Related categories
Subcategories:
2957 found
Search inside:
(import / add options)   Sort by:
1 — 50 / 2957
Material to categorize
  1. Joachim Kopper (1958). Die dialektik der gemeinschaft. Kant-Studien 49 (1-4):113-131.
    Remove from this list |
    Translate to English
    | Direct download (3 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
Kant: Metaphysics
See also: Kant: Freedom
  1. Uygar Abaci (2014). Kant's Only Possible Argument and Chignell's Real Harmony. Kantian Review 19 (1):1-25.
    Andrew Chignell recently proposed an original reconstruction of Kant's for the existence of God. Chignell claims that what motivates the of Kant's proof, , is the requirement that the predicates of a really possible thing must be , i.e. compatible in an extra-logical or metaphysical sense. I take issue with Chignell's reconstruction. First, the pre-Critical Kant does not present as a general condition of real possibility. Second, the real harmony requirement is not what motivates the of the proof. Instead, this (...)
    Remove from this list | Direct download (3 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  2. David Landy (2009). Inferentialism and the Transcendental Deduction. Kantian Review 14 (1):1-30.
  3. D. H. Mellor (1998). Transcendental Tense. Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 72 (1):29 - 56.
    [D. H. Mellor] Kant's claim that our knowledge of time is transcendental in his sense, while false of time itself, is true of tenses, i.e. of the locations of events and other temporal entities in McTaggart's A series. This fact can easily, and I think only, be explained by taking time itself to be real but tenseless. /// [J. R. Lucas] Mellor's argument from Kant fails. The difficulties in his first Antinomy are due to topological confusions, not the tensed nature (...)
    Remove from this list | Direct download (4 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
Kant: Space
  1. Lucy Allais (2009). Kant, Non-Conceptual Content and the Representation of Space. Journal of the History of Philosophy 47 (3):pp. 383-413.
  2. Henry E. Allison (1976). The Non-Spatiality of Things in Themselves for Kant. Journal of the History of Philosophy 14 (3):313-321.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (3 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  3. A. Altmann (1988). A Hitherto Unknown Critique of Kant Theory of Time and Space by Eberhard. Kant-Studien 79 (3):329-341.
    Remove from this list |
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  4. Alexander Altmann (1988). Eine bisher unbekannte frühe Kritik Eberhards an Kants Raum-und Zeitlehre. Kant-Studien 79 (3):329-341.
    Remove from this list |
    Translate to English
    |
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  5. Manuel Bächtold (2011). L'espace dans ses dimensions transcendantale et pragmatiste. Kant-Studien 102 (2):145-167.
    This article examines the Kantian thesis of the a priori nature of our knowledge of space. Because it makes the representation of objects possible as external to us and all others, and consequently, as distinct and individualized, space (whatever its structure may be) claims the status as necessary condition and as apriori possibility of all knowledge. However, in the light of various physical, psychological and philosophical considerations, it seems that the particular structure allocated by Kant to space (i.e. uniqueness, infinity, (...)
    Remove from this list |
    Translate to English
    | Direct download (3 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  6. Manuel Baechtold (2011). The Space in its Transcendental and Pragmatist Dimensions. Kant-Studien 102 (2).
    Remove from this list |
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  7. Sorin Baiasu (2011). Space, Time and Mind-Dependence. Kantian Review 16 (2):175-190.
  8. John Tull Baker (1937). Henry More and Kant: A Note to the Second Argument on Space in the Transcendental Aesthetic. Philosophical Review 46 (3):298-306.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (4 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  9. Erik C. Banks (2005). Kant, Herbart and Riemann. Kant-Studien 96 (2):208-234.
    A look at the dynamical concept of space and space-generating processes to be found in Kant, J.F. Herbart and the mathematician Bernhard Riemann's philosophical writings.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (6 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  10. B. Bavink (1927). Raum, Zeit und Kausalität im System des kritischen Realismus. Kant-Studien 32 (1-3):264-272.
    Remove from this list |
    Translate to English
    | Direct download (3 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  11. Sven Bernecker (2012). Kant on Spatial Orientation. European Journal of Philosophy 20 (4):519-533.
    This paper develops a novel interpretation of Kant's argument from incongruent counterparts to the effect that the representations of space and time are intuitions rather than concepts. When properly understood, the argument anticipates the contemporary position whereby the meaning of indexicals cannot be captured by descriptive contents.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (8 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  12. Graham Bird (2013). Reply to Edward Kanterian. Kantian Review 18 (2):289-300.
    The reply to Kanterian offers a rebuttal of his central criticisms. It reaffirms the difference between Kant's arguments in the Aesthetic and at B 148-9; it rejects the alleged error of logic in Fischer's (and my) arguments; and it rejects Kanterian's reading of passages in the Preface (A xx-xxii) and of the Amphiboly. Beyond these specific points Kanterian assumes that Kant's project in the first Critique cannot be understood as a and so begs the question at issue.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (9 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  13. Henny Blomme (forthcoming). Kant et la matière de l'espace. Georg Olms Verlag.
  14. Henny Blomme (2013). Kants Raumbegriff in der Diskussion. Philosophische Rundschau 60 (3):225-239.
    Remove from this list |
    Translate to English
    | Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  15. Henny Blomme (2013). Können wir den ursprünglichen Raum erkennen? In Dieter Hüning, Stefan Klingner & Carsten Olk (eds.), Das Leben der Vernunft. Beiträge zur Philosophie Kants. De Gruyter. 30-39.
    Remove from this list |
    Translate to English
    | Direct download (2 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  16. Luciano Boi (1996). Les géométries non euclidiennes, le problème philosophique de l'espace et la conception transcendantale; Helmholtz et Kant, les néo-kantiens, Einstein, Poincaré et Mach. Kant-Studien 87 (3):257-289.
    Remove from this list |
    Translate to English
    | Direct download (3 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  17. Artur Buchenau (1909). Über den Begriff des Unendlichen und der intelligibeln Ausdehnung bei Malebranche und die Beziehung des letzteren zum Kantischen Raumbegriff. Kant-Studien 14 (1-3):440-467.
    Remove from this list |
    Translate to English
    | Direct download (3 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  18. Jill Vance Buroker (1997). Review: Falkenstein, Kant's Intuitionism: A Commentary on the Transcendental Aesthetic. [REVIEW] Kantian Review 1:162-171.
  19. Jeremy Byrd (2008). A Remark on Kant's Argument From Incongruent Counterparts. British Journal for the History of Philosophy 16 (4):789 – 800.
    I argue that, by the time of his essay "Concerning the Ultimate Ground of the Differentiation of Directions in Space" (1768), Kant had come to question the status of the Principle of Sufficient Reason as a result, at least in part, of his recognition of the existence of incongruent counterparts. Though Kant's argument against absolute space based on the existence of incongruent counterparts has been much discussed in recent years, its importance as a useful benchmark by which to judge the (...)
    Remove from this list | Direct download (4 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  20. Rudolf Carnap (1925). Über die Abhängigkeit der Eigenschaften des Raumes von denen der Zeit. Kant-Studien 30 (1-2):331-345.
    Remove from this list |
    Translate to English
    | Direct download (3 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  21. Martin Carrier (1992). Kant's Relational Theory of Absolute Space. Kant-Studien 83 (4):399-416.
  22. François-Xavier Chenet (1993). Que sont donc l'espace et le temps? Les hypothèses considérées par Kant et la lancinante objection de la «troisième possibilité». Kant-Studien 84 (2):129-153.
    Remove from this list |
    Translate to English
    | Direct download (3 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  23. Éric Dufour & Julien Servois (2005). Le Statut de l'espace esthétique dans la philosophie kantienne. Kant-Studien 96 (2):161-181.
    Remove from this list |
    Translate to English
    | Direct download (3 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  24. Howard Duncan (1983). Review: Buroker, Space and Incongruence: The Origin of Kant's Idealism. [REVIEW] Philosophy of Science 50 (2):346-.
  25. Steven M. Duncan, Mind, Body, Space, and Time.
    In this essay I explore some of the basic elements of consciousness from a substance dualist point of view, incorporating some elements of Kant's Transcendental Analytic into an overall account of the constitution of consciousness.
    Remove from this list |
    Translate to English
    | Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  26. E. J. Engel (2004). Mendelssohn Versus Kant--Early Evidence of a Confrontation with Kant's Doctrine of Time and Space in the Dissertation of 1770. Kant-Studien 95 (3):269-282.
  27. B. Falkenburg (1995). Kant 2nd Antinomy and Physics. Kant-Studien 86 (1):4-25.
  28. Lorne Falkenstein (1989). Kant's Argument for the Non-Spatiotemporality of Things in Themselves. Kant-Studien 80 (1-4):265-283.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (3 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  29. Gregg E. Franzwa (1978). Space and the Schematism. Kant-Studien 69 (1-4):149-159.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (3 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  30. Peter A. French (1973). Multi-Spatial Myths: Kant and the Dreamer. Southern Journal of Philosophy 11 (3):167-174.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (6 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  31. Michael Friedman (1990). Kant on Concepts and Intuitions in the Mathematical Sciences. Synthese 84 (2):213 - 257.
  32. Michael Friedman (1989). Kant on Space, the Understanding, and the Law of Gravitation. The Monist 72 (2):236-284.
  33. Michael Friedman (1985). Kant's Theory of Geometry. Philosophical Review 94 (4):455-506.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (5 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  34. S. P. Fullinwider (1993). Review: Hatfield, The Natural and the Normative. [REVIEW] Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 24 (3):485-491.
  35. W. Gent (1926). Leibnizens Philosophie der Zeit und des Raumes. Kant-Studien 31 (1-3):61-88.
    Remove from this list |
    Translate to English
    | Direct download (3 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  36. B. Gerlach (1998). Who Was the 'Great Man', Who Prepared the Theory of Space of Transcendental Idealism? (Kant, Moses Mendelssohn). Kant-Studien 89 (1):1-34.
  37. Marco Giovanelli (2011). Leibniz, Kant und der moderne symmetriebegriff. Kant-Studien 102 (4):422-454.
    The paper analyses the significance of the modern concept of „symmetry“ for the understanding of the concept of „intuition“ in Kant's philosophy of geometry. A symmetry transformation or automorphism is a structure preserving mapping of the space into itself that leaves all relevant structure intact so that the result is always like the original, in all relevant respects. Hermann Weyl was the first to show that this idea can be drawn on Leibniz's definition of similarity: two figures are similar if (...)
    Remove from this list |
    Translate to English
    | Direct download (3 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  38. Michelle Grier (1993). Illusion and Fallacy in Kant's First Antinomy. Kant-Studien 84:257-82.
    Remove from this list |
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  39. Shahen Hacyan (2006). On the Transcendental Ideality of Space and Time in Modern Physics. Kant-Studien 97 (3):382-395.
    In Newtonian physics, all phenomena take place in absolute space, which is a fixed scenario, and are referred to absolute time, which rules all processes. Motion is governed by a set of basic differential equations, and it is possible, at least in principle, to deduce future events from present initial conditions.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (3 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  40. Carl H. Hamburg (1954). Kant, Cassirer and the Concept of Space. Tulane Studies in Philosophy 3:89-111.
  41. William Harper (1991). Kant on Incongruent Counterparts. In James Van~Cleve & Robert E. Frederick (eds.), The Philosophy of Right and Left. Kluwer. 263--313.
    Consider your right hand and a mirror image duplicate of it. Kant calls such pairs incongruent counterparts. According to him they have the following puzzling features. The relation and situation of the parts of your hand with respect to one another are not sufficient to distinguish it from its mirror duplicate. Nevertheless, there is a spatial difference between the two. Turn and twist them how you will, you cannot make one of them occupy the exact boundaries now occupied by the (...)
    Remove from this list | Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  42. William Harper (1984). Kant on Space, Empirical Realism and the Foundations of Geometry. Topoi 3 (2):143-161.
  43. Peter Herissone-Kelly (2007). The Transcendental Ideality of Space and the Neglected Alternative. Kant-Studien 98 (3):269-282.
    In the Transcendental Aesthetic, Kant famously makes the following startling claim, which we can call the transcendental ideality thesis concerning the nature of space, or, for ease of reference in what follows, simply “TI”.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (3 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  44. Carl Hoefer (2000). Kant's Hands and Earman's Pions: Chirality Arguments for Substantival Space. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 14 (3):237 – 256.
    This paper outlines a new interpretation of an argument of Kant's for the existence of absolute space. The Kant argument, found in a 1768 essay on topology, argues for the existence of Newtonian-Euclidean absolute space on the basis of the existence of incongruous counterparts (such as a left and a right hand, or any asymmetrical object and its mirror-image). The clear, intrinsic difference between a left hand and a right hand, Kant claimed, cannot be understood on a relational view of (...)
    Remove from this list | Direct download (6 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  45. Desmond Hogan (2009). Three Kinds of Rationalism and the Non-Spatiality of Things in Themselves. Journal of the History of Philosophy 47 (3):pp. 355-382.
  46. Pamela H. Huby (1971). Kant or Cantor? That the Universe, If Real, Must Be Finite in Both Space and Time. Philosophy 46 (176):121-.
1 — 50 / 2957