Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Intentionality, mind and folk psychology.Winand H. Dittrich & Stephen E. G. Lea - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):39-41.
    The comment addresses central issues of a "theory theory" approach as exemplified in Gopnik' and Goldman's BBS-articles. Gopnik, on the one hand, tries to demonstrate that empirical evidence from developmental psychology supports the view of a "theory theory" in which common sense beliefs are constructed to explain ourselves and others. Focusing the informational processing routes possibly involved we would like to argue that his main thesis (e.g. idea of intentionality as a cognitive construct) lacks support at least for two reasons: (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is scientific theory change similar to early cognitive development? Gopnik on science and childhood.Tim Fuller - 2013 - Philosophical Psychology 26 (1):109 - 128.
    (2013). Is scientific theory change similar to early cognitive development? Gopnik on science and childhood. Philosophical Psychology: Vol. 26, No. 1, pp. 109-128. doi: 10.1080/09515089.2011.625114.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The psychologist's fallacy.Philip David Zelazo & Douglas Frye - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):89-90.
  • Intentionality, theoreticity and innateness.Deborah Zaitchik & Jerry Samet - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):87-89.
  • Three questions for Goldman.Andrew Woodfield - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):86-87.
  • The mystery-mastery-imagery complex.H. T. A. Whiting & R. P. Ingvaldsen - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):228-229.
  • Potential disparities between imagining and preparing motor skills.Charles B. Walter & Stephan P. Swinnen - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):227-228.
  • Imagery needs preparation too.Stefan Vogt - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):226-227.
  • Common sense, functional theories and knowledge of the mind.Max Velmans - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):85-86.
    A commentary on a target article by Alison Gopnik (1993) How we know our minds: the illusion of first-person knowledge of intentionality. Focusing on evidence of how children acquire a theory of mind, this commentary argues that there are internal inconsistencies in theories that both argue for the functional role of conscious experiences and the irreducibility of those experiences to third-person viewable information processing.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Action and attention.A. H. C. Van der Heijden & Bruce Bridgeman - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):225-226.
  • Where's the person?Michael Tomasello - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):84-85.
  • Why Alison Gopnik should be a behaviorist.Nicholas S. Thompson - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):83-84.
  • Separability of reference frame distinctions from motor and visual images.Gary W. Strong - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):224-225.
  • Categories, categorisation and development: Introspective knowledge is no threat to functionalism.Kim Sterelny - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):81-83.
  • The developmental history of an illusion.Keith E. Stanovich - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):80-81.
  • How do we satisfy our goals?Paul G. Skokowski - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):224-224.
  • Canonical representations and constructive praxis: Some developmental and linguistic considerations.Chris Sinha - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):223-224.
  • Knowing children's minds.Michael Siegal - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):79-80.
  • Special access lies down with theory-theory.Sydney Shoemaker - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):78-79.
  • Disenshrining the Cartesian self.Barbara A. C. Saunders - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):77-78.
  • Neurophysiology of preparation, movement and imagery.Jerome N. Sanes - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):221-223.
  • On leaving your children wrapped in thought.James Russell - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):76-77.
  • What is this thing called 'commonsense psychology'?Lynne Rudder Baker - 1999 - Philosophical Explorations 2 (1):3-19.
    What is this thing called ‘Commonsense Psychology’? The first matter to settle is what the issue is here. By ‘commonsense psychology,’ I mean primarily the systems of describing, explaining and predicting human thought and action in terms of beliefs, desires, hopes, fears, expectations, intentions and other so-called propositional attitudes. Although commonsense psychology encompasses more than propositional attitudes--e.g., emotions, traits and abilities are also within its purview--belief-desire reasoning forms the core of commonsense psychology. Commonsense psychology is what we use to explain (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Kinaesthetic illusions as tools in understanding motor imagery.J. P. Roll, J. C. Gilhodes & R. Roll - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):220-221.
  • Nonconscious motor images.Giacomo Rizzolatti - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):220-220.
  • Qualities and relations in folk theories of mind.Lance J. Rips - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):75-76.
  • Why presume analyses are on-line?Georges Rey - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):74-75.
  • To dream is not to (intend to) do.Jean Requin - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):218-219.
  • Theories of mind: Some methodological/conceptual problems and an alternative approach.Sam S. Rakover - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):73-74.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Theory-theory theory.Howard Rachlin - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):72-73.
  • Motor images are action plans.Wolfgang Prinz - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):218-218.
  • Matching and mental-state ascription.Ian Pratt - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):71-72.
  • Representational development and theory-of-mind computations.David C. Plaut & Annette Karmiloff-Smith - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):70-71.
  • Limitations on first-person experience: Implications of the “extent”.Bradford H. Pillow - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):69-69.
  • First-person authority and beliefs as representations.Paul M. Pietroski - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):67-69.
  • Practical belief and philosophical theory.Philip Pettit - 1998 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 76 (1):15 – 33.
    Philosophy invariably starts with the attempt to spell out ideas and beliefs that we already hold, whether on topics like time or causality, colour or value, consciousness or free will, democracy or justice or freedom. It may go well beyond such pre-philosophical assumptions in its further developments, regimenting them in unexpected ways, revising them on novel lines, even discarding them entirely in favour of other views. But philosophy always begins with the articulation of ordinary ideas and beliefs. This is where (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • A plea for the second functionalist model and the insufficiency of simulation.Josef Perner - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):66-67.
  • Representations of movement and representations in movement.Giuseppe Pellizzer & Apostolos P. Georgopoulos - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):216-217.
  • Jeannerod's representing brain: Image or illusion?Jean Pailhous & Mireille Bonnard - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):215-216.
  • The role of concepts in perception and inference.David R. Olson & Janet Wilde Astington - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):65-66.
  • Developmental evidence and introspection.Shaun Nichols - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):64-65.
  • Motor simulation.Adam Morton - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):215-215.
  • Mismatching categories?William Edward Morris & Robert C. Richardson - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):62-63.
  • Heuristics and counterfactual self-knowledge.Adam Morton - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):63-64.
  • Knowledge of the psychological states of self and others is not only theory-laden but also data-driven.Chris Moore & John Barresi - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):61-62.
  • Are motor images based on kinestheticvisual matching?Robert W. Mitchell - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):214-215.
  • Visually guided action and the “need to know”.A. David Milner, David P. Carey & Monika Harvey - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):213-214.
  • Reporting on Past Psychological States: Beliefs, Desires, and Intentions.Alfred Mele - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):61.
  • Mind-making practices: the social infrastructure of self-knowing agency and responsibility.Victoria McGeer - 2015 - Philosophical Explorations 18 (2):259-281.
    This paper is divided into two parts. In Section 1, I explore and defend a “regulative view” of folk-psychology as against the “standard view”. On the regulative view, folk-psychology is conceptualized in fundamentally interpersonal terms as a “mind-making” practice through which we come to form and regulate our minds in accordance with a rich array of socially shared and socially maintained sense-making norms. It is not, as the standard view maintains, simply an epistemic capacity for coming to know about the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   64 citations  
  • On assuming other folks have mental states.Michael E. Malone - 1994 - Philosophical Investigations 17 (1):37-52.