Results for 'William A. Edmundson'

(not author) ( search as author name )
1000+ found
Order:
  1.  39
    John Rawls: Reticent Socialist.William A. Edmundson - 2017 - New York, NY, USA: Cambridge University Press.
    This book is the first detailed reconstruction of the late work of John Rawls, who was perhaps the most influential philosopher of the twentieth century. Rawls's 1971 treatise, A Theory of Justice, stimulated an outpouring of commentary on 'justice-as-fairness,' his conception of justice for an ideal, self-contained, modern political society. Most of that commentary took Rawls to be defending welfare-state capitalism as found in Western Europe and the United States. Far less attention has been given to Rawls's 2001 book, Justice (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  2. State of the Art: The Duty to Obey the Law.William A. Edmundson - 2004 - Legal Theory 10 (4):215–259.
    Philosophy, despite its typical attitude of detachment and abstraction, has for most of its long history been engaged with the practical and mundane-seeming question of whether there is a duty to obey the law. As Matthew Kramer has recently summarized: “For centuries, political and legal theorists have pondered whether each person is under a general obligation of obedience to the legal norms of the society wherein he or she lives. The obligation at issue in those theorists' discussions is usually taken (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  3.  28
    An Introduction to Rights.William A. Edmundson - 2006 - Cambridge University Press.
    Rights come in various types - human, moral, civil, political and legal - and claims about who has a right, and to what, are often contested. What are rights? Are they timeless and universal, or merely conventional? How are they related to other morally significant values, such as well-being, autonomy, and community? Can animals have rights? Or fetuses? Do we have a right to do as we please so long as we do not harm others? This is the only accessible (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  4. Three Anarchical Fallacies: An Essay on Political Authority.William A. Edmundson - 2000 - Mind 109 (436):896-900.
    How is a legitimate state possible? Obedience, coercion and intrusion are three ideas that seem inseparable from all government and seem to render state authority presumptively illegitimate. This book exposes three fallacies inspired by these ideas and in doing so challenges assumptions shared by liberals, libertarians, cultural conservatives, moderates and Marxists. In three clear and tightly argued essays William Edmundson dispels these fallacies and shows that living in a just state remains a worthy ideal. This is an important (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  5.  21
    Three Anarchical Fallacies: An Essay on Political Authority.William A. Edmundson - 1998 - Cambridge University Press.
    How is a legitimate state possible? Obedience, coercion and intrusion are three ideas that seem inseparable from all government and seem to render state authority presumptively illegitimate. This book exposes three fallacies inspired by these ideas and in doing so challenges assumptions shared by liberals, libertarians, cultural conservatives, moderates and Marxists. In three clear and tightly argued essays William Edmundson dispels these fallacies and shows that living in a just state remains a worthy ideal. This is an important (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  6. Political Authority, Moral Powers and the Intrinsic Value of Obedience.William A. Edmundson - 2010 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 30 (1):179-191.
    Three concepts—authority, obedience and obligation—are central to understanding law and political institutions. The three are also involved in the legitimation of the state: an apology for the state has to make a normative case for the state’s authority, for its right to command obedience, and for the citizen’s obligation to obey the state’s commands. Recent discussions manifest a cumulative scepticism about the apologist’s task. Getting clear about the three concepts is, of..
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  7. Legitimate authority without political obligation.William A. Edmundson - 1998 - Law and Philosophy 17 (1):43 - 60.
    It is commonly supposed that citizens of a reasonably just state have a prima facie duty to obey its laws. In recent years, however, a number of influential political philosophers have concluded that there is no such duty. But how can the state be a legitimate authority if there is no general duty to obey its laws? This article is an attempt to explain how we can make sense of the idea of legitimate political authority without positing the existence of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  8.  95
    Afterword: Proportionality and the difference death makes.William A. Edmundson - 2002 - Criminal Justice Ethics 21 (2):40-43.
    Proponents and opponents of the death penalty both typically assume that punishment, in some form or other, is justified, somehow or other, and that just punishment must in some sense be proportionate to the crime. These shared assumptions turn out to embarrass both parties. Proponents have to explain why certain prima facie proportionate punishments, such as torture, are off the table, while death remains, so to speak, on it. Opponents have to explain why their favored alternatives to capital punishment, such (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9. Is Law Coercive?William A. Edmundson - 1995 - Legal Theory 1 (1):81-111.
    That law is coercive is something we all more or less take for granted. It is an assumption so rooted in our ways of thinking that it is taken as a given of social reality, an uncontroversial datum. Because it is so regarded, it is infrequently stated, and when it is, it is stated without any hint of possible complications or qualifications. I will call this the “prereflective view,” and I want to examine it with the care it deserves.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  10.  69
    What Are “The Means of Production”?William A. Edmundson - 2020 - Journal of Political Philosophy 28 (4):421-437.
    Journal of Political Philosophy, EarlyView.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  11. Because I Said So.William A. Edmundson - 2013 - Problema. Anuario de Filosofía y Teoria Del Derecho 7 (7):41-61.
    Political authority is the moral power to impose moral duties upon a perhaps unwilling citizenry. David Enoch has proposed that authority be understood as a matter of "robust" duty-giving. This paper argues that Enoch's conditions for attempted robust duty- or reason-giving are, along with his non-normative success condition, implausibly strong. Moreover, Enoch's attempt and normative- success conditions ignore two facts. The first is that success requires that citizens be tolerant of modest errors by the authority, which means that, in conditions (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  12.  47
    What Is the Argument for the Fair Value of Political Liberty?William A. Edmundson - 2020 - Social Theory and Practice 46 (3):497-514.
    The equal political liberties are among the basic first-principle liberties in John Rawls’s theory of Justice as fairness. Rawls insists, further, that the “fair value” of the political liberties must be guaranteed. Disavowing an interest in fair value is what disqualifies welfare-state capitalism as a possible realizer of Justice as fairness. Yet Rawls never gives a perspicuous statement of the reasoning in the original position for the fair-value guarantee. This article gathers up two distinct strands of Rawls’s argument, and presents (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  13.  36
    Is Law Coercive?William A. Edmundson - 1995 - Legal Theory 1 (1):81-111.
    That lawiscoercive is something we all more or less take for granted. It is an assumption so rooted in our ways of thinking that it is taken as a given of social reality, an uncontroversial datum. Because it is so regarded, it is infrequently stated, and when it is, it is stated without any hint of possible complications or qualifications. I will call this the “prereflective view,” and I want to examine it with the care it deserves.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  14.  11
    Legitimate Authority Without Political Obligation.William A. Edmundson - 1998 - Law and Philosophy 17 (1):43-60.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  15.  73
    The virtue of law-abidance.William A. Edmundson - 2006 - Philosophers' Imprint 6:1-21.
    The last half-century has seen a steady loss of confidence in the defensibility of a duty to obey the law — even a qualified, pro tanto duty to obey the laws of a just or nearly just state. Over roughly the same period, there has been increasing interest in virtue ethics as an alternative to the dominant consequentialist and deontological approaches to normative ethics. Curiously, these two tendencies have so far only just barely linked up. Although there has been discussion (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  16. Consent and Its Cousins.William A. Edmundson - 2011 - Ethics 121 (2):335-53.
    Consent theories of political obligation draw upon the unique powers consent exhibits in everyday dealings, but they are frustrated by the "problem of massive nonconsent." Expansions of what is counted as consent, such as tacit or hypothetical consent, have seemed untrue to the core concept of giving willing consent. David Estlund proposes a novel conception, "normative consent," to address the problem of massive nonconsent while being true to "the idiom of consent." This comment details consent’s virtues and shows that consent (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  17. Why legal theory is political philosophy.William A. Edmundson - 2013 - Legal Theory 19 (4):331-346.
    The concept of law is not a theorist's invention but one that people use every day. Thus one measure of the adequacy of a theory of law is its degree of fidelity to the concept as it is understood by those who use it. That means as far as possible. There are important truisms about the law that have an evaluative cast. The theorist has either to say what would make those evaluative truisms true or to defend her choice to (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. Do Animals Need Rights?William A. Edmundson - 2014 - Journal of Political Philosophy 22 (2):345-360.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. Distributive Justice and Distributed Obligations.A. Edmundson William - 2018 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 15 (1):1-19.
    _ Source: _Page Count 19 Collectivities can have obligations beyond the aggregate of pre-existing obligations of their members. Certain such collective obligations _distribute_, i.e., become members’ obligations to do their fair share. In _incremental good_ cases, i.e., those in which a member’s fair share would go part way toward fulfilling the collectivity’s obligation, each member has an unconditional obligation to contribute.States are involuntary collectivities that bear moral obligations. Certain states, _democratic legal states_, are collectivities whose obligations can distribute. Many existing (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  13
    Do Animals Need Rights?William A. Edmundson - 2015 - Journal of Political Philosophy 23 (3):345-360.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  21. The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory.Martin P. Golding & William A. Edmundson (eds.) - 2004 - Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.
  22. The Property Question.William A. Edmundson - manuscript
    The “property question” is the constitutional question whether a society’s basic resources are to be publicly or privately owned; that is, whether these basic resources are to be available to private owners, perhaps subject to tax and regulation, or whether instead they are to be retained in joint public ownership, and managed by democratic processes. James Madison’s approach represents a case in which prior holdings are taken for granted, and the property question itself is kept off of the political agenda. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  68
    Charlie Hebdo Meets Utility Monster.William A. Edmundson - forthcoming - The Critique.
    The Charlie Hebdo massacre in January 2015 and the subsequent attacks of November 13 cast a garish light onto a conundrum at the center of how liberal democracies understand themselves. The Syrian emigrant crisis has added further color. How can a tolerant, liberal political culture tolerate the presence of intolerant, illiberal, sub-cultures while remaining true to its principles of tolerance? The problem falls within the intersection of two developments in the thinking of John Rawls, the great American political philosopher who (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24. Ought We to Do What We Ought to Be Made to Do?William A. Edmundson - forthcoming - In Georgios Pavlakos Veronica Rodriguez-Blanco (ed.), Practical Normativity. Essays on Reasons and Intentions in Law and Practical Reason. Cambridge University Press.
    The late Jerry Cohen struggled to reconcile his egalitarian political principles with his personal style of life. His efforts were inconclusive, but instructive. This comment locates the core of Cohen’s discomfort in an abstract principle that connects what we morally ought to be compelled to do and what we have a duty to do anyway. The connection the principle states is more general and much tighter than Cohen and others, e.g. Thomas Nagel, have seen. Our principles of justice always put (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25. Speeding: A Sprawling Offense?William A. Edmundson - 2002 - Fulton County Daily Report 10.
    Urban sprawl and aggressive driving are two problems that afflict many of America’s major cities. The two affect Atlanta to a notoriously high degree. The two problems are connected. Aggressive driving is not so much a symptom of “road rage” as it is an attempt to communicate with slower drivers. The aggressive driver tailgates other drivers with the intention of letting them know that they are impeding the flow of faster traffic. Aggressive drivers are engaged in what “New Chicago School” (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26. Politics in a State of Nature.William A. Edmundson - 2013 - Ratio Juris 26 (2):149-186.
    Aristotle thought we are by nature political animals, but the state-of-nature tradition sees political society not as natural but as an artifice. For this tradition, political society can usefully be conceived as emerging from a pre-political state of nature by the exercise of innate normative powers. Those powers, together with the rest of our native normative endowment, both make possible the construction of the state, and place sharp limits on the state's just powers and prerogatives. A state-of-nature theory has three (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27.  19
    The Choice of a Social System: Reflections on a “property-owning democracy and the difference principle”.William A. Edmundson - forthcoming - Philosophy and Public Issues - Filosofia E Questioni Pubbliche.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. Contextualist Answers to Skepticism, and What a Lawyer Cannot Know.William A. Edmundson - 2002 - Florida State University Law Review 30:1-23.
    Contextualism answers skepticism by proposing a variable standard of justification, keyed to the context of utterance. A lawyer's situation with respect to a criminal defendant's factual guilt is a special one. The argument here is that in this special context an especially high standard of epistemic justification applies. The standard is even more exacting than the proof-beyond-reasonable-doubt standard that juries are sworn to follow. The upshot is that criminal defense lawyers normally cannot know that a client is factually guilt.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  29
    Coercion, Stability, and Indoctrination in the Pejorative Sense.William A. Edmundson - manuscript
    John Rawls argued in A Theory of Justice that “justice as fairness…is likely to have greater stability than the traditional alternatives since it is more in line with the principles of moral psychology”. In support, he presented a psychology of moral development that was informed by a comprehensive liberalism. In Political Liberalism, Rawls confessed that the argument was “unrealistic and must be recast”. Rawls, however, never provided a psychology of moral development informed by a specifically political liberalism, leaving it at (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  28
    Coercion, Stability, and Indoctrination in the Pejorative Sense.William A. Edmundson - 2016 - Jurisprudence 7 (3):540-556.
    John Rawls argued in A Theory of Justice that ‘justice as fairness … is likely to have greater stability than the traditional alternatives since it is more in line with the principles of moral psychology'. In support, he presented a psychology of moral development that was informed by a comprehensive liberalism. In Political Liberalism, Rawls confessed that the argument was 'unrealistic and must be recast'. Rawls, however, never provided a psychology of moral development informed by a specifically political liberalism, leaving (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  77
    Civility as political constraint.William A. Edmundson - 2002 - Res Publica 8 (3):217-229.
    The everyday virtue of civility functions as a constraint upon informal social pressures. Can civility also be understood, as John Rawls has proposed, as a distinctively political constraint? I contrast Rawls's project of constraining the political with Mill's of constraining both the social and the political, and explore Rawls's account of the relation between the two. I argue that Rawls's political duty of civility rests on the assumption that the political is peculiarly coercive; ignores the social enforcement of morality; and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  23
    Comments on coherence theory in the philosophy of law.William A. Edmundson - manuscript
    Coherentism, in philosophy generally, is of either an epistemological or a metaphysical type. The epistemological type responds to worries about foundationalism that have no serious counterpart within the philosophy of law. The metaphysical type is implausible generally, but has been put to use within the philosophy of law - by Ronald Dworkin in particular - to close up "gaps" in the law that provide an opening for purportedly worrisome exercises of judicial discretion. These remarks conclude with the suggestion that the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  25
    Distributive Justice and Distributed Obligations.A. Edmundson William - forthcoming - New Content is Available for Journal of Moral Philosophy.
    _ Source: _Page Count 19 Collectivities can have obligations beyond the aggregate of pre-existing obligations of their members. Certain such collective obligations _distribute_, i.e., become members’ obligations to do their fair share. In _incremental good_ cases, i.e., those in which a member’s fair share would go part way toward fulfilling the collectivity’s obligation, each member has an unconditional obligation to contribute.States are involuntary collectivities that bear moral obligations. Certain states, _democratic legal states_, are collectivities whose obligations can distribute. Many existing (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  51
    First Force.William A. Edmundson - 2006 - Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 1 (3):1-9.
    The state’s very existence seems morally problematic: there may be a justification, but there had better be. A vivid way of putting this is to say that gunmen, and the state as “gunman writ large,” threaten first force, while individuals who make conspicuous their readiness to defend what is theirs threaten not first but second force. But the “No First Force” maxim–originally Kant’s–must be relaxed if any institution of private property is to get off the ground. Property begins not in (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  20
    In Such Ways as Promise Some Success.William A. Edmundson - 2021 - The Harvard Review of Philosophy 28:1-22.
    This year is the centenary of the birth of philosopher John Rawls and the semi-centenary of his monumental A Theory of Justice. This essay explores the differences between political opposition and political resistance as reflected in his work. Rawls is remembered for the careful conditions he imposed in the Vietnam-War era upon justifiable civil disobedience in “nearly just” societies. It is less well known that he came to regard the United States as a fundamentally unjust society. The nation has shown (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  72
    Morality without responsibility.William A. Edmundson - manuscript
    Morality as we know it seems inextricably involved with notions of responsibility, desert, and blame. But a number of philosophers (e.g., Pereboom, G. Strawson) have concluded that responsibility in the desert-supporting sense rests upon metaphysical presuppositions that are unsatisfiable whether or not determinism is true. Some of these philosophers go on to argue that we ought - morally ought - to discard the idea of moral responsibility. Is this proposal coherent? Could morality intelligibly be practiced in a way that dispenses (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37.  48
    Neoliberalism versus distributional autonomy: the skipped step in rawls’s the law of peoples.William A. Edmundson & Matthew R. Schrepfer - 2019 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 49 (2):169-181.
    ABSTRACT: Debates about global distributive justice focus on the gulf between the wealthy North and the impoverished South, rather than on issues arising between liberal democracies. A review of John Rawls’s approach to international justice discloses a step Rawls skipped in his extension of his original-position procedure. The skipped step is where a need for the distributional autonomy of sovereign liberal states reveals itself. Neoliberalism denies the possibility and the desirability of distributional autonomy. A complete Rawlsian account of global justice (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  3
    Privacy.William A. Edmundson - 2004 - In Martin P. Golding & William A. Edmundson (eds.), The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 271–283.
    This chapter contains section titled: Dimensions of Privacy Theories of Privacy Liberty and Decisional Privacy Justifying a Right to Informational Privacy Secrecy and Authority Note References.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  20
    Schauer on precedent in the U.s. Supreme court.William A. Edmundson - 2007 - Georgia State University Law Review 24 (2):403-13.
    Recent critics of the Roberts Court chide it for its lack of regard for precedent. Fred Schauer faults these critics for erroneously assuming that a rule of stare decisis formerly played a significant role in the Supreme Court's decision-making. In fact, it has long played only a rare and weak role in the Court's work. Nonetheless, according to Schauer, the critics are to be thanked for invigorating a needed debate about the importance of "stability, consistency, settlement, reliance, notice, and predictability" (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40.  8
    The Property Question.William A. Edmundson - 2020 - Public Affairs Quarterly 34 (1):1-25.
    The “property question” is the constitutional question of whether a society’s basic resources are to be publicly or privately owned—that is, whether these basic resources are to be available to private owners, perhaps subject to tax and regulation, or are instead to be retained in joint public ownership and managed by democratic processes. James Madison’s approach represents a case in which prior holdings are taken for granted, and the property question itself is kept off of the political agenda. By contrast, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41. Antony Duff, ed., Philosophy and the Criminal Law: Principle and Critique Reviewed by.William A. Edmundson - 1999 - Philosophy in Review 19 (5):325-327.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. Adding reasons up.William A. Edmundson - 2007 - In Barbara Montero & Mark D. White (eds.), Economics and the mind. Routledge.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  57
    Comments on Richard Arneson's “Joel Feinberg and the justification of hard paternalism”.William A. Edmundson - 2005 - Legal Theory 11 (3):285-291.
  44.  3
    Introduction.William A. Edmundson - 2005 - In Martin P. Golding & William A. Edmundson (eds.), The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 1–12.
    This chapter contains section titled: Contending Schools of Thought Doctrinal Domains and their Philosophical Foundations Perennial Topics Continental Perspectivess Methodological Concerns.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. Jaap C. Hage, Reasoning with Rules: An Essay on Legal Reasoning and Its Underlying Logic Reviewed by.William A. Edmundson - 1998 - Philosophy in Review 18 (3):178-179.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. Moral education and the ethics of consent.William A. Edmundson - 2018 - In Peter Schaber & Andreas Müller (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of the Ethics of Consent. Routledge.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. Do Animals Need Citizenship?William A. Edmundson - manuscript
    An ambitious proposal by Sue Donaldson and Will Kymlicka seeks to break out of an impasse that animal-rights advocacy seems to have reached. They divide the animal kingdom into three categories and distribute rights accordingly. Domesticated animals are to be treated as citizens, enjoying the same rights and duties as human citizens (adjusting for relevant differences in ability, just as we do for children and the severely cognitively handicapped). Wild animal species are to be treated as sovereign nations having rights (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. The "Race-of-the-Victim" Effect in Capital Sentencing: McClesky v. Kemp and Underadjustment Bias.William A. Edmundson - 1990 - Jurimetrics 32:125-41.
    This is a critical discussion of the Baldus study of capital sentencing in Georgia. It concludes that the Baldus finding of a "race-of-the-victim" effect is less robust than capital-punishment abolitionists have claimed. But the flaws in the Baldus study should not comfort death-penalty advocates, for they reveal an epistemological barrier to the US Supreme Court's ever being able to satisfy itself both that the sentence reflects particularized consideration of the circumstances and character of the defendant and that it is not (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  43
    Pluralism, Intransitivity, Incoherence.William A. Edmundson - 2009 - In Mark White (ed.), THEORETICAL FOUNDATIONS OF LAW AND ECONOMICS. Cambridge University Press.
    Pluralism is an appealing and now orthodox view of the sources of value. But pluralism has led to well-known difficulties for social-choice theory. Moreover, as Susan Hurley has argued, the difficulties of pluralism go even deeper. In 1954, Kenneth May suggested an intrapersonal analogue to Arrow's Impossibility Theorem. In brief, May showed that an individual's response to a plurality of values will, given certain additional assumptions, lead to intransitive preference orderings. (Daniel Kahneman and others have shown that intransitivity is an (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  63
    Coercion.William A. Edmundson - 2012 - In Andrei Marmor (ed.), Routledge Companion to the Philosophy of Law. Routledge.
    This chapter explains the concept of coercion as it features in recent legal and political philosophical work.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 1000