Switch to: References

Citations of:

The Senses Considered As Perceptual Systems

Allen & Unwin (1966)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Intentionality, mind and folk psychology.Winand H. Dittrich & Stephen E. G. Lea - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):39-41.
    The comment addresses central issues of a "theory theory" approach as exemplified in Gopnik' and Goldman's BBS-articles. Gopnik, on the one hand, tries to demonstrate that empirical evidence from developmental psychology supports the view of a "theory theory" in which common sense beliefs are constructed to explain ourselves and others. Focusing the informational processing routes possibly involved we would like to argue that his main thesis (e.g. idea of intentionality as a cognitive construct) lacks support at least for two reasons: (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Kant on space, empirical realism and the foundations of geometry.William Harper - 1984 - Topoi 3 (2):143-161.
  • Minds, brains, and programs.John Searle - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):417-57.
    What psychological and philosophical significance should we attach to recent efforts at computer simulations of human cognitive capacities? In answering this question, I find it useful to distinguish what I will call "strong" AI from "weak" or "cautious" AI. According to weak AI, the principal value of the computer in the study of the mind is that it gives us a very powerful tool. For example, it enables us to formulate and test hypotheses in a more rigorous and precise fashion. (...)
    Direct download (14 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1692 citations  
  • Where are we now in the theory of the mind?Rom Harre - 1973 - Philosophical Papers 2 (October):41-51.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the what_ and _how of learning.R. C. Gonzalez & Matthew Yarczower - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):145-145.
  • Contrasting approaches to a theory of learning.Timothy D. Johnston - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):125-139.
    The general process view of learning, which guided research into learning for the first half of this century, has come under attack in recent years from several quarters. One form of criticism has come from proponents of the so-called biological boundaries approach to learning. These theorists have presented a variety of data showing that supposedly general laws of learning may in fact be limited in their applicability to different species and learning tasks, and they argue that the limitations are drawn (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   287 citations  
  • Methodological solipsism considered as a research strategy in cognitive psychology.Jerry A. Fodor - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):63-73.
    The paper explores the distinction between two doctrines, both of which inform theory construction in much of modern cognitive psychology: the representational theory of mind and the computational theory of mind. According to the former, propositional attitudes are to be construed as relations that organisms bear to mental representations. According to the latter, mental processes have access only to formal (nonsemantic) properties of the mental representations over which they are defined.The following claims are defended: (1) That the traditional dispute between (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   668 citations  
  • Methodological solipsism: replies to commentators.J. A. Fodor - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):99-109.
    The paper explores the distinction between two doctrines, both of which inform theory construction in much of modern cognitive psychology: the representational theory of mind and the computational theory of mind. According to the former, propositional attitudes are to be construed as relations that organisms bear to mental representations. According to the latter, mental processes have access only to formal (nonsemantic) properties of the mental representations over which they are defined.The following claims are defended: (1) That the traditional dispute between (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • What (good) are scales of sensation?Lawrence E. Marks - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):199-200.
  • Warren's physical correlate theory: Correlation does not imply causation.Donald D. Dorfman - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):192-193.
    Warren's major contention is that judgments of subjective magnitude are not possible, and therefore subjects base such judgments upon physical correlates of the dimension in question. It would appear that Warren's theory will almost surely fail as a comprehensive model, even though it does provide a heuristic account of judgments of loudness and brightness. In order for the theory to succeed, Warren must specify a physical correlate for judgments ofeverysubjective attribute that has yielded orderly data with Stevens's scaling procedures.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Measurement of sensory intensity.Richard M. Warren - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):175-189.
    The measurement of sensory intensity has had a long history, attracting the attention of investigators from many disciplines including physiology, psychology, physics, mathematics, philosophy, and even chemistry. While there has been a continuing doubt by some that sensation has the properties necessary for measurement, experiments designed to obtain estimates of sensory intensity have found that a general rule applies: Equal stimulus ratios produce equal sensory ratios. Theories concerning the basis for this simple psychophysical rule are discussed, with emphasis given to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   167 citations  
  • Sensation magnitude judgments are based upon estimates of physical magnitudes.Richard M. Warren - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):213-223.
    After writing my response to the commentaries, I sat back and reflected on the fascination and frustration of work on this topic. There is the ancient fascination of trying to understand the nature of the sensory bridge linking us to the external world. Also, discussing the measurability of sensation brings to the surface concepts we use and take for granted when we are working in other areas of psychology; and it holds them before us for critical examination. The frustration lies (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Categories, life, and thinking.Michael T. Ghiselin - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):269-283.
    Classifying is a fundamental operation in the acquisition of knowledge. Taxonomic theory can help students of cognition, evolutionary psychology, ethology, anatomy, and sociobiology to avoid serious mistakes, both practical and theoretical. More positively, it helps in generating hypotheses useful to a wide range of disciplines. Composite wholes, such as species and societies, are “individuals” in the logical sense, and should not be treated as if they were classes. A group of analogous features is a natural kind, but a group of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   185 citations  
  • Talking to yourself about what is where: What is the vocabulary of preattentive vision?Jeremy M. Wolfe - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):254-255.
  • “What” and “where” in spatial language and spatial cognition.Barbara Landau & Ray Jackendoff - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):217-238.
    Fundamental to spatial knowledge in all species are the representations underlying object recognition, object search, and navigation through space. But what sets humans apart from other species is our ability to express spatial experience through language. This target article explores the language ofobjectsandplaces, asking what geometric properties are preserved in the representations underlying object nouns and spatial prepositions in English. Evidence from these two aspects of language suggests there are significant differences in the geometric richness with which objects and places (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   100 citations  
  • Varieties of visual perspectives.David J. Bennett - 2009 - Philosophical Psychology 22 (3):329-352.
    One often hears it said that our visual-perceptual contact with the world is “perspectival.” But this can mean quite different things. Three different senses in which our visual contact with the world is “perspectival” are distinguished. The first involves the detection or representation of behaviorally important relations, holding between a perceiving subject and the world. These include time to contact, body-scaled size, egocentric position, and direction of heading. The second perspective becomes at least explicitly manifest in taking up the “proximal (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Perceptual content and the content of mental imagery.Bence Nanay - 2015 - Philosophical Studies 172 (7):1723-1736.
    The aim of this paper is to argue that the phenomenal similarity between perceiving and visualizing can be explained by the similarity between the structure of the content of these two different mental states. And this puts important constraints on how we should think about perceptual content and the content of mental imagery.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • Magnitude estimation: Why one of Warren's claims is correct.G. E. Zuriff - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):212-213.
  • What are the contributions of the direct perception approach?Carl B. Zuckerman - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):407-408.
  • The computational/representational paradigm as normal science: further support.Steven W. Zucker - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):406-407.
  • Does connectionism suffice?Steven W. Zucker - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (2):301-302.
  • Adaptation and attention.Steven W. Zucker - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):458-458.
  • Human and nonhuman systems are adaptive in a different sense.Tamás Zétényi - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):507-508.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The nature of external representations in problem solving.Jiajie Zhang - 1997 - Cognitive Science 21 (2):179-217.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • Representations in Distributed Cognitive Tasks.Jiaje Zhang & Donald A. Norman - 1994 - Cognitive Science 18 (1):87-122.
    In this article we propose a theoretical framework of distributed representations and a methodology of representational analysis for the study of distributed cognitive tasks—tasks that require the processing of information distributed across the internal mind and the external environment. The basic principle of distributed representations Is that the representational system of a distributed cognitive task is a set of internal and external representations, which together represent the abstract structure of the task. The basic strategy of representational analysis is to decompose (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   66 citations  
  • The psychologist's fallacy.Philip David Zelazo & Douglas Frye - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):89-90.
  • Postural control: A further look at neural control stategies set by boundaries in space.Felix E. Zajac - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):167-167.
  • Intentionality, theoreticity and innateness.Deborah Zaitchik & Jerry Samet - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):87-89.
  • Variability in the measurement of sensory intensity.William A. Yost - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):211-212.
  • The significance of the active pick-up of information in ecological theories of motion perception.Lucy Yardley - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):340-340.
  • Two more proofs of present qualia.Edmond Wright - 1990 - Theoria 56 (1-2):3-22.
    Now in so far as it is recognized that the constituents of the environment are not present inside the body in the same way as they are present outside it, to that extent they are bound, the moment they are inside it, to become something essentially different from the environment.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Three questions for Goldman.Andrew Woodfield - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):86-87.
  • Two categories of content.Andrew Woodfield - 1986 - Mind and Language 1 (4):319-54.
  • Methodological solipsism.Andrew Woodfield - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):98-99.
  • Complexity, guided search, and the data.Jeremy M. Wolfe - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):457-458.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the hierarchy of “reflexes”.Uwe Windhorst - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):625-626.
  • An Ecological Approach to Semiotics.W. Luke Windsor - 2004 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 34 (2):179-198.
    This paper proposes an ecological approach to the perception and interpretation of signs. The theory draws upon the ecological approach of James Gibson . It is proposed that cultural and natural perception can both be explained in terms of the direct pick-up of structured information and the Gibsonian concept of affordances without having to invoke a sharp distinction between direct and indirect perception. The application of the theory is exemplified through attention to language and to the visual and audio arts.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • What is it like to be nonconscious? A defense of Julian Jaynes.Gary Williams - 2011 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 10 (2):217-239.
    I respond to Ned Block’s claim that it is ridiculous to suppose that consciousness is a cultural construction based on language and learned in childhood. Block is wrong to dismiss social constructivist theories of consciousness on account of it being ludicrous that conscious experience is anything but a biological feature of our animal heritage, characterized by sensory experience, evolved over millions of years. By defending social constructivism in terms of both Julian Jaynes’ behaviorism and J.J. Gibson’s ecological psychology, I draw (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The metaphysics of individuality and its consequences for systematic biology.E. O. Wiley - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):302-303.
  • Meaning making and the mind of the externalist.Robert A. Wilson - 2010 - In Richard Menary (ed.), The Extended Mind. MIT Press. pp. 167--188.
    This paper attempts to do two things. First, it recounts the problem of intentionality, as it has typically been conceptualized, and argues that it needs to be reconceptualized in light of the radical form of externalism most commonly referred to as the extended mind thesis. Second, it provides an explicit, novel argument for that thesis, what I call the argument from meaning making, and offers some defense of that argument. This second task occupies the core of the paper, and in (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Embodied Cognition is Not What you Think it is.Andrew D. Wilson & Sabrina Golonka - 2013 - Frontiers in Psychology 4.
  • Computers, cognition and philosophy.Robert Wilensky - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):449-450.
  • A function for sensory storage: perception of rapid change.J. T. Lindsay Wilson - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):42-43.
  • Visual space from the perspective of possible-worlds semantics, I.L. Wiesenthal - 1983 - Synthese 56 (August):199-238.
  • The SMA: A “supplementary motor” or a “supramotor” area?Mario Wiesendanger - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):600-601.
  • Singular Clues to Causality and Their Use in Human Causal Judgment.Peter A. White - 2014 - Cognitive Science 38 (1):38-75.
    It is argued that causal understanding originates in experiences of acting on objects. Such experiences have consistent features that can be used as clues to causal identification and judgment. These are singular clues, meaning that they can be detected in single instances. A catalog of 14 singular clues is proposed. The clues function as heuristics for generating causal judgments under uncertainty and are a pervasive source of bias in causal judgment. More sophisticated clues such as mechanism clues and repeated interventions (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Motion perception: Rights, wrongs and further speculations.Alexander H. Wertheim - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):340-355.
  • Motion perception during selfmotion: The direct versus inferential controversy revisited.Alexander H. Wertheim - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):293-311.
    According to the traditional inferential theory of perception, percepts of object motion or stationarity stem from an evaluation of afferent retinal signals (which encode image motion) with the help of extraretinal signals (which encode eye movements). According to direct perception theory, on the other hand, the percepts derive from retinally conveyed information only. Neither view is compatible with a perceptual phenomenon that occurs during visually induced sensations of ego motion (vection). A modified version of inferential theory yields a model in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Fixations or smooth eye movements?Alexander H. Wertheim - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):281-282.
  • Situated action, symbol systems and universal computation.Andrew Wells - 1996 - Minds and Machines 6 (1):33-46.
    Vera & Simon (1993a) have argued that the theories and methods known as situated action or situativity theory are compatible with the assumptions and methodology of the physical symbol systems hypothesis and do not require a new approach to the study of cognition. When the central criterion of computational universality is added to the loose definition of a symbol system which Vera and Simon provide, it becomes apparent that there are important incompatibilities between the two approaches such that situativity theory (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark