Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Herbrandized modified realizability.Gilda Ferreira & Paulo Firmino - forthcoming - Archive for Mathematical Logic:1-19.
    Realizability notions in mathematical logic have a long history, which can be traced back to the work of Stephen Kleene in the 1940s, aimed at exploring the foundations of intuitionistic logic. Kleene’s initial realizability laid the ground for more sophisticated notions such as Kreisel’s modified realizability and various modern approaches. In this context, our work aligns with the lineage of realizability strategies that emphasize the accumulation, rather than the propagation of precise witnesses. In this paper, we introduce a new notion (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Constructivity and Computability in Historical and Philosophical Perspective.Jacques Dubucs & Michel Bourdeau (eds.) - 2014 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer.
    Ranging from Alan Turing’s seminal 1936 paper to the latest work on Kolmogorov complexity and linear logic, this comprehensive new work clarifies the relationship between computability on the one hand and constructivity on the other. The authors argue that even though constructivists have largely shed Brouwer’s solipsistic attitude to logic, there remain points of disagreement to this day. Focusing on the growing pains computability experienced as it was forced to address the demands of rapidly expanding applications, the content maps the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Gödel's functional interpretation and its use in current mathematics.Ulrich Kohlenbach - 2008 - Dialectica 62 (2):223–267.
  • Gödel's Functional Interpretation and its Use in Current Mathematics.Ulrich Kohlenbach - 2008 - Dialectica 62 (2):223-267.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Dag Prawitz on Proofs and Meaning.Heinrich Wansing (ed.) - 2014 - Cham, Switzerland: Springer.
    This volume is dedicated to Prof. Dag Prawitz and his outstanding contributions to philosophical and mathematical logic. Prawitz's eminent contributions to structural proof theory, or general proof theory, as he calls it, and inference-based meaning theories have been extremely influential in the development of modern proof theory and anti-realistic semantics. In particular, Prawitz is the main author on natural deduction in addition to Gerhard Gentzen, who defined natural deduction in his PhD thesis published in 1934. The book opens with an (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The absorption law: Or: how to Kreisel a Hilbert–Bernays–Löb.Albert Visser - 2020 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 60 (3-4):441-468.
    In this paper, we show how to construct for a given consistent theory U a $$\varSigma ^0_1$$ Σ 1 0 -predicate that both satisfies the Löb Conditions and the Kreisel Condition—even if U is unsound. We do this in such a way that U itself can verify satisfaction of an internal version of the Kreisel Condition.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A realizability interpretation for classical analysis.Henry Towsner - 2004 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 43 (7):891-900.
    We present a realizability interpretation for classical analysis–an association of a term to every proof so that the terms assigned to existential formulas represent witnesses to the truth of that formula. For classical proofs of Π2 sentences ∀x∃yA(x,y), this provides a recursive type 1 function which computes the function given by f(x)=y iff y is the least number such that A(x,y).
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Gödel’s second incompleteness theorem: How it is derived and what it delivers.Saeed Salehi - 2020 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 26 (3-4):241-256.
    The proofs of Gödel (1931), Rosser (1936), Kleene (first 1936 and second 1950), Chaitin (1970), and Boolos (1989) for the first incompleteness theorem are compared with each other, especially from the viewpoint of the second incompleteness theorem. It is shown that Gödel’s (first incompleteness theorem) and Kleene’s first theorems are equivalent with the second incompleteness theorem, Rosser’s and Kleene’s second theorems do deliver the second incompleteness theorem, and Boolos’ theorem is derived from the second incompleteness theorem in the standard way. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Unifying Functional Interpretations.Paulo Oliva - 2006 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 47 (2):263-290.
    This article presents a parametrized functional interpretation. Depending on the choice of two parameters one obtains well-known functional interpretations such as Gödel's Dialectica interpretation, Diller-Nahm's variant of the Dialectica interpretation, Kohlenbach's monotone interpretations, Kreisel's modified realizability, and Stein's family of functional interpretations. A functional interpretation consists of a formula interpretation and a soundness proof. I show that all these interpretations differ only on two design choices: first, on the number of counterexamples for A which became witnesses for ¬A when defining (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Should pluralists be pluralists about pluralism?Robert Passmann - 2021 - Synthese 199 (5-6):12663-12682.
    How many correct logics are there? Monists endorse that there is one, pluralists argue for many, and nihilists claim that there are none. Reasoning about these views requires a logic. That is the meta-logic. It turns out that there are some meta-logical challenges specifically for the pluralists. I will argue that these depend on an implicitly assumed absoluteness of correct logic. Pluralists can solve the challenges by giving up on this absoluteness and instead adopt contextualism about correct logic. This contextualism (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Reflexive Intermediate Propositional Logics.Nathan C. Carter - 2006 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 47 (1):39-62.
    Which intermediate propositional logics can prove their own completeness? I call a logic reflexive if a second-order metatheory of arithmetic created from the logic is sufficient to prove the completeness of the original logic. Given the collection of intermediate propositional logics, I prove that the reflexive logics are exactly those that are at least as strong as testability logic, that is, intuitionistic logic plus the scheme $\neg φ ∨ \neg\neg φ. I show that this result holds regardless of whether Tarskian (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The coherence of antirealism.Charles McCarty - 2006 - Mind 115 (460):947-956.
    The project of antirealism is to construct an assertibility semantics on which (1) the truth of statements obeys a recognition condition so that (2) counterexamples are forthcoming to the law of the excluded third and (3) intuitionistic formal predicate logic is provably sound and complete with respect to the associated notion of validity. Using principles of intuitionistic mathematics and employing only intuitionistically correct inferences, we show that prima facie reasonable formulations of (1), (2), and (3) are inconsistent. Therefore, it should (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Skolem's paradox and constructivism.Charles McCarty & Neil Tennant - 1987 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 16 (2):165 - 202.
  • Constructions and negationless logic.E. G. K. López-Escobar - 1972 - Studia Logica 30 (1):7 - 22.
  • On Guaspari's problem about partially conservative sentences.Taishi Kurahashi, Yuya Okawa, V. Yu Shavrukov & Albert Visser - 2022 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 173 (5):103087.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Relative constructivity.Ulrich Kohlenbach - 1998 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 63 (4):1218-1238.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Continuation-passing style models complete for intuitionistic logic.Danko Ilik - 2013 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 164 (6):651-662.
    A class of models is presented, in the form of continuation monads polymorphic for first-order individuals, that is sound and complete for minimal intuitionistic predicate logic . The proofs of soundness and completeness are constructive and the computational content of their composition is, in particular, a β-normalisation-by-evaluation program for simply typed lambda calculus with sum types. Although the inspiration comes from Danvyʼs type-directed partial evaluator for the same lambda calculus, the use of delimited control operators is avoided. The role of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Kripke models for classical logic.Danko Ilik, Gyesik Lee & Hugo Herbelin - 2010 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 161 (11):1367-1378.
    We introduce a notion of the Kripke model for classical logic for which we constructively prove the soundness and cut-free completeness. We discuss the novelty of the notion and its potential applications.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Strongly uniform bounds from semi-constructive proofs.Philipp Gerhardy & Ulrich Kohlenbach - 2006 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 141 (1):89-107.
    In [U. Kohlenbach, Some logical metatheorems with applications in functional analysis, Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 357 89–128], the second author obtained metatheorems for the extraction of effective bounds from classical, prima facie non-constructive proofs in functional analysis. These metatheorems for the first time cover general classes of structures like arbitrary metric, hyperbolic, CAT and normed linear spaces and guarantee the independence of the bounds from parameters ranging over metrically bounded spaces. Recently ]), the authors obtained generalizations of these metatheorems which (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Semantic Completeness of First-Order Theories in Constructive Reverse Mathematics.Christian Espíndola - 2016 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 57 (2):281-286.
    We introduce a general notion of semantic structure for first-order theories, covering a variety of constructions such as Tarski and Kripke semantics, and prove that, over Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, the completeness of such semantics is equivalent to the Boolean prime ideal theorem. Using a result of McCarty, we conclude that the completeness of Kripke semantics is equivalent, over intuitionistic Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, to the Law of Excluded Middle plus BPI. Along the way, we also prove the equivalence, over ZF, between (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The prehistory of the subsystems of second-order arithmetic.Walter Dean & Sean Walsh - 2017 - Review of Symbolic Logic 10 (2):357-396.
    This paper presents a systematic study of the prehistory of the traditional subsystems of second-order arithmetic that feature prominently in the reverse mathematics program of Friedman and Simpson. We look in particular at: (i) the long arc from Poincar\'e to Feferman as concerns arithmetic definability and provability, (ii) the interplay between finitism and the formalization of analysis in the lecture notes and publications of Hilbert and Bernays, (iii) the uncertainty as to the constructive status of principles equivalent to Weak K\"onig's (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Intuitionistic Completeness and Classical Logic.D. C. McCarty - 2002 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 43 (4):243-248.
    We show that, if a suitable intuitionistic metatheory proves that consistency implies satisfiability for subfinite sets of propositional formulas relative either to standard structures or to Kripke models, then that metatheory also proves every negative instance of every classical propositional tautology. Since reasonable intuitionistic set theories such as HAS or IZF do not demonstrate all such negative instances, these theories cannot prove completeness for intuitionistic propositional logic in the present sense.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • On Theorems of Gödel and Kreisel: Completeness and Markov's Principle.D. C. McCarty - 1994 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 35 (1):99-107.
    In 1957, Gödel proved that completeness for intuitionistic predicate logic HPL implies forms of Markov's Principle, MP. The result first appeared, with Kreisel's refinements and elaborations, in Kreisel. Featuring large in the Gödel-Kreisel proofs are applications of the axiom of dependent choice, DC. Also in play is a form of Herbrand's Theorem, one allowing a reduction of HPL derivations for negated prenex formulae to derivations of negations of conjunctions of suitable instances. First, we here show how to deduce Gödel's results (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Intuitionistic completeness of first-order logic.Robert Constable & Mark Bickford - 2014 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 165 (1):164-198.
    We constructively prove completeness for intuitionistic first-order logic, iFOL, showing that a formula is provable in iFOL if and only if it is uniformly valid in intuitionistic evidence semantics as defined in intuitionistic type theory extended with an intersection operator.Our completeness proof provides an effective procedure that converts any uniform evidence into a formal iFOL proof. Uniform evidence can involve arbitrary concepts from type theory such as ordinals, topological structures, algebras and so forth. We have implemented that procedure in the (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Current Research on Gödel’s Incompleteness Theorems.Yong Cheng - 2021 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 27 (2):113-167.
    We give a survey of current research on Gödel’s incompleteness theorems from the following three aspects: classifications of different proofs of Gödel’s incompleteness theorems, the limit of the applicability of Gödel’s first incompleteness theorem, and the limit of the applicability of Gödel’s second incompleteness theorem.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Principles of continuous choice and continuity of functions in formal systems for constructive mathematics.Michael J. Beeson - 1977 - Annals of Mathematical Logic 12 (3):249.
  • Paraconsistent Metatheory: New Proofs with Old Tools.Guillermo Badia, Zach Weber & Patrick Girard - 2022 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 51 (4):825-856.
    This paper is a step toward showing what is achievable using non-classical metatheory—particularly, a substructural paraconsistent framework. What standard results, or analogues thereof, from the classical metatheory of first order logic can be obtained? We reconstruct some of the originals proofs for Completeness, Löwenheim-Skolem and Compactness theorems in the context of a substructural logic with the naive comprehension schema. The main result is that paraconsistent metatheory can ‘re-capture’ versions of standard theorems, given suitable restrictions and background assumptions; but the shift (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Non-classical Metatheory for Non-classical Logics.Andrew Bacon - 2013 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 42 (2):335-355.
    A number of authors have objected to the application of non-classical logic to problems in philosophy on the basis that these non-classical logics are usually characterised by a classical metatheory. In many cases the problem amounts to more than just a discrepancy; the very phenomena responsible for non-classicality occur in the field of semantics as much as they do elsewhere. The phenomena of higher order vagueness and the revenge liar are just two such examples. The aim of this paper is (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Logical Combinatorialism.Andrew Bacon - 2020 - Philosophical Review 129 (4):537-589.
    In explaining the notion of a fundamental property or relation, metaphysicians will often draw an analogy with languages. The fundamental properties and relations stand to reality as the primitive predicates and relations stand to a language: the smallest set of vocabulary God would need in order to write the “book of the world.” This paper attempts to make good on this metaphor. To that end, a modality is introduced that, put informally, stands to propositions as logical truth stands to sentences. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • The metamathematics of ergodic theory.Jeremy Avigad - 2009 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 157 (2-3):64-76.
    The metamathematical tradition, tracing back to Hilbert, employs syntactic modeling to study the methods of contemporary mathematics. A central goal has been, in particular, to explore the extent to which infinitary methods can be understood in computational or otherwise explicit terms. Ergodic theory provides rich opportunities for such analysis. Although the field has its origins in seventeenth century dynamics and nineteenth century statistical mechanics, it employs infinitary, nonconstructive, and structural methods that are characteristically modern. At the same time, computational concerns (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Explicit provability and constructive semantics. [REVIEW]Jeremy D. Avigad - 2002 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 8 (3):432-432.
  • Explicit provability and constructive semantics.Sergei N. Artemov - 2001 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 7 (1):1-36.
    In 1933 Godel introduced a calculus of provability (also known as modal logic S4) and left open the question of its exact intended semantics. In this paper we give a solution to this problem. We find the logic LP of propositions and proofs and show that Godel's provability calculus is nothing but the forgetful projection of LP. This also achieves Godel's objective of defining intuitionistic propositional logic Int via classical proofs and provides a Brouwer-Heyting-Kolmogorov style provability semantics for Int which (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   112 citations  
  • Necessity of Thought.Cesare Cozzo - 2015 - In Heinrich Wansing (ed.), Dag Prawitz on Proofs and Meaning. Springer. pp. 101-20.
    The concept of “necessity of thought” plays a central role in Dag Prawitz’s essay “Logical Consequence from a Constructivist Point of View” (Prawitz 2005). The theme is later developed in various articles devoted to the notion of valid inference (Prawitz, 2009, forthcoming a, forthcoming b). In section 1 I explain how the notion of necessity of thought emerges from Prawitz’s analysis of logical consequence. I try to expound Prawitz’s views concerning the necessity of thought in sections 2, 3 and 4. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The logic of brouwer and heyting.Joan Rand Moschovakis - 2009 - In Dov Gabbay (ed.), The Handbook of the History of Logic. Elsevier. pp. 77-125.