Switch to: References

Citations of:

Behaviorism is false

Journal of Philosophy 66 (14):417-52 (1969)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Theoretical contingencies.B. F. Skinner - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):541-546.
  • Behavioral and statistical theorists and their disciples.Leroy Wolins - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):540-541.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Psychology: Toward the mathematical inner man.James T. Townsend - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):539-540.
  • Behavior, theories, and the inner.Ernest Sosa - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):537-539.
  • The question: Not shall_ it be, but _which shall it be?Charles P. Shimp - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):536-537.
  • Theories and human behavior.Morton L. Schagrin - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):536-536.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Current questions for the science of behavior.Kenneth M. Sayre - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):535-535.
  • The dark side of Skinnerian epistemology.William W. Rozeboom - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):533-535.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What then should we do?Seth Roberts - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):532-533.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Are Skinner's warnings still relevant to current psychology?Marc N. Richelle - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):531-532.
  • Lessons from the history of science?John M. Nicholas - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):530-531.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Skinner's philosophy of method.R. J. Nelson - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):529-530.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Should we return to the laboratory to find out about learning?J. M. E. Moravcsik - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):529-529.
  • Cognitive science: A different approach to scientific psychology.Richard Millward - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):527-529.
  • The role of the statistician in psychology.F. H. C. Marriott - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):527-527.
  • The challenge to Skinner's theory of behavior.Brian Mackenzie - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):526-527.
  • Behavior theory: A contradiction in terms?R. Duncan Luce - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):525-526.
  • Real people, ordinary language, and natural measurement.Samuel M. Deitz - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):524-525.
  • Methods and theories in the experimental analysis of behavior.B. F. Skinner - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):511-523.
    We owe most scientific knowledge to methods of inquiry that are never formally analyzed. The analysis of behavior does not call for hypothetico-deductive methods. Statistics, taught in lieu of scientific method, is incompatible with major features of much laboratory research. Squeezing significance out of ambiguous data discourages the more promising step of scrapping the experiment and starting again. As a consequence, psychologists have taken flight from the laboratory. They have fled to Real People and the human interest of “real life,” (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • The competence-performance distinction in mental philosophy.Raymond J. Nelson - 1978 - Synthese 39 (November):337-382.
  • On mechanical recognition.R. J. Nelson - 1976 - Philosophy of Science 43 (1):24-52.
    In this paper I argue that human pattern recognition can be simulated by automata. In particular, I show that gestalt recognition and recognition of family resemblances are within the capabilities of sufficiently complex Turing machines. The argument rests on elementary facts of automata and computability theory which are used to explicate our preanalytic, informal concepts concerning gestalt patterns and recognition. The central idea is that of a machine which "knows" its own structure. Although the paper thus aims to support mechanism, (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Machine models for cognitive science.Raymond J. Nelson - 1987 - Philosophy of Science 54 (September):391-408.
    Introduction. During the past two decades philosophers of psychology have considered a large variety of computational models for philosophy of mind and more recently for cognitive science. Among the suggested models are computer programs, Turing machines, pushdown automata, linear bounded automata, finite state automata and sequential machines. Many philosophers have found finite state automata models to be the most appealing, for various reasons, although there has been no shortage of defenders of programs and Turing machines. A paper by Arthur Burks (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Skinner on the prediction and control of behavior.Hugh M. Lacey - 1979 - Theory and Decision 10 (1-4):353-385.
  • Psychological conflict and human nature: The case of behaviourism and cognition.Hugh M. Lacey - 1980 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 10 (3):131–156.
    A reasonable choice between Skinner's and Chomsky's theories requires reference to a conception of human nature. It is explained in detail why this is so, in the context of an analysis of what it is to ‘choose’ a theory. This account helps to explain the unity and coherence of the science, methodology, conception of science, object of scientific inquiry and views towards control of each of Skinner and Chomsky, and thereby explains the chasm which separates the parties to their respective (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Perception and action: Alternative views.Susan Hurley - 2001 - Synthese 129 (1):3-40.
    A traditional view of perception and action makestwo assumptions: that the causal flow betweenperception and action is primarily linear or one-way,and that they are merely instrumentally related toeach other, so that each is a means to the other.Either or both of these assumptions can be rejected. Behaviorism rejects the instrumental but not theone-way aspect of the traditional view, thus leavingitself open to charges of verificationism. Ecologicalviews reject the one-way aspect but not theinstrumental aspect of the traditional view, so thatperception and (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   78 citations  
  • Dispositions, logical states, and mental occurrents.Ronald C. Hoy - 1980 - Synthese 44 (2):207-40.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Towards a General Theory of Reduction. Part III: Cross-Categorical Reduction.C. A. Hooker - 1981 - Dialogue 20 (3):496-529.
    Any theory of reduction that goes only so far as carried in Parts I and II does only half the job. Prima facie at least, there are cases of would-be reduction which seem torn between two conflicting intuitions. On the one side there is a strong intuition that reduction is involved, and a strongly retentive reduction at that. On the other side it seems that the concepts at one level cross-classify those at the other level, so that there is no (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Computation and Cognition. [REVIEW]Robert Cummins - 1988 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 18 (1):147-162.
  • Critical Notice: "Computational Theory: critical discussion of Pylyshyn, "Computation and Cognition".Criical Notice.Robert Cummins - 1988 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 18 (1):147-162.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Is absence of evidence of pain ever evidence of absence?Deborah J. Brown & Brian Key - 2021 - Synthese 199 (1-2):3881-3902.
    Absence of evidence arguments are indispensable to comparative neurobiology. The absence in a given species of a homologous neural architecture strongly correlated with a type of conscious experience in humans should be able to be taken as a prima facie reason for concluding that the species in question does not have the capacity for that conscious experience. Absence of evidence reasoning is, however, widely disparaged for being both logically illicit and unscientific. This paper argues that these concerns are unwarranted. There (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Images et réalités du behaviorisme.Jean Bélanger - 1978 - Philosophiques 5 (1):3-110.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Theory Construction in Psychology: The Interpretation and Integration of Psychological Data.Gordon M. Becker - 1981 - Theory and Decision 13 (3):251.