Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Primate handedness: Inadequate analysis, invalid conclusions.J. M. Warren - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):288-289.
  • Or in the hand, or in the heart? Alternative routes to lateralization.Stephen Walker - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):288-288.
  • Measurement of Statistical Evidence: Picking Up Where Hacking and Others Left Off.Veronica J. Vieland - 2017 - Philosophy of Science 84 (5):853-865.
    Hacking’s Law of Likelihood says—paraphrasing—that data support hypothesis H1 over hypothesis H2 whenever the likelihood ratio for H1 over H2 exceeds 1. But Hacking later noted a seemingly fatal flaw in the LR itself: it cannot be interpreted as the degree of “evidential significance” across applications. I agree with Hacking about the problem, but I do not believe the condition is incurable. I argue here that the LR can be properly calibrated with respect to the underlying evidence, and I sketch (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Visually guided reaching in adult baboons.Jacques Vauclair & Joël Fagot - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):287-287.
  • A Verisimilitude Framework for Inductive Inference, with an Application to Phylogenetics.Olav B. Vassend - 2018 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 71 (4):1359-1383.
    Bayesianism and likelihoodism are two of the most important frameworks philosophers of science use to analyse scientific methodology. However, both frameworks face a serious objection: much scientific inquiry takes place in highly idealized frameworks where all the hypotheses are known to be false. Yet, both Bayesianism and likelihoodism seem to be based on the assumption that the goal of scientific inquiry is always truth rather than closeness to the truth. Here, I argue in favour of a verisimilitude framework for inductive (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Why the left hand?Michael Tomasello - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):286-287.
  • When Null Hypothesis Significance Testing Is Unsuitable for Research: A Reassessment.Denes Szucs & John P. A. Ioannidis - 2017 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 11.
  • Bentham's Theory of Fictions. A "Curious Double Language".Nomi Maya Stolzenberg - 1999 - Cardozo Studies in Law and Literature 11 (2):223-261.
  • Primate handedness: Reaching and grasping for straws?Horst D. Steklis & Linda F. Marchant - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):284-286.
  • Reichenbach’s cubical universe and the problem of the external world.Elliott Sober - 2011 - Synthese 181 (1):3 - 21.
    This paper is a sympathetic critique of the argument that Reichenbach develops in Chap. 2 of Experience and Prediction for the thesis that sense experience justifies belief in the existence of an external world. After discussing his attack on the positivist theory of meaning, I describe the probability ideas that Reichenbach presents. I argue that Reichenbach begins with an argument grounded in the Law of Likelihood but that he then endorses a different argument that involves prior probabilities. I try to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Likelihood and convergence.Elliott Sober - 1988 - Philosophy of Science 55 (2):228-237.
    A common view among statisticians is that convergence (which statisticians call consistency) is a necessary property of an inference rule or estimator. In this paper, this view is challenged by appeal to an example in which a rule of inference has a likelihood rationale but is not convergent. The example helps clarify the significance of the likelihood concept in statistical inference.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Is Drift a Serious Alternative to Natural Selection as an Explanation of Complex Adaptive Traits?Elliott Sober - 2005 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 56:10-11.
    ‘There are known knowns; there are things we know we know. We also know there are known unknowns; that is to say we know there are some things we do not know. But there are also unknown unknowns—the ones we don’t know we don’t know.’ —Donald Rumsfeld, 2003, President George W. Bush’s Secretary of Defense, on the subject of the U.S. government’s failure to discover weapons of mass destruction in Iraq.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Instrumentalism, parsimony, and the akaike framework.Elliott Sober - 2002 - Proceedings of the Philosophy of Science Association 2002 (3):S112-S123.
    Akaike’s framework for thinking about model selection in terms of the goal of predictive accuracy and his criterion for model selection have important philosophical implications. Scientists often test models whose truth values they already know, and they often decline to reject models that they know full well are false. Instrumentalism helps explain this pervasive feature of scientific practice, and Akaike’s framework helps provide instrumentalism with the epistemology it needs. Akaike’s criterion for model selection also throws light on the role of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Instrumentalism, Parsimony, and the Akaike Framework.Elliott Sober - 2002 - Philosophy of Science 69 (S3):S112-S123.
    Akaike's framework for thinking about model selection in terms of the goal of predictive accuracy and his criterion for model selection have important philosophical implications. Scientists often test models whose truth values they already know, and they often decline to reject models that they know full well are false. Instrumentalism helps explain this pervasive feature of scientific practice, and Akaike's framework helps provide instrumentalism with the epistemology it needs. Akaike's criterion for model selection also throws light on the role of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Common cause explanation.Elliott Sober - 1984 - Philosophy of Science 51 (2):212-241.
    Russell (1948), Reichenbach (1956), and Salmon (1975, 1979) have argued that a fundamental principle of science and common sense is that "matching" events should not be chalked up to coincidence, but should be explained by postulating a common cause. Reichenbach and Salmon provided this intuitive idea with a probabilistic formulation, which Salmon used to argue for a version of scientific realism. Van Fraassen (1980, 1982) showed that the principle, so construed, runs afoul of certain results in quantum mechanics. In this (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Absence of evidence and evidence of absence: evidential transitivity in connection with fossils, fishing, fine-tuning, and firing squads.Elliott Sober - 2009 - Philosophical Studies 143 (1):63-90.
    “Absence of evidence isn’t evidence of absence” is a slogan that is popular among scientists and nonscientists alike. This article assesses its truth by using a probabilistic tool, the Law of Likelihood. Qualitative questions (“Is E evidence about H ?”) and quantitative questions (“How much evidence does E provide about H ?”) are both considered. The article discusses the example of fossil intermediates. If finding a fossil that is phenotypically intermediate between two extant species provides evidence that those species have (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • An Empirical Critique of Two Versions of the Doomsday Argument – Gott's Line and Leslie's Wedge.E. Sober - 2003 - Synthese 135 (3):415-430.
    I discuss two versions of the doomsday argument. According to ``Gott's Line'',the fact that the human race has existed for 200,000 years licences the predictionthat it will last between 5100 and 7.8 million more years. According to ``Leslie'sWedge'', the fact that I currently exist is evidence that increases the plausibilityof the hypothesis that the human race will come to an end sooner rather than later.Both arguments rest on substantive assumptions about the sampling process thatunderlies our observations. These sampling assumptions have (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Propensity theories of probability unscathed: A reply to white.Tom Settle - 1972 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 23 (4):331-335.
  • Collins' core fine-tuning argument.Mark Douglas Saward - 2014 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 76 (2):209-222.
    Collins (The Blackwell companion to natural theology, 2009) presents an argument he calls the ‘core fine-tuning argument’. In this paper, I show that Collins’ argument is flawed in at least two ways. First, the structure, depending on likelihoods, fails to establish anything about the posterior probability of God’s existence given fine-tuning. As an argument for God’s existence, this is a serious failing. Second, his analysis of what is appropriately restricted background knowledge, combined with the credences of a specially chosen ‘alien’, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Conflict between Indexical Credal Transparency and Relevance Confirmation.Joel Pust - 2021 - Philosophy of Science 88 (3):385-397.
    According to the probabilistic relevance account of confirmation, E confirms H relative to background knowledge K just in case P(H/K&E) > P(H/K). This requires an inequality between the rational degree of belief in H determined relative to two bodies of total knowledge which are such that one (K&E) includes the other (K) as a proper part. In this paper, I argue that it is quite plausible that there are no two possible bodies of total knowledge for ideally rational agents meeting (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Deductive Reasoning Under Uncertainty: A Water Tank Analogy.Guy Politzer - 2016 - Erkenntnis 81 (3):479-506.
    This paper describes a cubic water tank equipped with a movable partition receiving various amounts of liquid used to represent joint probability distributions. This device is applied to the investigation of deductive inferences under uncertainty. The analogy is exploited to determine by qualitative reasoning the limits in probability of the conclusion of twenty basic deductive arguments (such as Modus Ponens, And-introduction, Contraposition, etc.) often used as benchmark problems by the various theoretical approaches to reasoning under uncertainty. The probability bounds imposed (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Three conceptions of explaining how possibly—and one reductive account.Johannes Persson - 2009 - In Henk W. de Regt (ed.), Epsa Philosophy of Science: Amsterdam 2009. Springer. pp. 275--286.
    Philosophers of science have often favoured reductive approaches to how-possibly explanation. This article identifies three alternative conceptions making how-possibly explanation an interesting phenomenon in its own right. The first variety approaches “how possibly X?” by showing that X is not epistemically impossible. This can sometimes be achieved by removing misunderstandings concerning the implications of one’s current belief system but involves characteristically a modification of this belief system so that acceptance of X does not result in contradiction. The second variety offers (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Log[p(h/eb)/p(h/b)] is the one true measure of confirmation.Peter Milne - 1996 - Philosophy of Science 63 (1):21-26.
    Plausibly, when we adopt a probabilistic standpoint any measure Cb of the degree to which evidence e confirms hypothesis h relative to background knowledge b should meet these five desiderata: Cb > 0 when P > P < 0 when P < P; Cb = 0 when P = P. Cb is some function of the values P and P assume on the at most sixteen truth-functional combinations of e and h. If P < P and P = P then (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   89 citations  
  • Ontogenetic considerations in the phylogenetic history and adaptive significance of the bias in human handedness.George F. Michel & Debra A. Harkins - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):283-284.
  • On the one hand, on the other hand: Statistical fallacies in laterality research.I. C. McManus - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):282-283.
  • Primate handedness should be considered – but not “reconsidered” at this point.Walter F. McKeever - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):281-282.
  • Severe testing as a basic concept in a neyman–pearson philosophy of induction.Deborah G. Mayo & Aris Spanos - 2006 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 57 (2):323-357.
    Despite the widespread use of key concepts of the Neyman–Pearson (N–P) statistical paradigm—type I and II errors, significance levels, power, confidence levels—they have been the subject of philosophical controversy and debate for over 60 years. Both current and long-standing problems of N–P tests stem from unclarity and confusion, even among N–P adherents, as to how a test's (pre-data) error probabilities are to be used for (post-data) inductive inference as opposed to inductive behavior. We argue that the relevance of error probabilities (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  • Gradualism, natural selection, and the randomness of mutation–fisher, Kimura, and Orr, connecting the dots.Matthew J. Maxwell & Elliott Sober - 2023 - Biology and Philosophy 38 (2):1-22.
    Evolutionary gradualism, the randomness of mutations, and the hypothesis that natural selection exerts a pervasive and substantial influence on evolutionary outcomes are pair-wise logically independent. Can the claims about selection and mutation be used to formulate an argument for gradualism? In his Genetical Theory of Natural Selection, R.A. Fisher made an important start at this project in his famous “geometric argument” by showing that a random mutation that has a smaller effect on two or more phenotypes will have a higher (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Primate predatory, postural, and prehensile proclivities and professional peer pressures: Postscripts.Peter F. MacNeilage, Michael G. Studdert-Kennedy & Bjorn Lindblom - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):289-303.
  • Primate handedness reconsidered.Peter F. MacNeilage, Michael G. Studdert-Kennedy & Bjorn Lindblom - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):247-263.
  • Counting experiments.Jonathan Livengood - 2019 - Philosophical Studies 176 (1):175-195.
    In this paper, I show how one might resist two influential arguments for the Likelihood Principle by appealing to the ontological significance of creative intentions. The first argument for the Likelihood Principle that I consider is the argument from intentions. After clarifying the argument, I show how the key premiss in the argument may be resisted by maintaining that creative intentions sometimes independently matter to what experiments exist. The second argument that I consider is Gandenberger’s :475–503, 2015) rehabilitation of Birnbaum’s (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Statistical bioinformatic methods in microbial genome analysis.Pietro Liò - 2003 - Bioessays 25 (3):266-273.
    It is probable that, increasingly, genome investigations are going to be based on statistical formalization. This review summarizes the state of art and potentiality of using statistics in microbial genome analysis. First, I focus on recent advances in functional genomics, such as finding genes and operons, identifying gene conversion events, detecting DNA replication origins and analysing regulatory sites. Then I describe how to use phylogenetic methods in genome analysis and methods for genome‐wide scanning for positively selected amino acids. I conclude (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Evolution of handedness.Marjorie LeMay - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):281-281.
  • On the other hand ….Ralph A. W. Lehman - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):280-281.
  • Postscript: Bayesian Statistical Inference in Psychology: Comment on Trafimow (2003).Michael D. Lee & Eric-Jan Wagenmakers - 2005 - Psychological Review 112 (3):668-668.
  • Bayesian statistical inference in psychology: Comment on Trafimow (2003).Michael D. Lee & Eric-Jan Wagenmakers - 2005 - Psychological Review 112 (3):662-668.
  • Hypothesis-Testing Demands Trustworthy Data—A Simulation Approach to Inferential Statistics Advocating the Research Program Strategy.Antonia Krefeld-Schwalb, Erich H. Witte & Frank Zenker - 2018 - Frontiers in Psychology 9.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Reaching for the brain.Bryan Kolb & Bryan Fantie - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):279-280.
  • Explanation and Falsification in Phylogenetic Inference: Exercises in Popperian Philosophy.Arnold G. Kluge - 2009 - Acta Biotheoretica 57 (1-2):171-186.
    Deduction leads to causal explanation in phylogenetic inference when the evidence, the systematic character, is conceptualized as a transformation series. Also, the deductive entailment of modus tollens is satisfied when those kinds of events are operationalized as patristic difference. Arguments to the contrary are based largely on the premise that character-states are defined intensionally as objects, in terms of similarity relations. However, such relations leave biologists without epistemological access to the causal explanation and explanatory power of historical statements. Moreover, the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Structured statistical models of inductive reasoning.Charles Kemp & Joshua B. Tenenbaum - 2009 - Psychological Review 116 (1):20-58.
  • Hypothesis tests and confidence intervals in the single case.D. J. Johnstone - 1988 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 39 (3):353-360.
  • Which hand lost its cunning?Harry J. Jerison - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):278-279.
  • Piecewise versus Total Support: How to Deal with Background Information in Likelihood Arguments.Benjamin C. Jantzen - 2014 - Philosophy of Science 81 (3):313-331.
    The use of the Law of Likelihood (LL) as a general tool for assessing rival hypotheses has been criticized for its ambiguous treatment of background information. The LL endorses radically different answers depending on what information is designated as background versus evidence. I argue that once one distinguishes between two questions about evidentiary support, the ambiguity vanishes. I demonstrate this resolution by applying it to a debate over the status of the ‘fine-tuning argument’.
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • How Pseudo-hypotheses Defeat a Non-Bayesian Theory of Evidence: Reply to Bandyopadhyay, Taper, and Brittan.Colin Howson - 2016 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 30 (3):299-306.
    Bandyopadhyay, Taper, and Brittan advance a measure of evidential support that first appeared in the statistical and philosophical literature four decades ago and have been extensively discussed since. I have argued elsewhere, however, that it is vulnerable to a simple counterexample. BTB claim that the counterexample is flawed because it conflates evidence with confirmation. In this reply, I argue that the counterexample stands, and is fatal to their theory.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Does a hand preference indicate a hemispheric specialization?Herbert Heuer - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):277-278.
  • Empirical adequacy.Joseph F. Hanna - 1983 - Philosophy of Science 50 (1):1-34.
    In his book, The Scientific Image, Bas van Fraassen argues for an anti-realist view of science according to which the sole epistemological aim of science is to "save the phenomena". As originally conceived, his constructive empiricism is strongly extensional, but in his account of the empirical adequacy of probabilistic theories, van Fraassen reluctantly abandons this extensional position, arguing that modal (intensional) notions are unavoidable in interpreting probability. I argue in this paper that van Fraassen has not presented the strongest possible (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Likelihood. [REVIEW]Ian Hacking - 1972 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 23 (2):132-137.
  • Precursors to what? Theory is lacking for handedness in humans.Yves Guiard - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):276-277.
  • Two hemispheres: One reaching hand.M. A. Goodale - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):275-276.
  • The riddle of Carlyle: The unsolved problem of the origin of handedness.I. I. Glezer - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):273-275.