Switch to: References

Citations of:

Bioethics in a liberal society: the political framework of bioethics decision making

Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press (2002)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. A Review of: “Thomas May. 2002. Bioethics in a Liberal Society: The Political Framework of Bioethics Decision Making”: Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press. 135 pp. $42.00, hardcover. [REVIEW]James Stacey Taylor - 2005 - American Journal of Bioethics 5 (1):92-93.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How to Regulate the Right to Self-Medicate.Joseph T. F. Roberts - 2022 - HEC Forum 34 (3):233-255.
    In _Pharmaceutical Freedom_ Professor Flanigan argues we ought to grant people self-medication rights for the same reasons we respect people’s right to give (or refuse to give) informed consent to treatment. Despite being the most comprehensive argument in favour of self-medication written to date, Flanigan’s _Pharmaceutical Freedom_ leaves a number of questions unanswered, making it unclear how the safe-guards Flanigan incorporates to protect people from harming themselves would work in practice. In this paper, I extend Professor Flanigan’s account by discussing (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A Review of: “Stephen H. Miles. 2003. The Hippocratic Oath and the Ethics of Medicine”: New York: Oxford University Press. 208 pp. $35.00, hardcover. [REVIEW]Simon Mills - 2005 - American Journal of Bioethics 5 (1):90-92.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • You Kids Get off My Ethics Lawn!: An Admitted Curmudgeonly Critique of Credentialing Individual Clinical Ethics Consultants.Thomas May - 2020 - American Journal of Bioethics 20 (3):32-34.
    Volume 20, Issue 3, March 2020, Page 32-34.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Social restrictions on informed consent: Research ethics and medical decision making.Thomas May - 2004 - HEC Forum 16 (1):38-44.
  • On the Justifiability of ACMG Recommendations for Reporting of Incidental Findings in Clinical Exome and Genome Sequencing.Thomas May - 2015 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 43 (1):134-142.
    This paper examines three possible justifications for original ACMG recommendations to return incidental findings from whole exome or genome sequencing independent of patient preferences. The first two potential justifications, based on a patient's authentic values, then on harms to others, are founding lacking as a basis of justification for these recommendations. The third, grounded in analogous professional practices, might serve as a potential justification if several controversies can be avoided. However, given the nature of these controversies and the need to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Autonomy, Well-Being, and the Value of Genetic Testing for Adopted Persons.Thomas May & Harold Grotevant - 2018 - HEC Forum 30 (3):283-295.
    This paper argues that the value of genetic-relative family health history information and the notion that lack of this information is a disadvantage can be established through its role as a nested goal in comprehensive life projects independent of documentation of particular health outcomes. Health information often plays a significant role in a person's formulation of life goals and projects, as well as in identification of plausible effective means to realize these goals. If health outcomes are valuable in part because (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Infectious Diseases Society of America Lyme guidelines: a cautionary tale about the development of clinical practice guidelines.Lorraine Johnson & Raphael B. Stricker - 2010 - Philosophy, Ethics, and Humanities in Medicine 5:1-17.
    Flawed clinical practice guidelines may compromise patient care. Commercial conflicts of interest on panels that write treatment guidelines are particularly problematic, because panelists may have conflicting agendas that influence guideline recommendations. Historically, there has been no legal remedy for conflicts of interest on guidelines panels. However, in May 2008, the Attorney General of Connecticut concluded a ground-breaking antitrust investigation into the development of Lyme disease treatment guidelines by one of the largest medical societies in the United States, the Infectious Diseases (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • An ethics of expertise based on informed consent.Kevin C. Elliott - 2006 - Science and Engineering Ethics 12 (4):637-661.
    Ethicists widely accept the notion that scientists have moral responsibilities to benefit society at large. The dissemination of scientific information to the public and its political representatives is central to many of the ways in which scientists serve society. Unfortunately, the task of providing information can often give rise to moral quandaries when scientific experts participate in politically charged debates over issues that are fraught with uncertainty. This paper develops a theoretical framework for an “ethics of expertise” (EOE) based on (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Relevant Information and Informed Consent in Research: In Defense of the Subjective Standard of Disclosure.Vilius Dranseika, Jan Piasecki & Marcin Waligora - 2017 - Science and Engineering Ethics 23 (1):215-225.
    In this article, we seek to contribute to the debate on the requirement of disclosure in the context of informed consent for research. We defend the subjective standard of disclosure and describe ways to implement this standard in research practice. We claim that the researcher should make an effort to find out what kinds of information are likely to be relevant for those consenting to research. This invites researchers to take empirical survey information seriously, attempt to understand the cultural context, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Professional-Client Relationships: Rethinking Confidentiality, Harm, and Journalists' Public Health Duties.Renita Coleman & Thomas May - 2004 - Journal of Mass Media Ethics 19 (3-4):276-292.
    Journalists seldom consider the layers of those affected by their actions; third parties such as families, children, and even people unlucky enough to be in the wrong place at the wrong time. This article argues for consideration of the broader group, considering a range of options available for doing their duty to inform the public while also minimizing harm to others. Journalists might compare themselves with other professions that have similar roles, such as anthropologists, on such issues as confidentiality and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Speak No Evil? Conscience and the Duty to Inform, Refer or Transfer Care.Mark P. Aulisio & Kavita Shah Arora - 2014 - HEC Forum 26 (3):257-266.
    This paper argues that the type of conscience claims made in last decade’s spate of cases involving pharmacists’ objections to filling birth control prescriptions and cases such as Ms. Means and Mercy Health Partners of Michigan, and even the Affordable Care Act and the Little Sisters of the Poor, as different as they appear to be from each other, share a common element that ties them together and makes them fundamentally different in kind from traditional claims of conscience about which (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations