Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Is “ethicist” anything to call a philosopher?Richard M. Zaner - 1984 - Human Studies 7 (3-4):71 - 90.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Unfused homunculi.K. V. Wilkes - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):115-116.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Quantum theory and consciousness.David L. Wilson - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):615-616.
  • Extinction and hemi-inattention: Their relation to commissurotomy.Edwin A. Weinstein - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):114-115.
  • Cognitive mapping and algorithmic complexity: Is there a role for quantum processes in the evolution of human consciousness?Ron Wallace - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):614-615.
  • Puccetti's mental-duality thesis: A case of bad arguments.Barbara Von Eckardt - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):113-114.
  • The incompleteness of quantum physics.Euan J. Squires - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):613-614.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Evidence marshaling for imaginative fact investigation.David A. Schum - 2001 - Artificial Intelligence and Law 9 (2-3):165-188.
  • On the relationship between human brain functions and the foundations of physics, science, and technology.Juan G. Roederer - 1978 - Foundations of Physics 8 (5-6):423-438.
    The objective of this paper is to discuss the relationship between the functional properties and information-processing modes of the human brain and the evolution of scientific thought. Science has emerged as a tool to carry out predictive operations that exceed the accuracy, temporal scale, and intrinsic operational limitations of the human brain. Yet the scientific method unavoidably reflects some fundamental characteristics of the information-acquisition and -analysis modes of the brain, which impose a priori boundary conditions upon how science can develop (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Neurometaphorology: The new faculty psychology.Daniel N. Robinson - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):112-113.
  • The case for mental duality: Evidence from split-brain data and other considerations.Roland Puccetti - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):93-123.
    Contrary to received opinion among philosophers, psychologists, and neuroscientists, conscious duality as a principle of brain organization is neither incoherent nor demonstrably false. The present paper begins by reviewing the history of the theory and its anatomical basis and defending it against the claim that it rests upon an arbitrary decision as to what constitutes the biological substratum of mind or person.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   118 citations  
  • Consensus progress in brain science.Roland Puccetti - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):116-123.
  • The realization of mind.Karl H. Pribram - 1971 - Synthese 22 (3-4):313 - 322.
  • The philosophical issue in machine consciousness.Piotr Boltuc - 2009 - International Journal of Machine Consciousness 1 (1):155-176.
    The truly philosophical issue in machine conscioiusness is whether machines can have 'hard consciounsess'. Criteria for hard consciousness are higher than for phenomenal consciousness, since the latter incorporates first-person functional consciousness.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • An emperor still without mind.Roger Penrose - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):616-622.
  • Mental duality: An unmade case.Charles E. Marks - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):111-112.
  • Mental ascriptions and mental unity: Molar subjects, brains, and homunculi.Joseph Margolis - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):110-111.
  • The brain and the split brain: A duel with duality as a model of mind.Joseph E. LeDoux & Michael S. Gazzaniga - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):109-110.
  • Are two heads better than one?Robert J. Joynt - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):108-109.
  • Mind the truth: Penrose's new step in the Gödelian argument.Salvatore Guccione - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):612-613.
  • May we forget our minds for the moment?Michael B. Green - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):107-108.
  • The perverseness of the right hemisphere.Norman Geschwind - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):106-107.
  • Resurrecting logical probability.James Franklin - 2001 - Erkenntnis 55 (2):277-305.
    The logical interpretation of probability, or "objective Bayesianism'' – the theory that (some) probabilities are strictly logical degrees of partial implication – is defended. The main argument against it is that it requires the assignment of prior probabilities, and that any attempt to determine them by symmetry via a "principle of insufficient reason" inevitably leads to paradox. Three replies are advanced: that priors are imprecise or of little weight, so that disagreement about them does not matter, within limits; that it (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Mental dualism and commissurotomy.John C. Eccles - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):105-105.
  • A New Discovery of the Mind?: On John Searle's The Rediscovery of the Mind.D. Dubrovskii - 2007 - Russian Studies in Philosophy 45 (4):43-72.
  • How subtle is Gödel's theorem? More on Roger Penrose.Martin Davis - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):611-612.
  • Cognitive processing is not equivalent to conscious processing.Richard J. Davidson - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):104-105.
  • How many angels…?Patricia Smith Churchland - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):103-104.
  • Structural levels and mental unity.Jason W. Brown - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):102-103.
  • In two minds.John L. Bradshaw - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):101-102.
  • Mental numerosity: Is one head better than two?Joseph E. Bogen - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):100-101.
  • Neurobiology and free will: a dialogue between Mariano Artigas and John Eccles.Javier Bernácer - 2016 - Scientia et Fides 4 (2):437-445.
    In this article, I discuss the importance of multidisciplinary research to tackle the questions that empirical sciences, and in particular neuroscience, ultimately encounter. The last decades have witnessed an enormous progress in brain research, mainly because of the improvement of neuroimaging techniques and neurogenetics, and the development of optogenetics. Furthermore, the US Government and European Union have launched the BRAIN Initiative and Human Brain Project, respectively, to promote a better understanding of brain functioning and its disorders. Unfortunately, their gates appear (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A quantum mechanical mind-body interaction.Ludvik Bass - 1975 - Foundations of Physics 5 (1):159-72.
    The reduction of a quantum mechanical wave function by the entry of a datum into the consciousness of an observer is used, in a semirealistic neurochemical model, to bring about excitation of a nerve cell in that observer's central nervous system. It is suggested that mind can induce muscular movements by choosing to note data originating from specialized elements of the nervous system. Only the freedom to note or not to note a relevant datum is postulated for the observer's mind; (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Sensory suppression and the unity of consciousness.Robert M. Anderson & Joseph F. Gonsalves - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):99-100.
  • Chaos.Robert Bishop - 2015 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    The big news about chaos is supposed to be that the smallest of changes in a system can result in very large differences in that system's behavior. The so-called butterfly effect has become one of the most popular images of chaos. The idea is that the flapping of a butterfly's wings in Argentina could cause a tornado in Texas three weeks later. By contrast, in an identical copy of the world sans the Argentinian butterfly, no such storm would have arisen (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The action of consciousness and the uncertainty principle.Jean E. Burns - 2012 - Journal of Nonlocality 1 (1).
    The term action of consciousness is used to refer to an influence, such as psychokinesis or free will, that produces an effect on matter that is correlated to mental intention, but not completely determined by physical conditions. Such an action could not conserve energy. But in that case, one wonders why, when highly accurate measurements are done, occasions of non-conserved energy (generated perhaps by unconscious PK) are not detected. A possible explanation is that actions of consciousness take place within the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Nonphysical Souls Would Violate Physical Laws.David L. Wilson - 2015 - In Keith Augustine & Michael Martin (eds.), The Myth of an Afterlife: The Case against Life After Death. Rowman & Littlefield. pp. 349-367.
    This paper argues that nonphysical souls would violate fundamental physical laws if they were able to influence brain events. Though we have no idea how nonphysical souls might operate, we know quite a bit about how brains work, so we can consider each of the ways that an external force could interrupt brain processes enough to control one’s body. It concludes that there is no way that a nonphysical soul could interact with the brain—neither by introducing new energy into the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation