This category needs an editor. We encourage you to help if you are qualified.
Volunteer, or read more about what this involves.
Related categories
Siblings:
14 found
Search inside:
(import / add options)   Sort by:
  1. David B. Annis (1981). Swain's Causal Theory of Knowledge. Southern Journal of Philosophy 19 (2):149-156.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (7 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  2. Brian Besong (2014). The Prudent Conscience View. International Philosophical Quarterly 54 (2):127-141.
    Moral intuitionism, which claims that some moral seemings are justification-conferring, has become an increasingly popular account in moral epistemology. Defenses of the position have largely focused on the standard account, according to which the justification-conferring power of a moral seeming is determined by its phenomenal credentials alone. Unfortunately, the standard account is a less plausible version of moral intuitionism because it does not take etiology seriously. In this paper, I provide an outline and defense of a non-standard account of moral (...)
    Remove from this list | Direct download (3 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  3. L. S. Carrier (1976). The Causal Theory of Knowledge. Philosophia 6 (2):237-257.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (7 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  4. Christian Coseru (2009). Mind in Indian Buddhist Philosophy. In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Perhaps no other classical philosophical tradition, East or West, offers a more complex and counter-intuitive account of mind and mental phenomena than Buddhism. While Buddhists share with other Indian philosophers the view that the domain of the mental encompasses a set of interrelated faculties and processes, they do not associate mental phenomena with the activity of a substantial, independent, and enduring self or agent. Rather, Buddhist theories of mind center on the doctrine of no-self (Pāli anatta, Skt.[1] anātma), which postulates (...)
    Remove from this list |
    Translate to English
    | Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  5. Francis W. Dauer (1980). Hume's Skeptical Solution and the Causal Theory of Knowledge. Philosophical Review 89 (3):357-378.
  6. D. Goldstick (1972). A Contribution Towards the Development of the Causal Theory of Knowledge. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 50 (3):238-248.
    1 Cf. D. M. Armstrong, A Materialist Theory of Mind (London, 1968), Chapter 9; 'A Causal Theory of Knowledge' by Alvin I. Goldman, The Journal of Philosophy , Vol. LXIV, No. 12, June 22, 1967. A striking parallelism would appear to exist between 'the causal theory of knowledge' and the orthodox Stoic doctrine regarding the kataleptike phantasia . See, for example, Sextus Empiricus, Adversus Mathematicos 7.248 (reprinted in Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta , edited by H. F. A. von Arnim, Leipzig, 1921, (...)
    Remove from this list | Direct download (3 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  7. D. Goldstick (1972). A Contribution Towards the Development of the Causal Theory of Knowledge. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 50 (3):238 – 248.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (4 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  8. Wolfgang Grassl (1981). Knowing That One Knows and the Causal Theory of Knowledge. International Studies in Philosophy 13 (1):43-59.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (4 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  9. A. J. Holland (1977). Can Mannison Avoid a Causal Theory of Knowledge? Philosophical Quarterly 27 (107):158-161.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (5 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  10. Christoph Jäger (2004). Skepticism, Information, and Closure: Dretske's Theory of Knowledge. Erkenntnis 61 (2-3):187 - 201.
    According to Fred Dretskes externalist theory of knowledge a subject knows that p if and only if she believes that p and this belief is caused or causally sustained by the information that p. Another famous feature of Dretskes epistemology is his denial that knowledge is closed under known logical entailment. I argue that, given Dretskes construal of information, he is in fact committed to the view that both information and knowledge are closed under known entailment. This has far-reaching consequences. (...)
    Remove from this list | Direct download (6 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  11. Joshua, The Implication of the Precision of SPRs.
    Remove from this list | Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  12. Neil McDonnell, The Deviance in Deviant Causal Chains.
    Causal theories of action, perception and knowledge are each beset by problems of so-called ‘deviant’ causal chains. For each such theory, counterexamples are formed using odd or co-incidental causal chains to establish that the theory is committed to unpalatable claims about some intentional action, about a case of veridical perception or about the acquisition of genuine knowledge. In this paper I will argue that three well-known examples of a deviant causal chain have something in common: they each violate Yablos proportionality (...)
    Remove from this list | Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  13. Christophe Menant, Sensorimotor Process with Constraint Satisfaction. Grounding of Meaning (2009).
    There is an increasing agreement in the cognitive sciences community that our sensations are closely related to our actions. Our actions impact our sensations from the environment and the knowledge we have of it. Cognition is grounded in sensori-motor coordination. In the perspective of implementing such a performance in artificial systems, there is a need for a model of sensori-motor coordination. We propose here such a model as based on the generation of meaningful information by a system submitted to a (...)
    Remove from this list |
    Translate to English
    | Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  14. Mark Steiner (1973). Platonism and the Causal Theory of Knowledge. Journal of Philosophy 70 (3):57-66.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (5 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation