Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Being human is a kaleidoscopic affair.Maria Kronfeldner - 2024 - Philosophy and Society 35 (1):5-24.
    This paper spells out the ways in which we need to be pluralists about “human nature”. It discusses a conceptual pluralism about the concept of “human nature”, stemming from post-essentialist ontology and the semantic complexity of the term “nature”; a descriptive pluralism about the “descriptive nature” of human beings, which is a pluralism regarding our self-understanding as human beings that stems from the long list of typical features of, and relations between, human beings; a natural kind term pluralism, which is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Evelyn Fox Keller: The Mirage of a Space Between Nature and Nurture.David S. Moore - 2012 - Science & Education 21 (4):583-590.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Phenotypic Plasticity and Reaction Norms.Jonathan M. Kaplan - 2008 - In Sahorta Sarkar & Anya Plutynski (eds.), Companion to the Philosophy of Biology. Blackwell. pp. 205–222.
    This chapter contains section titled: Introduction: What is Phenotypic Plasticity? Developmental Conversion and Developmental Sensitivity: Two Forms of Phenotypic Plasticity Environmental Heterogeneity, Cues, and Plasticity Phenotypic Plasticity and Developmental Buffering The Future of Phenotypic Plasticity Research Acknowledgments References Further Reading.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Biological information.Peter Godfrey-Smith & Kim Sterelny - 2012 - In Peter Adamson (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Culture or Biology? If this sounds interesting, you might be confused.Sebastian Watzl - 2019 - In Jaan Valsinger (ed.), Social Philosophy of Science for the Social Sciences. Springer. pp. 45-71.
    Culture or Biology? The question can seem deep and important. Yet, I argue in this chapter, if you are enthralled by questions about our biological differences, then you are probably confused. My goal is to diagnose the confusion. In debates about the role of biology in the social world it is easy to ask the wrong questions, and it is easy to misinterpret the scientific research. We are intuitively attracted to what is called psychological essentialism, and therefore interpret what is (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Evolution of Complexity.Mark Bedau - 2009 - In Barberousse Anouk, Morange M. & Pradeau T. (eds.), Mapping the Future of Biology. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol 266. Springer.
  • The Functional Perspective of Organismal Biology.Arno Wouters - 2005 - In Thomas A. C. Reydon & Lia Hemerik (eds.), Current Themes in Theoretical Biology : A Dutch Perspective. Springer. pp. 33--69.
    Following Mayr (1961) evolutionary biologists often maintain that the hallmark of biology is its evolutionary perspective. In this view, biologists distinguish themselves from other natural scientists by their emphasis on why-questions. Why-questions are legitimate in biology but not in other natural sciences because of the selective character of the process by means of which living objects acquire their characteristics. For that reason, why-questions should be answered in terms of natural selection. Functional biology is seen as a reductionist science that applies (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Reform for the evolutionary social sciences or new theory of human nature? [REVIEW]Stephen M. Downes - 2016 - Metascience 25 (3):479-485.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Cultural dynamics add multiple layers of complexity to behavioural genetics.Laurel Fogarty & Nicole Creanza - 2022 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 45:e161.
    As emphasized in early cultural evolutionary theory, understanding heritability of human traits – especially, behavioural traits – is difficult. The target article describes important ways that culture can enhance, or obscure, signatures of heritability in genetic studies. Here, we discuss the utility of calculating heritability for behavioural traits influenced by cultural evolution and point to conceptual and technical complications to consider in future models.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Early Confucian Philosophy and the Development of Compassion.David B. Wong - 2015 - Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy 14 (2):157-194.
    Metaphors of adorning, crafting, water flowing downward, and growing sprouts appear in the Analects , the Mencius , and the Xunzi 荀子. They express and guide thinking about what there is in human nature to cultivate and how it is to be cultivated. The craft metaphor seems to imply that our nature is of the sort that must be disciplined and reshaped to achieve goodness, while the adorning, water, and sprout metaphors imply that human nature has an inbuilt directionality toward (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • The Softening of the Modern Synthesis: Julian Huxley: Evolution: The Modern Synthesis; The Definitive Edition. Massimo Pigliucci and Gerd B. Müller : Evolution—The Extended Synthesis.Joeri Witteveen - 2011 - Acta Biotheoretica 59 (3):333-345.
    The Modern Synthesis has been receiving bad press for some time now. Back in 1983, in an article entitled “The Hardening of the Modern Synthesis” Stephen Jay Gould criticized the way the Modern Synthesis had developed since its inception in the 1930s and early 1940s (Gould 1983). Back then, those who would later become known as ‘architects’ of the synthesis were united in their call for explaining evolution at all levels in terms of causation at one level: genetics. What drove (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Reengineering the Darwinian Sciences in Social Context.William C. Wimsatt - 2006 - Biological Theory 1 (4):341-342.
  • Genes, memes, and cultural heredity.William C. Wimsatt - 1999 - Biology and Philosophy 14 (2):279-310.
  • Commentary: Reengineering the Darwinian Sciences in Social Context.William C. Wimsatt - 2006 - Biological Theory 1 (4):338-341.
  • Explaining individual differences.Zina B. Ward - 2023 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 101 (C):61-70.
    Most psychological research aims to uncover generalizations about the mind that hold across subjects. Philosophical discussions of scientific explanation have focused on such generalizations, but in doing so, have often overlooked an important phenomenon: variation. Variation is ubiquitous in psychology and many other domains, and an important target of explanation in its own right. Here I characterize explananda that concern individual differences and formulate an account of what it takes to explain them. I argue that the notion of actual difference (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Race, the heritability of IQ, and the intellectual scale of nature.Douglas Wahlsten - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):358-359.
  • Insensitivity of the analysis of variance to heredity-environment interaction.Douglas Wahlsten - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):109-120.
  • Goals and methods: The study of development versus partitioning of variance.Douglas Wahlsten - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):146-161.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Genetic influences on IQ.F. Vogel - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):358-358.
  • Correlation, regression and biased science.Atam Vetta - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):357-358.
  • Antitest views are refuted.P. E. Vernon - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):356-357.
  • What do double dissociations prove?G. Van Orden - 2001 - Cognitive Science 25 (1):111-172.
    Brain damage may doubly dissociate cognitive modules, but the practice of revealing dissociations is predicated on modularity being true (T. Shallice, 1988). This article questions the utility of assuming modularity, as it examines a paradigmatic double dissociation of reading modules. Reading modules illustrate two general problems. First, modularity fails to converge on a fixed set of exclusionary criteria that define pure cases. As a consequence, competing modular theories force perennial quests for purer cases, which simply perpetuates growth in the list (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Variation in means and in ends.Arie J. van Noordwijk - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):145-146.
  • Self-organization of cognitive performance.Guy C. Van Orden, John G. Holden & Michael T. Turvey - 2003 - Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 132 (3):331.
  • An existence proof for intelligence?Steven G. Vandenberg - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):355-356.
  • Cultural evolution of genetic heritability.Ryutaro Uchiyama, Rachel Spicer & Michael Muthukrishna - 2021 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 45:e152.
    Behavioral genetics and cultural evolution have both revolutionized our understanding of human behavior – largely independent of each other. Here, we reconcile these two fields under a dual inheritance framework, offering a more nuanced understanding of the interaction between genes and culture. Going beyond typical analyses of gene–environment interactions, we describe the cultural dynamics that shape these interactions by shaping the environment and population structure. A cultural evolutionary approach can explain, for example, how factors such as rates of innovation and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Tests are not to blame.Leona E. Tyler - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):354-355.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the big list of causes.Eric Turkheimer - 2023 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 46:e205.
    The methodological shift from twin studies to genome-wide association studies (GWASs) diminished estimates of true genetic causation underlying statistical heritability of behavioral differences. The sum total of causal genetic influence on behavior is not zero, but, (a) no one cited in the target article ever thought this was the case, and (b) there is still little known about concrete instances of genetic causation.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Interactionism is good, but not good enough.Esther Thelen - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):650-650.
  • Three puzzles and eight gaps: What heritability studies and critical commentaries have not paid enough attention to.Peter Taylor - 2010 - Biology and Philosophy 25 (1):1-31.
    This article examines eight “gaps” in order to clarify why the quantitative genetics methods of partitioning variation of a trait into heritability and other components has very limited power to show anything clear and useful about genetic and environmental influences, especially for human behaviors and other traits. The first two gaps should be kept open; the others should be bridged or the difficulty of doing so should be acknowledged: 1. Key terms have multiple meanings that are distinct; 2. Statistical patterns (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Socio-ecological webs and sites of sociality:Levins' strategy of model building revisited. [REVIEW]Peter Taylor - 2000 - Biology and Philosophy 15 (2):197-210.
    This essay extends Levins'' 1966 analysis of modelbuilding in ecology and evolutionary biology. Amodel, as the product of modeling, might bevalued according to its correspondence to reality. Yet Levins'' emphasis on provisionality and changeredirects attention to the processes ofmodeling, through which scientists select and generatetheir problems, define their categories, collect theirdata, compare competing models, and present theirfindings. I identify several points where decisionsare required that are not determined by nature. Thisinvites examination of the social considerationsmodelers are reacting to at the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Situatedness and problematic boundaries: Conceptualizing life's complex ecological context. [REVIEW]Peter Taylor & Yrjö Haila - 2001 - Biology and Philosophy 16 (4):521-532.
    A key challenge in conceptualizing ecological complexity is to allow simultaneously for particularity, contingency, and structure, and for such structure to be internally differentiated,dynamically tied to its context, and subject torestructuring. Because all organisms live insuch dynamic ecological circumstances, philosophy of ecology could become the leading site for addressing difficult conceptual questions concerning the situatedness or positionality of organisms –humans included – in their changing and intersecting worlds.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Distinctions that make a difference?Peter J. Taylor - 2015 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 51:70-76.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Building on construction: An exploration of heterogeneous constructionism, using an analogy from psychology and a sketch from socio-economic modeling.Peter J. Taylor - 1995 - Perspectives on Science 3 (1):66-98.
    I explore heterogeneous constructionism, my term for the perspective that science in the making is a process of agents building by combining a diversity of components. Issues addressed include causality and explanation; transcending both realism and relativism; scientists as acting, intervening, and imaginative agents; explanations that span many levels of social practice; counterfactuals in the analysis of causal claims; and practical reflexivity. An analogy from research on the social origins of depression and a sketch from my own experience in socioeconomic (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • A Gene-Free Formulation of Classical Quantitative Genetics Used to Examine Results and Interpretations Under Three Standard Assumptions.Peter J. Taylor - 2012 - Acta Biotheoretica 60 (4):357-378.
    Quantitative genetics (QG) analyses variation in traits of humans, other animals, or plants in ways that take account of the genealogical relatedness of the individuals whose traits are observed. “Classical” QG, where the analysis of variation does not involve data on measurable genetic or environmental entities or factors, is reformulated in this article using models that are free of hypothetical, idealized versions of such factors, while still allowing for defined degrees of relatedness among kinds of individuals or “varieties.” The gene (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Impact of Gene–Environment Interaction and Correlation on the Interpretation of Heritability.Omri Tal - 2011 - Acta Biotheoretica 60 (3):225-237.
    The presence of gene–environment statistical interaction and correlation in biological development has led both practitioners and philosophers of science to question the legitimacy of heritability estimates. The paper offers a novel approach to assess the impact of GxE and rGE on the way genetic and environmental causation can be partitioned. A probabilistic framework is developed, based on a quantitative genetic model that incorporates GxE and rGE, offering a rigorous way of interpreting heritability estimates. Specifically, given an estimate of heritability and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • From heritability to probability.Omri Tal - 2009 - Biology and Philosophy 24 (1):81-105.
    Can a heritability value tell us something about the weight of genetic versus environmental causes that have acted in the development of a particular individual? Two possible questions arise. Q1: what portion of the phenotype of X is due to its genes and what portion to its environment? Q2: what portion of X’s phenotypic deviation from the mean is a result of its genetic deviation and what portion a result of its environmental deviation? An answer to Q1 provides the full (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • R. A. Fisher, Lancelot Hogben, and the Origin of Genotype–Environment Interaction.James Tabery - 2008 - Journal of the History of Biology 41 (4):717-761.
    This essay examines the origin of genotype-environment interaction, or G×E. "Origin" and not "the origin" because the thesis is that there were actually two distinct concepts of G×E at this beginning: a biometric concept, or \[G \times E_B\], and a developmental concept, or \[G \times E_D \]. R. A. Fisher, one of the founders of population genetics and the creator of the statistical analysis of variance, introduced the biometric concept as he attempted to resolve one of the main problems in (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Making sense of the nature–nurture debate. [REVIEW]James Tabery - 2009 - Biology and Philosophy 24 (5):711-723.
  • Difference mechanisms: Explaining variation with mechanisms.James Tabery - 2009 - Biology and Philosophy 24 (5):645-664.
    Philosophers of science have developed an account of causal-mechanical explanation that captures regularity, but this account neglects variation. In this article I amend the philosophy of mechanisms to capture variation. The task is to explicate the relationship between regular causal mechanisms responsible for individual development and causes of variation responsible for variation in populations. As it turns out, disputes over this relationship have rested at the heart of the nature–nurture debate. Thus, an explication of the relationship between regular causal mechanisms (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • From a Genetic Predisposition to an Interactive Predisposition: Rethinking the Ethical Implications of Screening for Gene-Environment Interactions.James Tabery - 2009 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 34 (1):27-48.
    In a widely acclaimed study from 2002, researchers found a case of gene-environment interaction for a gene controlling neuroenzymatic activity (low vs. high), exposure to childhood maltreatment, and antisocial personality disorder (ASPD). Cases of gene-environment interaction are generally characterized as evincing a genetic predisposition; for example, individuals with low neuroenzymatic activity are generally characterized as having a genetic predisposition to ASPD. I first argue that the concept of a genetic predisposition fundamentally misconstrues these cases of gene-environment interaction. This misconstrual will (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Religion and religious beliefs as evolutionary adaptations.Konrad Szocik - 2017 - Zygon 52 (1):24-52.
    Scholars employing an evolutionary approach to the study of religion and religious beliefs search for ultimate explanations of the origin, propagation, and persistence of religious beliefs. This quest often pairs in debate two opposing perspectives: the adaptationist and “by-product” explanations of religion and religious beliefs. The majority of scholars prefer the by-product approach, which is agnostic and even doubtful of the usefulness of religious beliefs. Despite this pervasive negativity, it seems unwarranted to deny the great usefulness of religious beliefs—particularly concerning (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The nature/nurture debate: Same old wolf in new sheep's clothing?Horst D. Steklis - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):649-650.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Intelligence and test bias: Art and science.Robert J. Sternberg - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):353-354.
  • Happiness: The Potential Power of Environment.Clifford Sosis - 2012 - The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication 7.
    Many scientists have argued that they can determine to what extent human happiness levels are controlled by genes by comparing the average happiness levels of identical twins raised apart. If we discover that identical twins raised apart tend to be more hedonically similar than fraternal twins raised apart, this is interpreted as evidence for the thesis that genes have a strong influence on our happiness levels. If identical twins are hedonically dissimilar, as dissimilar as fraternal twins raised apart, this has (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Hedonic possibilities and heritability statistics.Clifford Sosis - 2014 - Philosophical Psychology 27 (5):681-702.
    Several influential psychologists have attempted to estimate to what extent human happiness levels are directly controlled by genes by comparing the happiness levels of identical twins raised apart. If we discover that the happiness levels of identical twins raised apart tend to be closer than the happiness levels of fraternal twins raised apart, this is taken as evidence that average happiness levels are largely controlled by genes. However, if it turns out that identical twins' happiness levels tend to be substantially (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The nature and nurture of birdsong.P. J. B. Slater - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):648-649.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Genetic Representation Explains the Cluster of Innateness‐Related Properties.Nicholas Shea - 2012 - Mind and Language 27 (4):466-493.
    The concept of innateness is used to make inferences between various better-understood properties, like developmental canalization, evolutionary adaptation, heritability, species-typicality, and so on (‘innateness-related properties’). This article uses a recently-developed account of the representational content carried by inheritance systems like the genome to explain why innateness-related properties cluster together, especially in non-human organisms. Although inferences between innateness-related properties are deductively invalid, and lead to false conclusions in many actual cases, where some aspect of a phenotypic trait develops in reliance on (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Drowning in shallow causality.Hao Shen & Marcus W. Feldman - 2023 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 46:e199.
    It has been known for decades that inference concerning genetic causes of human behavioral phenotypes cannot be legitimately made from correlations among relatives. We claim that these inferential difficulties cannot be overcome by assigning different names to causes inferred from within-family and population-level genome-wide association studies (GWASs). For educational attainment, for example, unraveling gene–environment interactions requires more than new names for causes.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Developmental Systems Theory Formulated as a Claim about Inherited Representations.Nicholas Shea - 2011 - Philosophy of Science 78 (1):60-82.
    Developmental Systems Theory (DST) emphasises the importance of non-genetic factors in development and their relevance to evolution. A common, deflationary reaction is that it has long been appreciated that non-genetic factors are causally indispensable. This paper argues that DST can be reformulated to make a more substantive claim: that the special role played by genes is also played by some (but not all) non-genetic resources. That special role is to transmit inherited representations, in the sense of Shea (2007: Biology and (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations