Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. On mechanisms of cultural evolution, and the evolution of language and the common law.Michael T. Ghiselin - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (1):11-11.
  • Epigenesis and culture.Robert Fagen - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (1):10-10.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Nuevo trabajo para una teoría de los universales [segunda parte].Diego Hernán Morales Pérez & David Lewis - 2015 - Ideas Y Valores 64 (158):249-279.
    El texto que se presenta aquí es la segunda parte de la traducción de New Theory of Universalsy se corresponde con las últimas secciones del artículo original. En el anterior número de Ideas y Valores (157 de abril de 2015) se publicó la primera parte, que corresponde a la introducción y las dos primeras secciones del original.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Morality, Reason, and Management Science: The Rationale of Cost-Benefit Analysis.David Copp - 1985 - Social Philosophy and Policy 2 (2):128-151.
    The ProblemEconomic efficiency is naturally thought to be a virtue of social policies and decisions, and cost-benefit (CB) analysis is commonly regarded as a technique for measuring economic efficiency. It is not surprising, then, that CB analysis is so widely used in social policy analysis. However, there is a great deal of controversy about CB analysis, including controversy about its underlying philosophical rationale. The rationales that have been proposed fall into three basic, though not mutually exclusive categories. There aremoralistviews to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Supervenience and anomalous monism: Blackburn on Davidson.Nick Zangwill - 1993 - Philosophical Studies 71 (1):59-79.
    In his paper "Supervenience Revisisted", Simon Blackburn redeployed his novel modal argument against moral realism as an argument against Donald Davidson's position of 'anomalous monism' in the philosophy of mind (Blackburn 1985).' I shall assess this redeployment. In the first part of this paper, I shall lay out Blackburn's argument. In the second and longer part I shall examine Davidson's denial of psychophysical laws in the light of this argument.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Supervenience, reduction, and infinite disjunction.Nick Zangwill - 1998 - Philosophia 26 (1-2):151-164.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Supervenience, reduction, and infinite disjunction.Nick Zangwill - 1995 - Philosophia 24 (3-4):321-30.
    Can a certain sort of property supervene on another sort of property without reducing to it? Many philosophers find the superveniencel irreducibility combination attractive in the philosophy of mind and in moral philosophy. They think that mental properties supervene upon physical properties but do not reduce to them, or that moral properties supervene upon natural properties without reducing to them. Other philosophers have tried to show that the combination is ultimately untenable, however attractive it might initially appear. Thus Ted Honderich (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Supervenience, reduction, and infinite disjunction.Nick Zangwill - 1998 - Philosophia 26 (1-2):321-330.
    Can a certain sort of property supervene on another sort of property without reducing to it? Many philosophers find the superveniencel irreducibility combination attractive in the philosophy of mind and in moral philosophy (Davidson 1980 and Moore 1903). They think that mental properties supervene upon physical properties but do not reduce to them, or that moral properties supervene upon natural properties without reducing to them. Other philosophers have tried to show that the combination is ultimately untenable, however attractive it might (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Mental causation and explanatory exclusion.Sara Worley - 1993 - Erkenntnis 39 (3):333-358.
    Kim argues that we can never have more than one complete and independent explanation for a single event. The existence of both mental and physical explanations for behavior would seem to violate this principle. We can avoid violating it only if we suppose that mental causal relationships supervene on physical causal relationships. I argue that although his solution is attractive in many respects, it will not do as it stands. I propose an alternate understanding of supervenient causation which preserves the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The place of mind, and the limits of amplification.Joachim F. Wohlwill - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (1):30-31.
  • Randomness and perceived-randomness in evolutionary biology.William C. Wimsatt - 1980 - Synthese 43 (2):287 - 329.
  • Two views of realization.Robert A. Wilson - 2001 - Philosophical Studies 104 (1):1-31.
    This paper examines the standard view of realization operative incontemporary philosophy of mind, and proposes an alternative, generalperspective on realization. The standard view can be expressed, insummary form, as the conjunction of two theses, the sufficiency thesis andthe constitutivity thesis. Physicalists of both reductionist and anti-reductionist persuasions share a conception of realization wherebyrealizations are determinative of the properties they realize and physically constitutive of the individuals with those properties. Centralto the alternative view that I explore here is the idea that (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • Genes, mind, and culture; A turning point.Thomas Rhys Williams - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (1):29-30.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Aristotle on how to define a psychological state.Michael V. Wedin - 1996 - Topoi 15 (1):11-24.
  • Content and cause in the aristotelian mind.Michael V. Wedin - 1993 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 31 (S1):49-105.
  • Fitness made physical: The supervenience of biological concepts revisited.Marcel Weber - 1996 - Philosophy of Science 63 (3):411-431.
    The supervenience and multiple realizability of biological properties have been invoked to support a disunified picture of the biological sciences. I argue that supervenience does not capture the relation between fitness and an organism's physical properties. The actual relation is one of causal dependence and is, therefore, amenable to causal explanation. A case from optimality theory is presented and interpreted as a microreductive explanation of fitness difference. Such microreductions can have considerable scope. Implications are discussed for reductive physicalism in evolutionary (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Supervenience and reductionism.Franz von Kutschera - 1992 - Erkenntnis 36 (3):333-343.
  • Primary and secondary qualities: An essay in epistemology. [REVIEW]Gerald Vision - 1982 - Erkenntnis 17 (2):135-170.
    It seems almost a truism to say that colour is a sensation; and yet Young, by honestly recognizing this elementary truth, established the first consistent theory of colour. So far as I know, Thomas Young was the first who, starting from the well-known fact that there are three primary colours, sought for the explanation of this fact, not in the nature of light, but in the constitution of man. (James Clerk Maxwell, p. 267.)It is doubtless scientific to disregard certain aspects (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Resistance to biological self-understanding.Pierre L. van den Berghe - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (1):27-27.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Information, feedback, and transparency.Robert Van Gulick - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (1):27-29.
  • The poor man's guide to supervenience and determination.Paul Teller - 1984 - Southern Journal of Philosophy Supplement 22 (S1):137-62.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • A Poor man's Guide to Supervenience and Determination 1.Paul Teller - 1984 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 22 (S1):137-162.
    I hope to show that supervenience and determination, as I have here intuitively characterized them, are really different expressions of the same core idea which one may make more precise in a great number of different ways, depending on the interpretation one puts on the catchall parameters “cases”, “truth of kind P”and “truth of kind S”.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Intentionality and naturalism.Stephen P. Stich & Stephen Laurence - 1994 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 19 (1):159-82.
    ...the deepest motivation for intentional irrealism derives not from such relatively technical worries about individualism and holism as we.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Deterministic and probabilistic reasons and causes.Wolfgang Spohn - 1983 - Erkenntnis 19 (1-3):371 - 396.
  • Mind and the linkage between genes and culture.John Maynard Smith - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (1):20-21.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A bully pulpit.L. B. Slobodkin - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (1):26-27.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Objective goodness and Aristotle's dilemma.Nicholas Sleigh - 1992 - Journal of Value Inquiry 26 (3):341-351.
  • The Search for Ontological Emergence.Michael Silberstein & John McGeever - 1999 - Philosophical Quarterly 49 (195):201-214.
    We survey and clarify some recent appearances of the term ‘emergence’. We distinguish epistemological emergence, which is merely a limitation of descriptive apparatus, from ontological emergence, which should involve causal features of a whole system not reducible to the properties of its parts, thus implying the failure of part/whole reductionism and of mereological supervenience for that system. Are there actually any plausible cases of the latter among the numerous and various mentions of ‘emergence’ in the recent literature? Quantum mechanics seems (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   86 citations  
  • The dialectic of life.Christopher Shields - 2012 - Synthese 185 (1):103-124.
    In the dialectic of debates about the extension of life, one witnesses a predictably repeating pattern: one side appeals to a motley of variegated criteria for something’s qualifying as a living system, only to find an opposite side taking issue with the individual necessity or collective sufficiency of the proposed criteria. Some of these criteria tend to cluster with one another, while others do not: metabolism, growth and reproduction; self-organization and homeostasis; an ability to decrease internal entropy by the appropriation (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Does externalism entail the anomalism of the mental?Nicholas Shea - 2003 - Philosophical Quarterly 53 (211):201-213.
    In ‘Mental Events’ Donald Davidson argued for the anomalism of the mental on the basis of the operation of incompatible constitutive principles in the mental and physical domains. Many years later, he has suggested that externalism provides further support for the anomalism of the mental. I examine the basis for that claim. The answer to the question in the title will be a qualified ‘Yes’. That is an important result in the metaphysics of mind and an interesting consequence of externalism.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Collaboration between biology and the social sciences: A milestone.Joseph Shepher - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (1):25-26.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • John Searle’s Naturalism as a Hybrid (Property-Substance) Version of Naturalistic Psychophysical Dualism.Dmytro Sepetyi - 2019 - Disputatio 11 (52):23-44.
    The article discusses the relationship between John Searle’s doctrine of naturalism and various forms of materialism and dualism. It is argued that despite Searle’s protestations, his doctrine is not substantially differ- ent from the epiphenomenalistic property dualism, except for the admis- sion, in his later works, of the existence of an irreducible non-Humean self. In particular, his recognition that consciousness is unique in having an irreducible first-person ontology makes his disavowal of property du- alism purely verbalistic. As for epiphenomenalism, Searle’s (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Epigenesis: The newer synthesis?Glendon Schubert - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (1):24-25.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Are there culturgens?Alexander Rosenberg - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (1):22-24.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Swinburne on the Euthyphro Dilemma. Can Supervenience Save Him?Simin Rahimi - 2008 - Forum Philosophicum: International Journal for Philosophy 13 (1):17-29.
    Modern philosophers normally either reject the „divine command theory” of ethics and argue that moral duties are independent of any commands, or make it dependent on God's commands but like Robert Adams modify their theory and identify moral duties in terms of the commands of a loving God. Adams regards this theory as metaphysically necessary. That is, if it is true, it is true in all possible worlds. But Swinburne's position is unprecedented insofar as he regards moral truths as analytically (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Propositional attitudes and psychological explanation.Keith Quillen - 1986 - Mind and Language 1 (2):133-57.
    Propositional attitudes, states like believing, desiring, intending, etc., have played a central role in the articulation of many of our major theories, both in philosophy and the social sciences. Until relatively recently, psychology was a prominent entry on the list of social sciences in which propositional attitudes occupied center stage. In this century, though, behaviorists began to make a self-conscious effort to expunge "mentalistic" notions from their theorizing. Behaviorism has failed. Psychology therefore is again experiencing "formative years," and two themes (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Genes, mind, and emotion.Robert Plutchik - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (1):21-22.
  • New formalism and the aesthetic appreciation of nature.Glenn Parsons & Allen Carlson - 2004 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 62 (4):363–376.
    Recently, several authors have defended a new version of formalism in the aesthetics of nature and attempted to refute earlier arguments against the doctrine. In this essay, we assess this new formalism by reconsidering the force of antiformalist arguments against both traditional formalism and new formalism. While we find that these arguments remain effective against traditional formalism, new formalism falls largely beyond their scope. We therefore provide a novel line of argument for the insignificance of the formal appreciation of nature. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Content, causation, and psychophysical supervenience.Joseph Owens - 1993 - Philosophy of Science 60 (2):242-61.
    There is a growing acceptance of the idea that the explanatory states of folk psychology do not supervene on the physical. Even Fodor (1987) seems to grant as much. He argues, however, that this cannot be true of theoretical psychology. Since theoretical psychology offers causal explanations, its explanatory states must be taxonomized in such a way as to supervene on the physical. I use this concession to invert his argument and cast doubt on the received model of folk psychological explanation (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Resplicing properties in the supervenience base.Graham Oddie & Pavel Tichý - 1990 - Philosophical Studies 58 (3):259-69.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Supervenience, goodness, and higher-order universals.Graham Oddie - 1991 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 69 (1):20 – 47.
    Supervenience theses promise ontological economy without reducibility. The problem is that they face a dilemma: either the relation of supervenience entails reducibility or it is mysterious. Recently higher-order universals have been invoked to avoid the dilemma. This article develops a higher-order framework in which this claim can be assessed. It is shown that reducibility can be avoided, but only at the cost of a rather radical metaphysical proposal.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Reduction, Supervenience, and the Autonomy of Social Scientific Laws.Lee C. McIntyre - 2000 - Theory and Decision 48 (2):101-122.
    Many have felt that it is impossible to defend autonomous laws of social science: where the regularities upheld are law-like it is argued that they are not at base social scientific, and where the phenomena to be explained would seem to require social descriptions, it is argued that laws governing the phenomena are unavailable at that level. But is it possible to develop an ontology that supports the dependence of the social on the physical, while nonetheless supporting the explanatory power (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Toward a natural science of human culture.Roger D. Masters - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (1):19-20.
  • The power of reduction and the limits of compressibility.Hubert Markl - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (1):18-19.
  • Mario Bunge (1919–2020): Conjoining Philosophy of Science and Scientific Philosophy.Martin Mahner - 2021 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 52 (1):3-23.
    The leitmotif of Mario Bunge’s work was that the philosophy of science should be informed by a comprehensive scientific philosophy, and vice versa; with both firmly rooted in realism and materialism. Now Bunge left such a big oeuvre, comprising more than 70 books and hundreds of articles, that it is impossible to review it in its entirety. In addition to biographical remarks, this obituary will therefore restrict itself to some select issues of his philosophy: his scientific metaphysics, his philosophy of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Précis of Genes, Mind, and Culture.Charles J. Lumsden & Edward O. Wilson - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (1):1-7.
    Despite its importance, the linkage between genetic and cultural evolution has until now been little explored. An understanding of this linkage is needed to extend evolutionary theory so that it can deal for the first time with the phenomena of mind and human social history. We characterize the process of gene-culture coevolution, in which culture is shaped by biological imperatives while biological traits are simultaneously altered by genetic evolution in response to cultural history. A case is made from both theory (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Genes and culture, protest and communication.Charles J. Lumsden & Edward O. Wilson - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (1):31-37.
    Despite its importance, the linkage between genetic and cultural evolution has until now been little explored. An understanding of this linkage is needed to extend evolutionary theory so that it can deal for the first time with the phenomena of mind and human social history. We characterize the process of gene-culture coevolution, in which culture is shaped by biological imperatives while biological traits are simultaneously altered by genetic evolution in response to cultural history. A case is made from both theory (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Top-down guidance from a bottom-up theory.Geoffrey R. Loftus - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (1):17-18.
  • Note on Supervenience and Definability.Lloyd Humberstone - 1998 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 39 (2):243-252.
    The idea of a property's being supervenient on a class of properties is familiar from much philosophical literature. We give this idea a linguistic turn by converting it into the idea of a predicate symbol's being supervenient on a set of predicate symbols relative to a (first order) theory. What this means is that according to the theory, any individuals differing in respect to whether the given predicate applies to them also differ in respect to the application of at least (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Supervenience and reductionism.Franz Kutschera - 1992 - Erkenntnis 36 (3):333-343.
    The aim of the paper is to show that claims of supervenience of the mental upon the physical do not define substantial forms of materialism. While weak supervenience holds trivially, even strong supervenience does not justify a claim of identity, dependence or determination; it is only a relation between classifications of persons by psychological and physical properties.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations