Bookmark and Share

Substance

Edited by Andrew J. Jaeger (University of Nebraska, Lincoln)
Related categories
Siblings:History/traditions: Substance
444 found
Search inside:
(import / add options)   Sort by:
1 — 50 / 444
  1. Robert Merrihew Adams (2002). Review: Substance and Individuation in Leibniz. [REVIEW] Mind 111 (444):851-855.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (5 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  2. Maria S. Aguiar & Carlos Tomaz (1990). Enhanced Habituation Produced by Posttrial Peripheral Injection of Substance P. Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 28 (3):204-206.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (2 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  3. Edwin B. Allaire (1964). The Attack on Substance: Descartes to Hume. Dialogue 3 (03):284-287.
  4. D. J. Allan (1964). Being or Substance? The Classical Review 14 (02):154-.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (2 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  5. R. E. Allen (1973). Substance and Predication in Aristotle's Categories. In Gregory Vlastos, Edward N. Lee, Alexander P. D. Mourelatos & Richard Rorty (eds.), Exegesis and Argument. Assen,van Gorcum. 362--373.
    Remove from this list |
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  6. Robert Ammerman (1965). Our Knowledge of Substance According to Locke. Theoria 31 (1):1-8.
  7. Lucas Angioni (2010). Prioridade e substância na metafísica de Aristóteles. Dois Pontos 7 (3):75-106.
    Pretendo neste artigo analisar as noções de prioridade reconhecidas por Aristóteles e examinar quais são os tipos de prioridade pelos quais ele demarca a primazia da substância em sua metafísica. Tentarei mostrar que a interpretação tradicional, que entende a prioridade ontológica da substância em termos de “existência independente”, não pode ser aceita. Em vez de prioridade em termos de existência, Aristóteles atribui à substância uma prioridade em termos de completude, bem como propõe certo tipo de prioridade causalexplanatória como característica das (...)
    Remove from this list |
    Translate to English
    | Direct download (6 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  8. Julia Annas (1977). Aristotle on Substance, Accident and Plato's Forms. Phronesis 22 (2):146-160.
  9. Elizabeth Anscombe (1989). The Simplicity of the Tractatus. Critica 21 (63):3 - 16.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (3 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  10. G. E. M. Anscombe & S. Körner (1964). Symposium: Substance. Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 38:69 - 90.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (2 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  11. Richard T. W. Arthur (2010). Leibniz: Body, Substance, Monad. British Journal for the History of Philosophy 18 (4):721-724.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (4 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  12. Pierre Aubenque (1999). La Transformation Cartésienne du Concept Aristotélicien de Substance. Enrahonar: Quaderns de Filosofía 1:87.
    Remove from this list | Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  13. M. R. Ayers (1994). The Foundations of Knowledge and the Logic of Substance. In G. A. J. Rogers (ed.), Locke's Philosophy: Content and Context. Oxford University Press. 49--73.
    Remove from this list |
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  14. M. R. Ayers (1975). The Ideas of Power and Substance in Locke's Philosophy. Philosophical Quarterly 25 (98):1-27.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (5 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  15. Michael Ayers (1991). Substance: Prolegomena to a Realist Theory of Identity. Journal of Philosophy 88 (2):69-90.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (5 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  16. Michael R. Ayers (1970). Substance, Reality, and the Great, Dead Philosophers. American Philosophical Quarterly 7 (1):38 - 49.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (3 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  17. Gaston Bachelard (1934). Lumière et substance. Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 41 (3):343 - 366.
    Remove from this list |
    Translate to English
    | Direct download (2 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  18. Jules A. Baisnée (1942). Experience and Substance. New Scholasticism 16 (4):393-399.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (3 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  19. David Bakhurst (2004). Sameness and Substance Renewed by David Wiggins, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001, Pp. XVI + 257. Philosophy 79 (1):133-141.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (7 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  20. Steven Baldner (1990). Substance and Modern Science. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 64 (4):569-571.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (6 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  21. Thomas Baldwin (1982). Sameness and Substance By David Wiggins Oxford: Blackwell, 1980, Xi + 238 Pp., £12.50Objects and Identity By Harold Noonan The Hague: Nijhoff, 1980, Xiv+176 Pp., 60 Guilders. [REVIEW] Philosophy 57 (220):269-.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (2 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  22. Gordon Barnes (2001). Should Property-Dualists Be Substance-Hylomorphists? Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 75:285-299.
    In recent years there has been a resurgence of interest in property dualism—the view that some mental properties are neither identical with, nor strongly supervenient on, physical properties. One of the principal objections to this view is that, according to natural science, the physical world is a causally closed system. So if mental properties are really distinct from physical properties, then it would seem that mental properties never really cause anything that happens in the physical world. Thus, dualism threatens to (...)
    Remove from this list | Direct download (4 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  23. Michael Baur (1996). Heidegger and Aquinas on the Self as Substance. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 70 (3):317-337.
  24. F. J. Beckwith (2004). The Explanatory Power of the Substance View of Persons. Christian Bioethics 10 (1):33-54.
    The purpose of this essay is to offer support for the substance view of persons, the philosophical anthropology defended by Patrick Lee in his essay. In order to accomplish this the author (1) presents a brief definition of the substance view; (2) argues that the substance view has more explanatory power in accounting for why we believe that human persons are intrinsically valuable even when they are not functioning as such (e.g., when one is temporarily comatose), why human persons remain (...)
    Remove from this list | Direct download (9 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  25. Jonathan Beere (2006). Potentiality and the Matter of Composite Substance. Phronesis 51 (4):303-329.
    The paper examines the connection between Aristotle's theory of generated substance and his notion of potentiality in "Metaphysics" Θ.7. Aristotle insists that the matter of a substance is not what that substance is, against a competing view that was widely held both in his day and now. He coined the term thaten (ἐ[unrepresentable symbol]νινονον) in order to make this point. The term highlights a systematic correspondence between the metaphysics of matter and of quality: the relationship between a thing and its (...)
    Remove from this list | Direct download (6 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  26. Jonathan Beere (2006). Potentiality and the Matter of Composite Substance. Phronesis 51 (4):303 - 329.
    The paper examines the connection between Aristotle's theory of generated substance and his notion of potentiality in "Metaphysics" Θ.7. Aristotle insists that the matter of a substance is not what that substance is, against a competing view that was widely held both in his day and now. He coined the term thaten (ἐ[unrepresentable symbol]νινονον) in order to make this point. The term highlights a systematic correspondence between the metaphysics of matter and of quality: the relationship between a thing and its (...)
    Remove from this list | Direct download (7 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  27. Jonathan Bennett (1965). Substance, Reality, and Primary Qualities. American Philosophical Quarterly 2 (January):1-17.
  28. Enrico Berti (2001). Multiplicity and Unity of Being in Aristotle. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 101 (2):185–207.
    I. In analytic philosophy, so-called 'univocalism' is the prevailing interpretation of the meaning of terms such as 'being' or 'existence', i.e. the thesis that these terms have only one meaning (see Russell, White, Quine, van Inwagen). But some analytical philosophers, inspired by Aristotle, maintain that 'being' has many senses (Austin, Ryle). II. Aristotle develops an argument in favour of this last thesis, observing that 'being' and 'one' cannot be a single genus, because they are predicated of their differences (Metaph. B (...)
    Remove from this list | Direct download (8 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  29. D. Bidney (1936). The Problem of Substance in Spinoza and Whitehead. Philosophical Review 45 (6):574-592.
  30. Thomas Bittner & Barry Smith (2001). A Taxonomy of Granular Partitions. In Spatial Information Theory. Foundations of Geographic Information Science. Lecture Notes in Computer Science 2205.
    In this paper we propose a formal theory of partitions (ways of dividing up or sorting or mapping reality) and we show how the theory can be applied in the geospatial domain. We characterize partitions at two levels: as systems of cells (theory A), and in terms of their projective relation to reality (theory B). We lay down conditions of well-formedness for partitions and we define what it means for partitions to project truly onto reality. We continue by classifying well-formed (...)
    Remove from this list |
    Translate to English
    | Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  31. Steven Boër (1985). Substance and Kind: Reflections on New Theory of Reference. In B. K. Matilal & J. L. Shaw (eds.), Analytical Philosophy in Comparative Perspective. D. Reidel. 103-50.
    Remove from this list |
    Translate to English
    |
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  32. Paul A. Bogaard (2006). After Substance: How Aristotle's Question Still Bears on the Philosophy of Chemistry. Philosophy of Science 73 (5):853-863.
    This article will explore whether there are arguments for Aristotle's concept mixis which can aid our current discussions within the philosophy of chemistry. We remain troubled by the way and extent to which chemical substance in bulk can be identified with or reduced to the stability and structure of molecules, and whether these in turn can be identified with or reduced to elemental atoms and the quantum theoretical characterization of their electrons. Aristotle was as determined as we are to think (...)
    Remove from this list | Direct download (4 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  33. Robert Bolton (1995). Science and the Science of Substance in Aristotle's Metaphysics Z. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 76:419-469.
    Remove from this list |
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  34. Alain Boutot (1998). Les théories de la morphogenèse et le dilemme de la substance. Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 2:189-204.
    Remove from this list |
    Translate to English
    | Direct download (3 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  35. Sheilah O'Flynn Brennan (1977). Substance Within Substance. Process Studies 7 (1):14-26.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (4 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  36. Justin Broackes (2006). Substance. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 106 (1):131–166.
    The categorial concepts of substance (thing) and substance (stuff) are described, and the conceptual relationships between things and their constitutive stuff delineated. The relationship between substance concepts, expressed by other count-nouns, and natural kind concepts is examined. Artefacts and their parts are argued to be substances, whereas parts of organisms are not. The confusions of seventeenth- and eighteenth-century philosophers who invoked the concept of substance are adumbrated.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (7 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  37. C. D. Broad (1954). Berkeley's Denial of Material Substance. Philosophical Review 63 (2):155-181.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (5 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  38. C. D. Broad & British Academy (1942). Berkeley's Argument About Material Substance. H. Milford.
    Remove from this list | Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  39. Léon Brunschvicg (1904). La révolution cartésienne et la notion spinoziste de la substance. Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 12 (5):755 - 798.
    Remove from this list |
    Translate to English
    | Direct download (2 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  40. Thomas BuchheimϠϠ (2008). “Dancing Matter” and the Stable Form Remarks on Substance and Form in Aristotle's. Soochow Journal of Philosophical Studies 18:1 - 21.
    Remove from this list | Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  41. Henry R. Burke (1936). Substance and Accident in the Philosophy of Descartes. New Scholasticism 10 (4):338-382.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (3 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  42. David B. Burrell (1972). Substance. Philosophical Studies 21:137-160.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (5 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  43. John Bussanich (1994). Frank A. Lewis, "Substance and Predication in Aristotle". [REVIEW] International Journal of Philosophical Studies 2 (1):158.
    Remove from this list |
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  44. Scott Campbell (2001). Persons and Substances. Philosophical Studies 104 (3):253-67.
    I have argued elsewhere that the psychological criterion of personalidentity entails that a person is not an object, but a series ofpsychological events. As this is somewhat counter-intuitive,I consider whether the psychological theorist can argue that a person, while not a substance, exists in a way that is akin to theway that substances exist. I develop ten criteria that such a`quasi-substance' should meet, and I argue that a reasonablecase can be made to show that the psychological theorist's conception of a (...)
    Remove from this list | Direct download (7 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  45. Chad Carmichael (2013). The Universe As We Find It, by John Heil. [REVIEW] Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2013.
    In this ambitious work, John Heil presents a fundamental ontology (chapters 1-8) consisting of finitely many substances and their properties (which he thinks of as particular, trope-like things), together with an account of causation, truthmaking, and a chapter on relations generally. He then applies this ontology (chapters 9-12) to a number of outstanding problems about reductionism, kinds, essences, emergence, consciousness, cognition, and much else. A final chapter reprises the main points about fundamental ontology from the first chapters.
    Remove from this list | Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  46. Ernst Cassirer (1923/2003). Substance and Function. Dover Publications.
    In this double-volume work, a great modern philosopher propounds a system of thought in which Einstein's theory of relativity represents only the latest (albeit the most radical) fulfillment of the motives inherent to mathematics and the physical sciences. In the course of its exposition, it touches upon such topics as the concept of number, space and time, geometry, and energy; Euclidean and non-Euclidean geometry; traditional logic and scientific method; mechanism and motion; Mayer's methodology of natural science; Richter's definite proportions; relational (...)
    Remove from this list |
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  47. E. Cattanei (1995). The problem of the object of mathematics as an intelligible substance in Aristotle's 'Metafisica'. Rivista di Filosofia Neo-Scolastica 87 (2):199-218.
    Remove from this list |
    Translate to English
    |
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  48. Alan Chalmers (2004). Giving `Substance' to Chemistry. Metascience 13 (1):109-111.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (6 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  49. David Charles (1999). Aristotle on Substance, Essence and Biological Kinds. In Lloyd P. Gerson (ed.), Aristotle: Critical Assessments. Routledge. 2--227.
    Remove from this list | Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  50. Chung-Hwan Chen (1957). Aristotle's Concept of Primary Substance in Books Z and H of the "Metaphysics". Phronesis 2 (1):46 - 59.
    Remove from this list | Direct download (6 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
1 — 50 / 444