Related categories
Subcategories:
1460 found
Search inside:
(import / add options)   Sort by:
1 — 50 / 1460
Material to categorize
  1. Ferdinando Abbri (1996). Chemical Lectures of HT Scheffer. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 18 (1):135-148.
    Remove from this list |
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  2. Peter Achinstein (1994). Jean Perrin and Molecular Reality. Perspectives on Science 2:396-427.
    Remove from this list |
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  3. G. Adomian (1991). An Analytical Solution of the Stochastic Navier-Stokes System. Foundations of Physics 21 (7):831-843.
    This paper, using the author's decomposition method and recent generalizations, presents algorithms for an analytic solution of the stochastic Navier-Stokes system without linearization, perturbation, discretization, or restrictive assumptions on the nature of stochasticity. The pressure, forces, velocities, and initial/boundary conditions can be stochastic processes and are not limited to white noise. Solutions obtained are physically realistic because of the avoidance of assumptions made purely for mathematical tractability by usual methods. Certain extensions and further generalizations of the decomposition method have provided (...)
    Remove from this list | Direct download (3 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  4. F. M. Akeroyd, D. Baird, T. Benfey, P. Duhem, R. B. King, J. Kovac, J. G. Mcevoy, J. Morrell, R. K. Nesbet & J. L. Ramsey (2000). Authors Index Volume 2. Foundations of Chemistry 2 (265).
    Remove from this list | Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  5. F. Michael Akeroyd (2008). Mechanistic Explanation Versus Deductive-Nomological Explanation. Foundations of Chemistry 10 (1):39-48.
    This paper discusses the important paper by Paul Thagard on the pathway version of mechanistic explanation that is currently used in chemical explanation. The author claims that this method of explanation has a respectable pedigree and can be traced back to the Chemical Revolution in the arguments used by the Lavoisier School in their theoretical duels with Richard Kirwan, the proponent of a revised phlogistonian theory. Kirwan believed that complex chemical reactions could be explained by recourse to affinity tables that (...)
    Remove from this list | Direct download (4 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  6. F. Michael Akeroyd (2000). Reply to Psarros: Popper and Chemistry. [REVIEW] Journal for General Philosophy of Science 31 (1):127-131.
    In this article I reply to criticism of my published work by N. Psarros (Journal for the General Philosophy of Science 28: 297–305,1997). I show that I had already answered the first criticism in my published work and not overlooked his supposed refutation. However I offer a plausible argument which he could have used to strengthen his claim. Psarros cites my work on Hopkins in his opening paragraph, but then makes no further reference to it in the text. I indicated (...)
    Remove from this list | Direct download (7 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  7. F. Michael Akeroyd (2000). Why Was a Fuzzy Model so Successful in Physical Organic Chemistry? Hyle 6 (2):161 - 173.
    This paper examines a facet of the rise of the Hughes-Ingold Theory of Nucleophilic Substitution in Organic Chemistry 1933-1942, arguing that the SN1/SN2 model of reaction mechanism used by Hughes and Ingold is an example of a fuzzy model. Many real world 'Fuzzy Logic' Controlling Devices gave better results compared to classical logic controlling devices in the period 1975-1985. I propose that the adoption of fuzzy principles in the Hughes-Ingold program 1933-1940 led to scientific advance at a time when the (...)
    Remove from this list | Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  8. F. Michael Akeroyd (1997). Conceptual Aspects of Theory Appraisal: Some Biochemical Examples. Hyle 3 (1):95 - 102.
    This paper considers papers on conceptual analysis by Laudan (1981) and Whitt (1989) and relates them to three biochemical episodes: (1) the modern 'biochemical explanation' of acupuncture; (2) the chemio-osmotic hypothesis of oxidative phosphorylation; (3) the theory of the complete digestion of proteins in the gut. The advantages of including philosophical debate in chemical/biochemical undergraduate courses is then discussed.
    Remove from this list | Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  9. Michael Akeroyd (2004). Predictions, Retrodictions and Chemistry: A 20th Century Example. Studia Philosophica 4:26.
    Remove from this list |
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  10. Timothy L. Alborn (1989). Negotiating Notation: Chemical Symbols and British Society, 1831–1835. Annals of Science 46 (5):437-460.
    One of the central debates among British chemists during the 1830s concerned the use of symbols to represent elements and compounds. Chemists such as Edward Turner, who desired to use symbolic notation mainly for practical reasons, eventually succeeded in fending off metaphysical objections to their approach. These objections were voiced both by the philosopher William Whewell, who wished to subordinate the chemists' practical aims to the rigid standard of algebra, and by John Dalton, whose hidebound opposition to abbreviated notation symbolized (...)
    Remove from this list | Direct download (4 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  11. Robert G. W. Anderson (2013). Chemistry Laboratories, and How They Might Be Studied. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 44 (4):669-675.
    Chemistry laboratories, as buildings, have been surprisingly little studied by historians of science; interest has been focused on them more as sites of specific scientific activity, with particular emphasis on the personalities who worked within them. This has overshadowed aspects of laboratories such as their specification, design, construction, fitting-out, adaptation, replacement, status as civic and academic structures, and so on. Systematic study of them would be aided by an agreed taxonomy of laboratory types, according to their purpose, and a scheme (...)
    Remove from this list | Direct download (2 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  12. C. B. Anfinsen (1985). The International Influence of the Carlsberg Laboratory on Protein Chemistry. Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 29 (3 Pt 2):S87 - 9.
    Remove from this list | Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  13. Peter Atkins (2004). Ponderable Matter: Explanation in Chemistry. In John Cornwell (ed.), Explanations: Styles of Explanation in Science. Oxford University Press. 111.
    Remove from this list | Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  14. Minh-Thu Dinh Audouin (2013). The New Challenges of Current Chemical Practices. In Jean-Pierre Llored (ed.), The Philosophy of Chemistry: Practices, Methodologies, and Concepts. Cambridge Scholars Publishing.
    Remove from this list |
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  15. T. B. (2000). Alchemy, Chemistry and the History of Science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 31 (4):711-720.
    Remove from this list | Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  16. Richard F. W. Bader & Chérif F. Matta (2013). Atoms in Molecules as Non-Overlapping, Bounded, Space-Filling Open Quantum Systems. Foundations of Chemistry 15 (3):253-276.
    The quantum theory of atoms in molecules (QTAIM) uses physics to define an atom and its contribution to observable properties in a given system. It does so using the electron density and its flow in a magnetic field, the current density. These are the two fields that Schrödinger said should be used to explain and understand the properties of matter. It is the purpose of this paper to show how QTAIM bridges the conceptual gulf that separates the observations of chemistry (...)
    Remove from this list | Direct download (6 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  17. Davis Baird (1993). Analytical Chemistry and the 'Big' Scientific Instrumentation Revolution. Annals of Science 50 (3):267-290.
    By a close examination of changes in analytical chemistry between the years 1920 and 1950, I document the case that natural science has undergone and continues to undergo a major revolution. The central feature of this transformation is the rise in importance of scientific instrumentation. Prior to 1920, analytical chemists determined the chemical constitution of some unknown by treating it with a series of known compounds and observing the kind of reactions it underwent. After 1950, analytical chemists determined the chemical (...)
    Remove from this list | Direct download (3 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  18. Davis Baird, Eric Scerri & Lee Mcintyre (2005). Introduction: The Invisibility of Chemistry. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 242:3-18.
    Remove from this list |
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  19. Davis Baird & Joachim Schummer (2005). Editorial: Nanotech Challenges, Part 2. Hyle 11 (1):3 - 4.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (4 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  20. Davis Baird & Joachim Schummer (2004). Editorial: Nanotech Challenges, Part 1. Hyle 10 (2):63 - 64.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (4 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  21. Stefania Bandini, Alessandro Mosca & Matteo Palmonari (2007). Model-Based Chemical Compound Formulation. In L. Magnani & P. Li (eds.), Model-Based Reasoning in Science, Technology, and Medicine. Springer. 413--430.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (2 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  22. Diana Kormos Barkan (1994). Simply a Matter of Chemistry? The Nobel Prize for 1920. Perspectives on Science 2 (4):357-395.
    Remove from this list |
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  23. Daniel Barragán (forthcoming). Essentials of Kinetics and Thermodynamics for Understanding Chemical Oscillations. Foundations of Chemistry:1-14.
    This paper presents a numerical study of the reaction A ↔ B in the presence of an intermediate and destabilizing step in its dynamics. After introducing a direct autocatalytic destabilizing process, namely quadratic autocatalysis ) and cubic autocatalysis ), a thermodynamic analysis of the evolution of the reaction in closed and open systems was performed. In addition, the Gibbs free energy, the thermodynamic affinity, and the entropy generation of the overall reaction were evaluated for each of the autocatalytic steps, in (...)
    Remove from this list | Direct download (2 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  24. Aparajito Basu (2006). Chemical Research in India (1876–1918). Annals of Science 52 (6):591-600.
    The first Indian institution for scientific research was founded in 1876. The period 1876–1918 was a time of gestation for Indian chemistry, in which pure research gradually replaced the need-based, result-oriented research formerly promoted by the British regime. This formative period in Indian chemistry came to an end after the First World War and was succeeded by a rapid expansion of chemical research. The educational and political background against which these changes took place, and the influence of European chemistry on (...)
    Remove from this list | Direct download (3 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  25. Juan Bautista Bengoetxea, Oliver Todt & José Luis Luján (2014). Similarity and Representation in Chemical Knowledge Practices. Foundations of Chemistry 16 (3):215-233.
    This paper argues for the theoretical and practical validity of similarity as a useful epistemological tool in scientific knowledge generation, specifically in chemistry. Classical analyses of similarity in philosophy of science do not account for the concept’s practical significance in scientific activities. We recur to examples from chemistry to counter the claim of authors like Quine or Goodman to the effect that similarity must be excluded from scientific practices . In conclusion we argue that more recent conceptualizations of the notion (...)
    Remove from this list | Direct download (2 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  26. Frederick Marsh Bennett (1922). Is Spirit a Chemical Reaction? Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 3 (2):106.
    Remove from this list |
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  27. Jutta Berger (1997). Chemische Mechanik Und Kinetik: Die Bedeutung der Mechanischen Wärmetheorie Für Die Theorie Chemischer Reaktionen. Annals of Science 54 (6):567-584.
    Summary The first systematic studies on the velocity of chemical reactions (now called reaction rates) were published in the 1850s and 1860s. Inquiring about the course of chemical change, their authors established empirical equations on the basis of their measurement results. But these laws, which represented reaction velocities as proportional to the actual concentration of the reagents, could not be given a physical foundation. The chemists themselves regarded their propositions as mere ad hoc hypotheses. In 1867 Leopold Pfaundler formulated a (...)
    Remove from this list | Direct download (3 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  28. S. Bergia, F. Cannata, A. Cornia & R. Livi (1980). On the Actual Measurability of the Density Matrix of a Decaying System by Means of Measurements on the Decay Products. Foundations of Physics 10 (9-10):723-730.
    The density matrix ρ describing a decaying system can be expressed in terms of correlations among observables belonging to the subsystems. Due to this structure and to the difficulties in measuring higher rank tensors of decay products for a single decay event, it is found that the mean value of ρ cannot be determined, in general, from measurements on the decay products. We also discuss the consequences of this conclusion as far as tests of quantum mechanics are concerned.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (3 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  29. José Ramón Bertomeu Sánchez (2004). Book Review: Lavoisier in Italia. [REVIEW] Foundations of Chemistry 6 (2):191-195.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (7 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  30. Nalini Bhushan (2004). Introduction. Foundations of Chemistry 6 (1):3-9.
  31. John E. Bloor & W. H. Eugen Schwarz (2006). Book Review. [REVIEW] Foundations of Chemistry 8 (3):293-303.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (3 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  32. Geoffrey Blumenthal (2013). Kuhn and the Chemical Revolution: A Re-Assessment. [REVIEW] Foundations of Chemistry 15 (1):93-101.
    A recent paper by Hoyningen-Huene argues that the Chemical Revolution is an excellent example of the success of Kuhn’s theory. This paper gives a succinct account of some counter-arguments and briefly refers to some further existing counter-arguments. While Kuhn’s theory does have a small number of more or less successful elements, it has been widely recognised that in general Kuhn’s theory is a “preformed and relatively inflexible framework” (1962, p. 24) which does not fit particular historical examples well; this paper (...)
    Remove from this list | Direct download (8 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  33. Victor Boantza & Ofer Gal (2011). The ‘Absolute Existence’ of Phlogiston: The Losing Party's Point of View. British Journal for the History of Science 44 (3):317-342.
    Long after its alleged demise, phlogiston was still presented, discussed and defended by leading chemists. Even some of the leading proponents of the new chemistry admitted its ‘absolute existence’. We demonstrate that what was defended under the title ‘phlogiston’ was no longer a particular hypothesis about combustion and respiration. Rather, it was a set of ontological and epistemological assumptions and the empirical practices associated with them. Lavoisier's gravimetric reduction, in the eyes of the phlogistians, annihilated the autonomy of chemistry together (...)
    Remove from this list | Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  34. Jan C. A. Boeyens (forthcoming). Wave-Mechanical Model for Chemistry. Foundations of Chemistry:1-16.
    The strength and defects of wave mechanics as a theory of chemistry are critically examined. Without the secondary assumption of wave–particle duality, the seminal equation describes matter waves and leaves the concept of point particles undefined. To bring the formalism into line with the theory of special relativity, it is shown to require reformulation in hypercomplex algebra that imparts a new meaning to electron spin as a holistic spinor, eliminating serious current misconceptions in the process. Reformulation in the curved space–time (...)
    Remove from this list | Direct download (2 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  35. Paul A. Bogaard (1978). The Limitations of Physics as a Chemical Reducing Agent. PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1978:345 - 356.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (2 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  36. Conal Boyce (2014). Using Logic to Define the Aufbau–Hund–Pauli Relation: A Guide to Teaching Orbitals as a Single, Natural, Unfragmented Rule-Set. [REVIEW] Foundations of Chemistry 16 (2):93-106.
    The general chemistry curriculum includes a prelude that consumes nearly all of the first semester and occupies the first third of the typical textbook. This necessary prelude to the main event is comparable in scope to precalculus though not broken out as a formal ‘prechemistry’ course. Atomic orbitals account for much of this prelude-to-chemistry. By tradition, orbital theory is conveyed to the student in three disjunct pieces, presented in the following illogical order: the Pauli principle, the Aufbau principle, and Hund’s (...)
    Remove from this list | Direct download (6 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  37. John Bradley (1955). On the Operational Interpretation of Classical Chemistry. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 6 (21):32-42.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (8 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  38. J. Brakel (1986). The Chemistry of Substances and the Philosophy of Mass Terms. Synthese 69 (3):291 - 324.
  39. Per Bro (1997). Chemical Reaction Automata. Complexity 2 (3):38-44.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (7 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  40. Wh Brock (1990). Essays on Chemical Ideas. History of Science 30 (90):439-442.
    Remove from this list |
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  41. Brown, Thomas Eisner & Robert H. Whittaker (1970). Allomones and Kairomones: Transspecific Chemical Messengers. BioScience 20 (1):21-22.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (2 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  42. Otávio Bueno (2004). The Drexler-Smalley Debate on Nanotechnology: Incommensurability at Work? Hyle 10 (2):83 - 98.
    In a recent debate, Eric Drexler and Richard Smalley have discussed the chemical and physical possibility of constructing molecular assemblers - devices that guide chemical reactions by placing, with atomic precision, reactive molecules. Drexler insisted on the mechanical feasibility of such assemblers, whereas Smalley resisted the idea that such devices could be chemically constructed, because we do not have the required control. Underlying the debate, there are differences regarding the appropriate goals, methods, and theories of nanotechnology, and the appropriate way (...)
    Remove from this list | Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  43. John W. Burbidge (2002). Chemism and Chemistry. The Owl of Minerva 34 (1):3-17.
    In order to answer the debate whether Hegel’s Philosophy of Nature is just an extension of his logic (Halper and Winfield) or combines thought with its other (Maker), this paper considers what Hegel writes about chemism (in the logic) and about chemical process (in the philosophy of nature). The logical argument can be constructed without reference to experience, from paradoxes that emerge within an original concept. In the philosophy of nature, however, an initial concept is analyzed, but its instantiation reflects (...)
    Remove from this list | Direct download (4 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  44. Julia R. Bursten (2012). Pauling's Defence of Bent-Equivalent Bonds: A View of Evolving Explanatory Demands in Modern Chemistry. Annals of Science 69 (1):69-90.
    Summary Linus Pauling played a key role in creating valence-bond theory, one of two competing theories of the chemical bond that appeared in the first half of the 20th century. While the chemical community preferred his theory over molecular-orbital theory for a number of years, valence-bond theory began to fall into disuse during the 1950s. This shift in the chemical community's perception of Pauling's theory motivated Pauling to defend the theory, and he did so in a peculiar way. Rather than (...)
    Remove from this list | Direct download (4 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  45. E. F. Caldin (1959). Theories and the Development of Chemistry. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 10 (39):209-222.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (8 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  46. Ana Carneiro & Natalie Pigeard (1997). Chimistes Alsaciens À Paris au 19ème Siècle: Un Réseau, Une École? Annals of Science 54 (6):533-546.
    Summary During the nineteenth century French chemistry was marked by an outstanding number of Alsation chemists whose scientific contributions cannot be ignored. Especially following the Franco-Prussian War, their regional origin was given a particular importance as a means of affirming their singularity on the French scientific scene. However, some questions may be raised: can we distinguish the Alsatians from other French chemists before 1870? Were they a homogeneous group sharing a common origin? The aim of this article therefore, is, to (...)
    Remove from this list | Direct download (3 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  47. Michael T. Casey (1961). The Structure of Chemistry. Philosophical Studies 11:331-331.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (4 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  48. Michael T. Casey (1958). An Introduction to Chemical Thermodynamics. Philosophical Studies 8:240-240.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (4 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  49. Mauro Causá, Andreas Savin & Bernard Silvi (2014). Atoms and Bonds in Molecules and Chemical Explanations. Foundations of Chemistry 16 (1):3-26.
    The concepts of atoms and bonds in molecules which appeared in chemistry during the nineteenth century are unavoidable to explain the structure and the reactivity of the matter at a chemical level of understanding. Although they can be criticized from a strict reductionist point of view, because neither atoms nor bonds are observable in the sense of quantum mechanics, the topological and statistical interpretative approaches of quantum chemistry (quantum theory of atoms in molecules, electron localization function and maximum probability domain) (...)
    Remove from this list | Direct download (5 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  50. Alan Chalmers (2012). Guest Editorial. Foundations of Chemistry 14 (1):3-6.
    Guest editorial Content Type Journal Article Category Editorial Pages 1-4 DOI 10.1007/s10698-012-9147-z Authors Alan Chalmers, Unit for History and Philosophy of Science, University of Sydney, Sydney, NSW, Australia Journal Foundations of Chemistry Online ISSN 1572-8463 Print ISSN 1386-4238.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (6 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
1 — 50 / 1460