022 - Cham: Springer.
    This book contains a selection of papers from the workshop *Women in the History of Analytic Philosophy* held in October 2019 in Tilburg, the Netherlands. It is the first volume devoted to the role of women in early analytic philosophy. It discusses the ideas of ten female philosophers and covers a period of over a hundred years, beginning with the contribution to the Significs Movement by Victoria, Lady Welby in the second half of the nineteenth century, and ending with Ruth (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  22
    Introduction.Jeanne Peijnenburg & Scott F. Aikin - 2014 - Metaphilosophy 45 (2):139-145.
    This introduction presents selected proceedings of a two-day meeting on the regress problem, sponsored by the Netherlands Organization for Scientific Research (NWO) and hosted by Vanderbilt University in October 2013, along with other submitted essays. Three forms of research on the regress problem are distinguished: metatheoretical, developmental, and critical work.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. Introduction to the Special Issue: Probability, Confirmation and Fallacies.Jeanne Peijnenburg, Branden Fitelson & Igor Douven - 2012 - Synthese 184 (1):1-1.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  78
    An Endless Hierarchy of Probabilities.Jeanne Peijnenburg & David Atkinson - 2012 - American Philosophical Quarterly 49 (3):267-276.
    Suppose q is some proposition, and let P(q) = v0 (1) be the proposition that the probability of q is v0.1 How can one know that (1) is true? One cannot know it for sure, for all that may be asserted is a further probabilistic statement like P(P(q) = v0) = v1, (2) which states that the probability that (1) is true is v1. But the claim (2) is also subject to some further statement of an even higher probability: P(P(P(q) (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24.  53
    Are there mental entities? Some lessons from Hans Reichenbach.Jeanne Peijnenburg - 1999 - Sorites 11 (11):66-81.
    The meaning of mental terms and the status of mental entities are core issues in contemporary philosophy of mind. It is argued that the old Reichenbachian distinction between abstracta and illata might shed new light on these issues. First, it suggests that beliefs, desires and other pro-attitudes that make up the higher mental life are not all equally substantial or real. Second, it conceives the elements of the lower mental life as entities that are inferred from concrete, observable events. As (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25.  55
    Biased Coins: A model for higher-order probabilities.Jeanne Peijnenburg & David Atkinson - 2014 - In Maria Clara Galavotti, Elisabeth Nemeth & Friedrich Stadler (eds.), European Philosophy of Science: Philosophy of Science in Europe and the Vienna Heritage. Springer. pp. 241-248.
    Is it coherent to speak of the probability of a probability, and the probability of a probability of a probability, and so on? We show that it is, in the sense that a regress of higher-order probabilities can lead to convergent sequences that determine all these probabilities. By constructing an implementable model which is based on coin-making machines, we demonstrate the consistency of our regress.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  63
    Crosswords and Coherence.Jeanne Peijnenburg - 2010 - Review of Metaphysics 63 (4):807-820.
    A common objection to coherentism is that it cannot account for truth: it gives us no reason to prefer a true theory over a false one, if both theories are equally coherent. By extending Susan Haack's crossword metaphor, the authors argue that there could be circumstances under which this objection is untenable. Although these circumstances are remote, they are in full accordance with the most ambitious modern theories in physics. Coherence may perhaps be truth conducive.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. Classical, nonclassical and neoclassical intentions.Jeanne Peijnenburg - 2005 - Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 84 (1):217-233.
    Kuipers' model of action explanation is compared, first with that of Anscombe, and then with models in the post-Anscombian tradition. Whereas Kuipers and Anscombe differ on the question of the first-person view, the difference with post-Anscombian writers concerns the so-called intentional statement. Kuipers criticizes the models of both Hempel and von Wright for their lack of an intentional statement. Kuipers' own model seems immune to this criticism, since it contains no less than two intentional statements, a "specific" and an "unspecific" (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  30
    De Faculteit Wijsbegeerte in Groningen.Jeanne Peijnenburg - 2009 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 71 (3):469.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  10
    Formal Proof or Linguistic Process? Beth and Hintikka on Kant’s Use of ‘Analytic’.Jeanne Peijnenburg - 1994 - Kant Studien 85 (2):160-178.
  30.  12
    Hoe zeker is Heisenbergs onzekerheidsprincipe?Jeanne Peijnenburg & David Atkinson - 2021 - Algemeen Nederlands Tijdschrift voor Wijsbegeerte 113 (1):137-156.
    How certain is Heisenberg’s uncertainty principle? Heisenberg’s uncertainty principle is at the heart of the orthodox or Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics. We first sketch the history that led up to the formulation of the principle. Then we recall that there are in fact two uncertainty principles, both dating from 1927, one by Werner Heisenberg and one by Earle Kennard. Finally, we explain that recent work in physics gives reason to believe that the principle of Heisenberg is invalid, while that (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  80
    Infinite regress in decision theory, philosophy of science, and formal epistemology.Jeanne Peijnenburg & Sylvia Wenmackers - 2014 - Synthese 191 (4):627-628.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. Is What 'Is Done Done? O_n Regret and Remorse'.Jeanne Peijnenburg - 2005 - Journal of Mind and Behavior 26 (4):219-226.
    Often, regret implies the wish not to have performed certain actions. In this article I claim that this wish can to some extent be fulfilled: it is possible, in a sense, to influence the character of actions that have already been performed. This possibility arises from combining a first person perspective with an outlook on actions as expressions of tendencies, where tendencies are identified on the basis of a number of actions. The idea is specified within the framework of Carnapian (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Nemen gedane zaken geen keer?: Opmerkingen over spijt.Jeanne Peijnenburg - 2004 - Algemeen Nederlands Tijdschrift voor Wijsbegeerte 96 (2).
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  20
    On the Concept of Discovery. Comments on Gerd Gigerenzer.Jeanne Peijnenburg - 2003 - Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 232:153-158.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  20
    Repliek.Jeanne Peijnenburg - 2015 - Algemeen Nederlands Tijdschrift voor Wijsbegeerte 107 (2):199-211.
    Amsterdam University Press is a leading publisher of academic books, journals and textbooks in the Humanities and Social Sciences. Our aim is to make current research available to scholars, students, innovators, and the general public. AUP stands for scholarly excellence, global presence, and engagement with the international academic community.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  26
    Reichenbach’s philosophy of mind.Jeanne Peijnenburg - 2002 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 10 (3):437 – 453.
  37.  32
    “Till at last there remain nothing”: Hume’s Treatise 1.4.1 in contemporary perspective.Jeanne Peijnenburg & David Atkinson - 2020 - Synthese 197 (8):3305-3323.
    In A Treatise of Human Nature, David Hume presents an argument according to which all knowledge reduces to probability, and all probability reduces to nothing. Many have criticized this argument, while others find nothing wrong with it. In this paper we explain that the argument is invalid as it stands, but for different reasons than have been hitherto acknowledged. Once the argument is repaired, it becomes clear that there is indeed something that reduces to nothing, but it is something other (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  22
    Transmissie, emergentie en fading foundations.Jeanne Peijnenburg - 2015 - Algemeen Nederlands Tijdschrift voor Wijsbegeerte 107 (2):125-146.
    A great deal of Anglo-Saxon epistemology is marked by the controversy between foundationalists and anti-foundationalists. The key question is as to how propositions, or beliefs in propositions, are to be justified. Is our body of knowledge sustained by basic beliefs, as foundationalists claim? Or are there no basic beliefs, and is there only mutual support between the elements of the structure, as the anti-foundationalists maintain? The matter is made especially difficult by the fact that no-one knows what precisely epistemic justification (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  3
    The philosophy faculty in groningen.Jeanne Peijnenburg - 2009 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 71 (3):469-474.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  16
    Confirmation, Empirical Progress and Truth Approximation: Essays in Debate with Theo Kuipers.Roberto Festa, Atocha Aliseda & Jeanne Peijnenburg (eds.) - 2005 - Rodopi.
    Theo AF Kuipers THE THREEFOLD EVALUATION OF THEORIES A SYNOPSIS OF FROM INSTRUMENTALISM TO CONSTRUCTIVE REALISM. ON SOME RELATIONS BETWEEN CONFIRMATION, EMPIRICAL PROGRESS, AND TRUTH APPROXIMATION (2000) ABSTRACT.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  41.  25
    Introduction to the special issue on epistemic justification.Benjamin Bewersdorf & Jeanne Peijnenburg - 2018 - Synthese 195 (9):3735-3735.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. Justification by an Infinity of Conditional Probabilities.David Atkinson & Jeanne Peijnenburg - 2009 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 50 (2):183-193.
    Today it is generally assumed that epistemic justification comes in degrees. The consequences, however, have not been adequately appreciated. In this paper we show that the assumption invalidates some venerable attacks on infinitism: once we accept that epistemic justification is gradual, an infinitist stance makes perfect sense. It is only without the assumption that infinitism runs into difficulties.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  43.  76
    Galileo and prior philosophy.David Atkinson & Jeanne Peijnenburg - 2004 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 35 (1):115-136.
    Galileo claimed inconsistency in the Aristotelian dogma concerning falling bodies and stated that all bodies must fall at the same rate. However, there is an empirical situation where the speeds of falling bodies are proportional to their weights; and even in vacuo all bodies do not fall at the same rate under terrestrial conditions. The reason for the deficiency of Galileo’s reasoning is analyzed, and various physical scenarios are described in which Aristotle’s claim is closer to the truth than is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  44.  18
    A New Condition for Transitivity of Probabilistic Support.David Atkinson & Jeanne Peijnenburg - 2021 - Erkenntnis 88 (1):253-265.
    As is well known, implication is transitive but probabilistic support is not. Eells and Sober, followed by Shogenji, showed that screening off is a sufficient constraint for the transitivity of probabilistic support. Moreover, this screening off condition can be weakened without sacrificing transitivity, as was demonstrated by Suppes and later by Roche. In this paper we introduce an even weaker sufficient condition for the transitivity of probabilistic support, in fact one that can be made as weak as one wishes. We (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  45.  6
    Confirmation, Empirical Progress, and Truth Approximation.Roberto Festa, Atocha Aliseda & Jeanne Peijnenburg (eds.) - 2005 - Rodopi.
    This book is the first of two volumes devoted to the work of Theo Kuipers, a leading Dutch philosopher of science. Philosophers and scientists from all over the world, thirty seven in all, comment on Kuipers' philosophy, and each of their commentaries is followed by a reply from Kuipers. The present volume focuses on Kuipers' views on confirmation, empirical progress, and truth approximation, as laid down in his From Instrumentalism to Constructive Realism (Kluwer, 2000). In this book, Kuipers offered a (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. Confirmation, Empirical Progress and Truth Approximation.Roberto Festa, Atocha Aliseda & Jeanne Peijnenburg (eds.) - 2004 - Rodopi.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47. Cognitive Structures in Scientific Inquiry: Essays in Debate with Theo Kuipers. Volume 2.Roberto Festa, Atocha Aliseda & Jeanne Peijnenburg (eds.) - 2005 - Rodopi.
    This book is the second of two volumes devoted to the work of Theo Kuipers, a leading Dutch philosopher of science. Philosophers and scientists from all over the world, thirty seven in all, comment on Kuipers’ philosophy, and each of their commentaries is followed by a reply from Kuipers. The present volume is devoted to Kuipers’ neo-classical philosophy of science, as laid down in his Structures in Science . Kuipers defends a dialectical interaction between science and philosophy in that he (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. Introduction.Roberto Festa, Atocha Aliseda & Jeanne Peijnenburg - 2005 - Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 83 (1):11-20.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  15
    Screening off generalized: Reichenbach’s legacy.David Atkinson & Jeanne Peijnenburg - 2021 - Synthese 199 (3-4):8335-8354.
    Eells and Sober proved in 1983 that screening off is a sufficient condition for the transitivity of probabilistic causality, and in 2003 Shogenji noted that the same goes for probabilistic support. We start this paper by conjecturing that Hans Reichenbach may have been aware of this fact. Then we consider the work of Suppes and Roche, who demonstrated in 1986 and 2012 respectively that screening off can be generalized, while still being sufficient for transitivity. We point out an interesting difference (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  50.  94
    How to Confirm the Conjunction of Disconfirmed Hypotheses.David Atkinson, Jeanne Peijnenburg & Theo Kuipers - 2009 - Philosophy of Science 76 (1):1-21.
    Can some evidence confirm a conjunction of two hypotheses more than it confirms either of the hypotheses separately? We show that it can, moreover under conditions that are the same for ten different measures of confirmation. Further we demonstrate that it is even possible for the conjunction of two disconfirmed hypotheses to be confirmed by the same evidence.
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
1 — 50 / 933