Switch to: References

Citations of:

Heterologicality

Analysis 11 (3):61 - 69 (1950)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. To Know or Not to Know: Beyond Realism and Anti-Realism.Jan J. T. Srzednicki - 1995 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer.
    l. THE GENERAL PROBLEM OF EPISTEMOLOGY There is a philosophical issue that surely precedes all other possible questions. It concerns the very possibility of our thinking about some thing to some purpose. Short of this no philosophy, theory or research would be possible. But it is not immediately clear that we are assured that what purports to be effective thought, and cognition is such in reality. What guarantee is there for instance that when one is under the impression that one (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Truth and what is said.Elia Zardini - 2008 - Philosophical Perspectives 22 (1):545-574.
    A notion of truth as applicable to events of assertoric use ( utterances ) of a sentence token is arguably presupposed and required by our evaluative practices of the use of language. The truth of an utterance seems clearly to depend on what the utterance says . This fundamental dependence seems in turn to be captured by the schema that, if an utterance u says that P , then u is true iff P . Such a schema may thus be (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Grounding, dependence, and paradox.Steve Yablo - 1982 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 11 (1):117 - 137.
  • The Liar Paradox and “Meaningless” Revenge.Jared Warren - 2023 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 53 (1):49-78.
    A historically popular response to the liar paradox (“this sentence is false”) is to say that the liar sentence is meaningless (or semantically defective, or malfunctions, or…). Unfortunately, like all other supposed solutions to the liar, this approach faces a revenge challenge. Consider the revenge liar sentence, “this sentence is either meaningless or false”. If it is true, then it is either meaningless or false, so not true. And if it is not true, then it can’t be either meaningless or (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Restricting the T‐schema to Solve the Liar.Jared Warren - 2023 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 108 (1):238-258.
    If we want to retain classical logic and standard syntax in light of the liar, we are forced to restrict the T-schema. The traditional philosophical justification for this is sentential – liar sentences somehow malfunction. But the standard formal way of implementing this is conditional, our T-sentences tell us that if “p” does not malfunction, then “p” is true if and only if p. Recently Bacon and others have pointed out that conditional T-restrictions like this flirt with incoherence. If we (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Zur Antinomik der Fehlbarkeit.Mike Stange - 2021 - Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 75 (1):5-32.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Semantic closure.Graham Priest - 1984 - Studia Logica 43 (1-2):117 - 129.
    This paper argues for tlie claims that a) a natural language such as English is semanticaly closed b) semantic closure implies inconsistency. A corollary of these is that the semantics of English must be paraconsistent. The first part of the paper formulates a definition of semantic closure which applies to natural languages and shows that this implies inconsistency. The second section argues that English is semeantically closed. The preceding discussion is predicated on the assumption that there are no truth value (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Propositions, possible languages and the liar's revenge.John F. Post - 1974 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 25 (3):223-234.
  • Grelling’s Paradox.Jay Newhard - 2005 - Philosophical Studies 126 (1):1 - 27.
    Grelling’s Paradox is the paradox which results from considering whether heterologicality, the word-property which a designator has when and only when the designator does not bear the word-property it designates, is had by ‘ ȁ8heterologicality’. Although there has been some philosophical debate over its solution, Grelling’s Paradox is nearly uniformly treated as a variant of either the Liar Paradox or Russell’s Paradox, a paradox which does not present any philosophical challenges not already presented by the two better known paradoxes. The (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Gaps, Gluts, and Paradox.A. D. Irvine - 1992 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume 18 (sup1):273-299.
    Consider the following sentence schema:This sentence entails that ϕ.Call a sentence which is obtained from this schema by the substitution of an arbitrary, contingent sentence, s, for ϕ, the sentence CS. Thus, This sentence entails that s.Now ask the following question: Is CS true?One sentence classically entails a second if and only if it is impossible for both the first to be true and the second to be false. Thus ‘Xanthippe is a mother’ entails ‘Xanthippe is female’ if and only (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Gödel, Tarski, Church, and the Liar.György Serény - 2003 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 9 (1):3-25.
    The fact that Gödel's famous incompleteness theorem and the archetype of all logical paradoxes, that of the Liar, are related closely is, of course, not only well known, but is a part of the common knowledge of the community of logicians. Indeed, almost every more or less formal treatment of the theorem makes a reference to this connection. Gödel himself remarked in the paper announcing his celebrated result :The analogy between this result and Richard's antinomy leaps to the eye;there is (...)
    Direct download (13 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Strengthened paradoxes.Laurence Goldstein & Leonard Goddard - 1980 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 58 (3):211 – 221.
  • Circular queue paradoxes - the missing link.L. Goldstein - 1999 - Analysis 59 (4):284-290.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Propositions First: Biting Geach's Bullet.M. J. Frápolli - 2019 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 86:87-110.
    To be a proposition is to possess propositional properties and to stand in inferential relations. This is the organic intuition, [OI], concerning propositional recognition. [OI] is not a circular characterization as long as those properties and relations that signal the presence of propositions are independently identified. My take on propositions does not depart from the standard approach widely accepted among philosophers of language. Propositions are truth-bearers, the arguments of truth-functions (‘not’, ‘or’, ‘and’, ‘if’), the arguments of propositional-attitude verbs (‘know’, ‘believe’, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Semantic Singularities: Paradoxes of Reference, Predication, and Truth, written by Simmons, K.George Englebretsen - 2020 - History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis 23 (2):499-506.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Comparative Taxonomy of Medieval and Modern Approaches to Liar Sentences.C. Dutilh Novaes - 2008 - History and Philosophy of Logic 29 (3):227-261.
    Two periods in the history of logic and philosophy are characterized notably by vivid interest in self-referential paradoxical sentences in general, and Liar sentences in particular: the later medieval period (roughly from the 12th to the 15th century) and the last 100 years. In this paper, I undertake a comparative taxonomy of these two traditions. I outline and discuss eight main approaches to Liar sentences in the medieval tradition, and compare them to the most influential modern approaches to such sentences. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Reflexivity: a source-book in self-reference.Steven James Bartlett (ed.) - 1992 - New York, N.Y., U.S.A.: Distributors for the U.S. and Canada, Elsevier Science Pub. Co..
    From the Editor’s Introduction: "The Internal Limitations of Human Understanding." We carry, unavoidably, the limits of our understanding with us. We are perpetually confined within the horizons of our conceptual structure. When this structure grows or expands, the breadth of our comprehensions enlarges, but we are forever barred from the wished-for glimpse beyond its boundaries, no matter how hard we try, no matter how much credence we invest in the substance of our learning and mist of speculation. -/- The limitations (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Insolubles.Paul Vincent Spade - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Note on 'Normalisation for Bilateral Classical Logic with some Philosophical Remarks'.Nils Kürbis - 2021 - Journal of Applied Logics 7 (8):2259-2261.
    This brief note corrects an error in one of the reduction steps in my paper 'Normalisation for Bilateral Classical Logic with some Philosophical Remarks' published in the Journal of Applied Logics 8/2 (2021): 531-556.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation