Switch to: References

Citations of:

Criticism and the growth of knowledge

Cambridge [Eng.]: Cambridge University Press (1970)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Radical constructivism and its failings: Anti‐realism and individualism.Mark Olssen - 1996 - British Journal of Educational Studies 44 (3):275-295.
    Radical constructivism has had a major influence on present-day education, especially in the teaching of science and mathematics. The article provides an epistemological profile of constructivism and considers its strengths and weaknesses from the standpoint of its educational implications. It is argued that there are two central problems with constructivism: anti- realism and individualism which, in turn, lead to difficulties associated with idealism and relativism which, together, prove fatal for the theory.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Languages of nature. Critical essays on science and literature : ed. L.J. Jordanova , 351 pp., £8.95 p.b.; £25.00 h.b. [REVIEW]Dagmar Barnouw - 1989 - History of European Ideas 10 (5):607-609.
  • Researching to improve theory, policy and practice. An essay review of Viviane Robinson, Problem‐based Methodology: Research for the Improvement of Practice, Oxford: Pergamon Press, 1993.J. C. Walker - 1996 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 28 (2):55-68.
  • Epistemology and Justifying the Curriculum of Educational Studies.J. C. Walker & C. W. Evers - 1982 - British Journal of Educational Studies 30 (2):213 - 229.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Obituary.[author unknown] - 2000 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 14 (1):77-81.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Thinking about change. Hussey - 2002 - Nursing Philosophy 3 (2):104-113.
    Beginning by offering a conceptual analysis of change – a statement of what change of any kind is – the paper sets out to examine possible ways of understanding a very common and important variety of change that may be called ‘evolutionary’. These changes include anything from the production of a clay pot on a potter's wheel to the emergence of a system of management, or from the effects of an analgesic drug to the development of a new programme of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Peer review: An unflattering picture.Kenneth M. Adams - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):135-136.
  • Against Harmony: Infinite Idealizations and Causal Explanation.Iulian D. Toader - 2015 - In Iulian D. Toader, Ilie Parvu & Gabriel Sandu (eds.), Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science, vol. 313: Springer. pp. 291-301.
    This paper argues against the view that the standard explanation of phase transitions in statistical mechanics may be considered a causal explanation, a distortion that can nevertheless successfully represent causal relations.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Guest Editorial.Zak van Straaten - 1980 - Philosophical Papers 9 (2):95-96.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Guest Editorial.Zak Van Straaten - 1979 - Philosophical Papers 8 (2):ebi-ebii.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Language acquisition: Growth or learning?Geoffrey Sampson - 1989 - Philosophical Papers 18 (3):203-240.
  • Ideology and the interpretative foundation of science.Mark Orkin - 1979 - Philosophical Papers 8 (2):1-20.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the what_ and _how of learning.R. C. Gonzalez & Matthew Yarczower - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):145-145.
  • Contrasting approaches to a theory of learning.Timothy D. Johnston - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):125-139.
    The general process view of learning, which guided research into learning for the first half of this century, has come under attack in recent years from several quarters. One form of criticism has come from proponents of the so-called biological boundaries approach to learning. These theorists have presented a variety of data showing that supposedly general laws of learning may in fact be limited in their applicability to different species and learning tasks, and they argue that the limitations are drawn (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   287 citations  
  • The meaning of representation in animal memory.H. L. Roitblat - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):353-372.
    A representation is a remnant of previous experience that allows that experience to affect later behavior. This paper develops a metatheoretical view of representation and applies it to issues concerning representation in animals. To describe a representational system one must specify the following: thedomainor range of situations in the represented world to which the system applies; thecontentor set of features encoded and preserved by the system; thecodeor transformational rules relating features of the representation to the corresponding features of the represented (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   312 citations  
  • Rejecting published work: It couldn't happen in physics! (or could it?).Michael J. Moravcsik - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (2):228-229.
  • Peer review and the Current Anthropology experience.Cyril Belshaw - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (2):200-201.
  • Peer-review practices of psychological journals: The fate of published articles, submitted again.Douglas P. Peters & Stephen J. Ceci - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (2):187-255.
    A growing interest in and concern about the adequacy and fairness of modern peer-review practices in publication and funding are apparent across a wide range of scientific disciplines. Although questions about reliability, accountability, reviewer bias, and competence have been raised, there has been very little direct research on these variables.The present investigation was an attempt to study the peer-review process directly, in the natural setting of actual journal referee evaluations of submitted manuscripts. As test materials we selected 12 already published (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   76 citations  
  • The uneven distribution of fears and phobias: A nonassociative account.Ross G. Menzies - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2):305-306.
    A review of data concerning the uneven distribution of phobias suggests that nonassociative, ethological models can account for most of tile important findings that cannot be attributed to expectancy biases. The origin of a variety of fears that appear in fixed developmental patterns across divergent cultures and species can best be explained by biological models.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Preparedness, phobias, and the Panglossian paradigm.Richard J. McNally - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2):303-304.
    In his critique of preparedness theory, Davey does not address the limitations of adaptationism. The purpose of this commentary is to outline problems that arise when one assumes that mental illness (e.g., phobic disorder)musthave had adaptive significance for it to have survived the vicissitudes of natural selection.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Preparedness and phobias: Specific evolved associations or a generalized expectancy bias?Graham C. L. Davey - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2):289-297.
    Most phobias are focussed on a small number of fear-inducing stimuli (e.g., snakes, spiders). A review of the evidence supporting biological and cognitive explanations of this uneven distribution of phobias suggests that the readiness with which such stimuli become associated with aversive outcomes arises from biases in the processing of information about threatening stimuli rather than from phylogenetically based associative predispositions or “biological preparedness.” This cognitive bias, consisting of a heightened expectation of aversive outcomes following fear-relevant stimuli, generates and maintains (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • Scientific revolutions.Thomas Nickles - 2010 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Thomas Kuhn.Alexander Bird - 2018 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Thomas Samuel Kuhn (1922–1996) is one of the most influential philosophers of science of the twentieth century, perhaps the most influential. His 1962 book The Structure of Scientific Revolutions is one of the most cited academic books of all time. Kuhn’s contribution to the philosophy of science marked not only a break with several key positivist doctrines, but also inaugurated a new style of philosophy of science that brought it closer to the history of science. His account of the development (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   92 citations  
  • Against method, against science? On logic, order and analogy in the sciences.Raymond Aaron Younis - 2017 - In Jeremy Horne (ed.), Philosophical Perceptions on Logic and Order. Hershey: IGI Global. pp. 270-282.
  • Biomorphism and Models in Design.Cameron Shelley - 2015 - In Woosuk Park, Ping Li & Lorenzo Magnani (eds.), Philosophy and Cognitive Science Ii: Western & Eastern Studies. Cham: Springer Verlag.
  • Conspiracy Theories and the Internet: Controlled Demolition and Arrested Development.Steve Clarke - 2007 - Episteme 4 (2):167-180.
    Abstract Following Clarke (2002), a Lakatosian approach is used to account for the epistemic development of conspiracy theories. It is then argued that the hypercritical atmosphere of the internet has slowed down the development of conspiracy theories, discouraging conspiracy theorists from articulating explicit versions of their favoured theories, which could form the hard core of Lakatosian research pro grammes. The argument is illustrated with a study of the “controlled demolition” theory of the collapse of three towers at the World Trade (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Deconstruction, postmodernism and philosophy of science: Some Epistemo‐critical bearings.Christopher Norris - 1998 - Cultural Values 2 (1):18-50.
    This essay argues a case for viewing Derrida's work in the context of recent French epistemology and philosophy of science; more specifically, the critical‐rationalist approach exemplified by thinkers such as Bachelard and Canguilhem. I trace this line of descent principally through Derrida's essay ‘White Mythology: Metaphor in the Text of Philosophy’. My conclusions are (1) that we get Derrida wrong if we read him as a fargone antirealist for whom there is nothing ‘outside the text'; (2) that he provides some (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Explanation, Causation and Deduction.Fred Wilson - 1985 - Dordrecht, Boston, Lancaster: Reidel.
    The purpose of this essay is to defend the deductive-nomological model of explanation against a number of criticisms that have been made of it. It has traditionally been thought that scientific explanations were causal and that scientific explanations involved deduction from laws. In recent years, however, this three-fold identity has been challenged: there are, it is argued, causal explanations that are not scientific, scientific explanations that are not deductive, deductions from laws that are neither causal explanations nor scientific explanations, and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Concept of Argument: A Philosophical Foundation.Harald R. Wohlrapp - 2014 - Dordrecht NL: Springer.
    Arguing that our attachment to Aristotelian modes of discourse makes a revision of their conceptual foundations long overdue, the author proposes the consideration of unacknowledged factors that play a central role in argument itself. These are in particular the subjective imprint and the dynamics of argumentation. Their inclusion in a four-dimensional framework and the focus on thesis validity allow for a more realistic view of our discourse practice. Exhaustive analyses of fascinating historical and contemporary arguments are provided. These range from (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Texting ECHO on historical data.Jan M. Zytkow - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):489-490.
  • Modularity need not imply locality: Damaged modules can have nonlocal effects.Edgar Zurif & David Swinney - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):89-90.
  • A counterargument, nevertheless.G. E. Zuriff - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):166-167.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What and where is the unconditioned (or conditioned) stimulus in the conditioning model of neurosis?Marvin Zuckerman - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (2):187-188.
  • What are the options? social determinants of personal research plants.John Ziman - 1981 - Minerva 19 (1):1-42.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Bias, incompetence, or bad management?John Ziman - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (2):245-246.
  • A gestalt theoretic account for the coordination of perception and action in motor learning.Alf C. Zimmer & Hermann Körndle - 1994 - Philosophical Psychology 7 (2):249-265.
    A review of the scanty Gestaltist literature on motor behaviour indicates that a genuine Gestalt theoretic approach to motor behaviour can be characterized by three research questions: (1) What are the natural units of motor behaviour? (2) What characterizes the self-organization in motor behaviour? (3) What are the conditions for invariance in motor behaviour? Tentative answers to these questions can be found by analysing the parallels between Gestalt theory and Bernstein's theory of motor actions and by showing that Gestalt theory (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Short-latency avoidance responses.Kazimierz Zieliński - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (2):186-187.
  • What to do about peer review: Is the cure worse than the disease?Thomas R. Zentall - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):166-167.
  • The heuristic value of representation.Thomas R. Zentall - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):393-394.
  • Reliability and validity of peer review.David Zeaman - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (2):245-245.
  • La recepción de T.S. Kuhn en España.Francisco Zamora Baño - 1997 - Endoxa 1 (9):187.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Logic of discovery or psychology of invention?Elie Zahar - 1983 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 34 (3):243-261.
  • Unphilosophical probability.Sandy L. Zabell - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (3):358-359.
  • From the logic of mathematical discovery to the methodology of scientific research programmes.Zheng Yuxin - 1990 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 41 (3):377-399.
  • Rational evaluation in belief revision.Yongfeng Yuan & Shier Ju - 2015 - Synthese 192 (7):2311-2336.
    We introduce a new operator, called rational evaluation, in belief change. The operator evaluates new information according to the agent’s core beliefs, and then exports the plausible part of the new information. It belongs to the decision module in belief change. We characterize rational evaluation by axiomatic postulates and propose two functional constructions for it, based on the well-known constructions of kernel sets and remainder sets, respectively. The main results of the paper are two representation theorems with respect to the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • What counts as local?Andrew W. Young - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):88-89.
  • Teaching Equals Indoctrination: The Dominant Epistemic Practices of Our Schools.R. E. Young - 1984 - British Journal of Educational Studies 32 (3):220 - 238.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Teaching equals indoctrination: The dominant epistemic practices of our schools.R. E. Young - 1984 - British Journal of Educational Studies 32 (3):220-238.
    . Teaching equals indoctrination: The dominant epistemic practices of our schools. British Journal of Educational Studies: Vol. 32, No. 3, pp. 220-238.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Stove's critique of "irrationalists".Steven Yates - 1987 - Metaphilosophy 18 (2):149–160.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark