Switch to: References

Citations of:

The World as Will and Representation

New York: Dover Publications. Edited by Judith Norman, Alistair Welchman & Christopher Janaway (1958)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Kant’s Crucial Contribution to Euler Diagrams.Jens Lemanski - 2024 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 55 (1):59–78.
    Logic diagrams have been increasingly studied and applied for a few decades, not only in logic, but also in many other fields of science. The history of logic diagrams is an important subject, as many current systems and applications of logic diagrams are based on historical predecessors. While traditional histories of logic diagrams cite pioneers such as Leibniz, Euler, Venn, and Peirce, it is not widely known that Kant and the early Kantians in Germany and England played a crucial role (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Value, Affect, and Drive.Paul Katsafanas - 2016 - In Peter Kail & Manuel Dries (eds.), Nietzsche on Mind and Nature. Oxford University Press.
    Nietzsche associates values with affects and drives: he not only claims that values are explained by drives and affects, but sometimes appears to identify values with drives and affects. This is decidedly odd: the agent's reflectively endorsed ends, principles, commitments--what we would think of as the agent's values--seem not only distinct from, but often in conflict with, the agent's drives. Consequently, it is unclear how we should understand Nietzsche's concept of value. This essay attempts to dispel these puzzles by reconstructing (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Wittgenstein, Kant, Schopenhauer, and critical philosophy.Julian Young - 1984 - Theoria 50 (2-3):73-105.
  • Heidegger’s Heimat.Julian Young - 2011 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 19 (2):285 - 293.
    International Journal of Philosophical Studies, Volume 19, Issue 2, Page 285-293, May 2011.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Conversations with Rush Rhees : From the Notes of Rush Rhees.Ludwig Wittgenstein, Rush Rhees & Gabriel Citron - 2015 - Mind 124 (493):1-71.
    Between 1937 and 1951 Wittgenstein had numerous philosophical conversations with his student and close friend, Rush Rhees. This article is composed of Rhees’s notes of twenty such conversations — namely, all those which have not yet been published — as well as some supplements from Rhees’s correspondence and miscellaneous notes. The principal value of the notes collected here is that they fill some interesting and important gaps in Wittgenstein ’s corpus. Thus, firstly, the notes touch on a wide range of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Concepts, mystics and post-Kantians.F. C. White - 1993 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 71 (3):305 – 315.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A problem for causal theories of action.Mark Thomas Walker - 2003 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 84 (1):84–108.
    Philosophical accounts of "action" standardly take an action to be a doing which _satisfies some description that is semantically related to the content of a propositional attitude of the subject's which _explains why that doing occurred. Causal theories of action require that the explanation in question must involve the causation of action-doings by propositional attitudes (typically intentions, volitions, or combinations of belief and desire). I argue that there are actions whose status, as such, cannot be acknowledged by any causal theory, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Gaston Bachelard and his reactions to phenomenology.Anton Vydra - 2014 - Continental Philosophy Review 47 (1):45-58.
    In this essay, I show how the French philosopher of science, Gaston Bachelard, reacted to the idea of phenomenology at different stages of his philosophical development. During the early years, Kantianism (through a Schopenhauerian reading of Kant) had the greatest influence on his understanding of phenomenology. Even if he always considered phenomenology a valuable method, Bachelard believed that the term noumenon is necessary, not for a full description of reality, but for probing possible sources of reality. For him, phenomena are (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Beyond the myth of “self-domination”.Aleš Vrbata - 2014 - Human Affairs 24 (1):136-147.
    This paper deals with the theoretical concepts of image and imagery as used by the foremost imaginal psychologists. Attributing primary epistemological status to image and imagery, imaginal psychology school developed a new theory of image and imagery, questioning the older thesis on the derivative and secondary epistemological status of the image. Using Jung’s concept of the autonomous psyche of an essentially archetypal nature, Hillman started to question Jung’s concept of the Self as a central archetype symbolizing a sort of disguised (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On Science of Metaphors and the Nature of Systemic Reasoning.Vuk Uskokovic - 2009 - World Futures 65 (4):241-269.
    Scientific method is presented not as a means for investigating a true and objective character of universal reality, but as a metaphorical tool applied for mutual co-ordination of experiences. By acknowledging the co-orientational and metaphoric roots of science, religion, arts, and ordinary linguistic communications alike, potential for their fruitful interdependent application becomes apparent. References to the paradigms of constructivism and objectivism are drawn in parallel in outlining the tracks along which the proposed concept of co-creation of experiential qualities is arrived (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Suicide and Freedom from Suffering in Schopenhauer’s “Die Welt als Wille und Vorstellung”.Christopher Roland Trogan - 2013 - Open Journal of Philosophy 3 (1):5-8.
    Schopenhauer’s stance on suicide focuses on the possibility of achieving freedom from suffering through the denial of the individual will-to-life. Ultimately, Schopenhauer argues that suicide fails to achieve this freedom, primarily because it is an act of will that confirms, rather than denies, the will-to-life. Suicide, he argues, is a kind of contradiction in that it involves the individual will’s willfully seeking to exterminate itself as a way of escaping the wretchedness of willing. While Schopenhauer explicitly states that one possesses (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Horizons, PIOs, and Bad Faith.James Tartaglia - 2012 - Philosophy and Technology 25 (3):345-361.
    I begin by comparing the question of what constitutes continuity of Personal Identity Online (PIO), to the traditional question of whether personal identity is constituted by psychological or physical continuity, bringing out the compelling but, I aim to show, ultimately misleading reasons for thinking only psychological continuity has application to PIO. After introducing and defending J.J. Valberg’s horizonal conception of consciousness, I show how it deepens our understanding of psychological and physical continuity accounts of personal identity, while revealing their shortcomings. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Minimally Creative Thought.Dustin Stokes - 2011 - Metaphilosophy 42 (5):658-681.
    Creativity has received, and continues to receive, comparatively little analysis in philosophy and the brain and behavioural sciences. This is in spite of the importance of creative thought and action, and the many and varied resources of theories of mind. Here an alternative approach to analyzing creativity is suggested: start from the bottom up with minimally creative thought. Minimally creative thought depends non-accidentally upon agency, is novel relative to the acting agent, and could not have been tokened before the time (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Zarathustra’s metaethics.Neil Sinhababu - 2015 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 45 (3):278-299.
    Nietzsche takes moral judgments to be false beliefs, and encourages us to pursue subjective nonmoral value arising from our passions. His view that strong and unified passions make one virtuous is mathematically derivable from this subjectivism and a conceptual analysis of virtue, explaining his evaluations of character and the nature of the Overman.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Schopenhauer’s Aesthetics and Philosophy of Art.Sandra Shapshay - 2012 - Philosophy Compass 7 (1):11-22.
    This essay focuses on Schopenhauer’s aesthetics and philosophy of art, areas of his philosophy which have attracted the most philosophical attention in recent years. After discussing the subjective and objective aspects of aesthetic experience on his account, I shall offer interpretations of Schopenhauer’s theory of the sublime and solution to the problem of tragedy. In addition, I shall touch upon the liveliest interpretive debates concerning his aesthetic theory: the intelligibility of the “Platonic Ideas” as the objects of aesthetic experience and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Poetic intuition and the Bounds of sense: Metaphor and metonymy in Schopenhauer's philosophy.Sandra Shapshay - 2008 - European Journal of Philosophy 16 (2):211-229.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • ‘Obviously all this Agrees with my Will and my Intellect’: Schopenhauer on Active and PassiveNousin Aristotle'sDe Animaiii.5.Mor Segev - 2014 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 22 (3):535-556.
    In one of the unpublished parts of his manuscript titled the Spicilegia, Arthur Schopenhauer presents an uncharacteristically sympathetic reading of an Aristotelian text. The text in question, De anima III. 5, happens to include the only occurrence of arguably the most controversial idea in Aristotle, namely the distinction between active and passive nous. Schopenhauer interprets these two notions as corresponding to his own notions of the ?will? and the ?intellect? or ?subject of knowledge?, respectively. The result is a unique interpretation, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Art and the ‘Morality System’: The Case of Don Giovanni.Genia Schönbaumsfeld - 2013 - European Journal of Philosophy 23 (4):1025-1043.
    Mozart's great opera, Don Giovanni, poses a number of significant philosophical and aesthetic challenges, and yet it remains, for the most part, little discussed by contemporary philosophers. A notable exception to this is Bernard Williams's important paper, ‘Don Juan as an Idea’, which contains an illuminating discussion of Kierkegaard's ground-breaking interpretation of the opera, ‘The Immediate Erotic Stages or the Musical-Erotic’, in Either/Or. Kierkegaard's pseudonymous author's approach here is, in some respects, reminiscent of a currently rather fashionable narrative-inspired moral philosophy, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Kant and the Problem of Recognition: Freedom, Transcendental Idealism, and the Third-Person.Joe Saunders - 2016 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 24 (2):164-182.
    Kant wants to show that freedom is possible in the face of natural necessity. Transcendental idealism is his solution, which locates freedom outside of nature. I accept that this makes freedom possible, but object that it precludes the recognition of other rational agents. In making this case, I trace some of the history of Kant’s thoughts on freedom. In several of his earlier works, he argues that we are aware of our own activity. He later abandons this approach, as he (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • On Punishing Emotions.Brian Rosebury - 2003 - Ratio Juris 16 (1):37-55.
    This paper challenges recent influential arguments which would encourage legislators and courts to give weight to an assessment of the “evaluative judgements” expressed by the emotions which motivate crimes. While accepting the claim of Kahan and Nussbaum and others that emotions, other than moods, have intentional objects , and are not mere impulses which bypass cognition, it suggests the following criticisms of their analysis. First, the concept of an emotional “evaluative judgement” tends to elide the distinction between “judgements” that are (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The eternal present of Utopianism.José Eduardo Dos Reis - 2000 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 3 (2-3):44-55.
    (2000). The eternal present of Utopianism. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy: Vol. 3, The Philosophy of Utopia, pp. 44-55.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Nietzschean Self, by Paul Katsafanas.Bernard Reginster - 2017 - Mind 126 (504):1260-1267.
    _The Nietzschean Self_, by KatsafanasPaul. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016. Pp. 292.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Two dogmatists.Charles Pigden - 1987 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 30 (1 & 2):173 – 193.
    Grice and Strawson's 'In Defense of a Dogma is admired even by revisionist Quineans such as Putnam (1962) who should know better. The analytic/synthetic distinction they defend is distinct from that which Putnam successfully rehabilitates. Theirs is the post-positivist distinction bounding a grossly enlarged analytic. It is not, as they claim, the sanctified product of a long philosophic tradition, but the cast-off of a defunct philosophy - logical positivism. The fact that the distinction can be communally drawn does not show (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A foundation for presentism.Robert E. Pezet - 2017 - Synthese 194 (5):1809–1837.
    Presentism states that everything is present. Crucial to our understanding of this thesis is how we interpret the ‘is’. Recently, several philosophers have claimed that on any interpretation presentism comes out as either trivially true or manifestly false. Yet, presentism is meant to be a substantive and interesting thesis. I outline in detail the nature of the problem and the standard interpretative options. After unfavourably assessing several popular responses in the literature, I offer an alternative interpretation that provides the desired (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • ‘The Zone of the Carcass and the Knacker'-On Adorno's Concern with the Suffering Body.Mathijs Peters - 2013 - European Journal of Philosophy 23 (4):1238-1258.
    Adorno's moral philosophy is famously problematic. One of the main reasons for this is that it revolves around the moral addendum: a physical impulse of solidarity with suffering beings that, he argues, cannot and should not be rationalized. I show that, since this moral addendum remains vague and since Adorno's radical negativity forces him to dismiss as uncritical all other approaches to morality, he deliberately places his thought in danger of relapsing into irrationality. Most commentators therefore disagree about the manner (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Nietzsche on Rock and Stone: The Dead World, Dance and Flight.Graham Parkes - 2013 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 21 (1):20 - 40.
    (2013). Nietzsche on Rock and Stone: The Dead World, Dance and Flight. International Journal of Philosophical Studies: Vol. 21, No. 1, pp. 20-40. doi: 10.1080/09672559.2012.746273.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Technological Production of a Space for Art and Environmental Aesthetics.Roger Paden - 2010 - Environment, Space, Place 2 (2):45-62.
    This paper argues against evolutionary accounts of aesthetics by defending the idea that our fundamental aesthetic categories have undergone great changes in the last two millennia, in particular, during an “artistic revolution” that lasted from 1680 to 1830. This revolution was made possible by the development of a number of technologies of art that created a separate cultural space for this new invention. The attempt to extend this revolution to include the aesthetic appreciation of the natural environment is aided by (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Philip Walsh, skepticism, modernity and critical theory.Sudarsan Padmanabhan - 2006 - Human Studies 29 (3):405-412.
  • How can Searle avoid property dualism? Epistemic-ontological inference and autoepistemic limitation.Georg Northoff & Kristina Musholt - 2006 - Philosophical Psychology 19 (5):589-605.
    Searle suggests biological naturalism as a solution to the mind-brain problem that escapes traditional terminology with its seductive pull towards either dualism or materialism. We reconstruct Searle's argument and demonstrate that it needs additional support to represent a position truly located between dualism and materialism. The aim of our paper is to provide such an additional argument. We introduce the concept of "autoepistemic limitation" that describes our principal inability to directly experience our own brain as a brain from the first-person (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Expressive perception as projective imagining.Paul Noordhof - 2008 - Mind and Language 23 (3):329–358.
    I argue that our experience of expressive properties (such as the joyfulness or sadness of a piece of music) essentially involves the sensuous imagination (through simulation) of an emotion-guided process which would result in the production of the properties which constitute the realisation of the expressive properties experienced. I compare this proposal with arousal theories, Wollheim’s Freudian account, and other more closely related theories appealing to imagination such as Kendall Walton’s. I explain why the proposal is most naturally developed in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Metasystem transitions, memes, and cybernetic immortality.Elan Moritz - 1995 - World Futures 45 (1):155-171.
    Recently the Principia Cybernetica Project undertook a computer‐based collaborative effort to develop a unified system of philosophy. The philosophy and its implementation are explicitly based on evolutionary principles of variation and natural selection (VNS) and a fundamental type of emergence called MetaSystem Transition (MST) which increases the overall freedom and adaptivity of systems. MST, conceived and articulated by Turchin (1977), occurs when a control subsystem is replicated and integrated into a whole through a higher level VNS generated control subsystem. Turchin (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The theme of civilization and its discontents in Durkheim's division of labor: Philosophical assumptions and practical consequences.Stjepan G. Meštrovi - 1989 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 19 (4):443–456.
  • The ethical irrationality of the world: Weber and hindu ethics.Pratap Mehta - 2001 - Critical Horizons 2 (2):203-225.
    This paper argues that Weber ought to be read as a comparative ethicist who brings his German intellectual inheritance, especially Schopenauer and Nietzsche, to a dialogue with ethical traditions in India and China. It shows that Weber not only had a supple understanding of the tensions within Hindu ethics, his own account of value often closely corresponds to Hindu axiology and was enriched by an encounter with it.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Happiness Vs Contentment? A Case for a Sociology of the Good Life.Jordan McKenzie - 2016 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 46 (3):252-267.
    Despite the enormous growth in happiness research in recent decades, there remains a lack of consistency in the use of the terms happiness, satisfaction, contentment and well-being. In this article I argue for a sociologically grounded distinction between happiness and contentment that defines the former as positive affect and the latter as positive reflection. Contentment is therefore understood as a fulfilling relationship with the self and society and happiness involves pleasurable experiences. There is a history of similar distinctions in philosophy (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Real World Regained? Searle’s External Realism Examined.Douglas McDermid - 2004 - Kriterion - Journal of Philosophy 18 (1):1-9.
    In Mind, Language, and Society: Philosophy in the Real World, John Searle presents an uncompromising apologia for realism which is distinguished both by its lucidity and by its vigour. His basic strategy is to show that realists have at their disposal the resources needed to refute skeptics who allege that a mind-independent world is unknowable. In this paper, I reconstruct Searle´s principal pro-realist argument (Section 3), then argue that it is vitiated by its reliance on two unwarranted assumptions (Sections 4-6). (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Integral Spirituality, Deep Science, and Ecological Awareness.Thomas P. Maxwell - 2003 - Zygon 38 (2):257-276.
    There is a growing understanding that addressing the global crisis facing humanity will require new methods for knowing, understanding, and valuing the world. Narrow, disciplinary, and reductionist perceptions of reality are proving inadequate for addressing the complex, interconnected problems of the current age. The pervasive Cartesian worldview, which is based on the metaphor of the universe as a machine, promotes fragmentation in our thinking and our perception of the cosmos. This divisive, compartmentalized thinking fosters alienation and self-focused behavior. I aim (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • ‘I am LW’: Wittgenstein on the self1.James Marshall - 1999 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 31 (2):113-121.
  • Drawing the Line: Art versus Pornography.Hans Maes - 2011 - Philosophy Compass 6 (6):385-397.
    Art and pornography are often thought to be mutually exclusive. The present article argues that this popular view is without adequate support. Section 1 looks at some of the classic ways of drawing the distinction between these two domains of representation. In Section 2, it is argued that the classic dichotomies may help to illuminate the differences between certain prototypical instances of pornography and art, but will not serve to justify the claim that pornography and art are fundamentally incompatible. Section (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Passions and Disinterest: From Kantian Free Play to Creative Determination by Power, via Schiller and Nietzsche.Eli I. Lichtenstein - 2019 - Ergo: An Open Access Journal of Philosophy 6:249-279.
    I argue that Nietzsche’s criticism of the Kantian theory of disinterested pleasure in beauty reflects his own commitment to claims that closely resemble certain Kantian aesthetic principles, specifically as reinterpreted by Schiller. I show that Schiller takes the experience of beauty to be disinterested both (1) insofar as it involves impassioned ‘play’ rather than desire-driven ‘work’, and (2) insofar as it involves rational-sensuous (‘aesthetic’) play rather than mere physical play. In figures like Nietzsche, Schiller’s generic notion of play—which is itself (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Knowledge as Masculine Heroism or Embodied Perception: Knowledge, Will, and Desire in Nietzsche.Cynthia Kaufman - 1998 - Hypatia 13 (4):63 - 87.
    Two distinct doctrines of the will operate in Nietzsche. On one, each person has a will that grows out of their engagement with life. This view can be the basis for a feminist epistemology. On the other, the will must be stimulated through the creation of unattainable goals and games of seduction. This view of the will is misogynist, as it posits a self that must constitute for itself a dominated and silenced other.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Deriving Ethics from Action: A Nietzschean Version of Constitutivism.Paul Katsafanas - 2011 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 83 (3):620-660.
    This paper has two goals. First, I offer an interpretation of Nietzsche’s puzzling claims about will to power. I argue that the will to power thesis is a version of constitutivism. Constitutivism is the view that we can derive substantive normative conclusions from an account of the nature of agency; in particular, constitutivism rests on the idea that all actions are motivated by a common, higher-order aim, whose presence generates a standard of assessment for actions. Nietzsche’s version of constitutivism is (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Spirit-of-This-World Encounters Spirit-of-Tragedy: Wang Guowei and Schopenhauer through the Hermeneutical Lenses of Kierkegaard and Heidegger.David Jones & He Jinli - 2014 - Comparative and Continental Philosophy 6 (1):68-83.
    China's encounter with Western cultures since the late Qing was generally viewed as a one-side “borrowing” and a radical “break” from traditional culture. “Westernization” became the dominant characteristic of the descriptions and interpretations of modern Chinese culture. Although Wang's work on comparative Chinese and Western philosophical studies has received much attention, there has been little attention given to the problem of Western influences, the domination of which, when appraising Wang's thought has persisted for a long time and has caused many (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Lest We Forget: Free-Thought and the Environment.Kile Jones - 2010 - Human Affairs 20 (4):294-299.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The body of sublime knowledge: The aesthetic phenomenology of Arthur Schopenhauer.James Luchte - 2009 - Heythrop Journal 50 (2):228-242.
  • Wittgenstein's anthropologism in logic, philosophy, and the social sciences.Dale Jacquette - 1999 - Social Epistemology 13 (3 & 4):303 – 322.
  • Schopenhauer's proof that thing-in-itself is will.Dale Jacquette - 2007 - Kantian Review 12 (2):76-108.
    In a bold series of pronouncements, Arthur Schopenhauer maintains that the Kantian thing-in-itself is Will. The division between the world as Will and representation, with its impressive array of implications, is Schopenhauer's most important and distinctive contribution to metaphysics. To understand what Schopenhauer means by ‘Will’ as opposed to the empirical ‘will’, and his reasons for identifying thing-in-itself with Will, we must look in detail at two related arguments by which Schopenhauer proposes to link these concepts. The arguments appear in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Find the Word! — But Where?: Maturana’s ‘Coordination’ and Sartre’s ‘Reflection’ around Naming.Seiichi Imoto - 2015 - Frontiers in Psychology 6.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Unhappiness and Education: some lessons from Schopenhauer.J. T. Hyland - 1985 - Educational Studies 11 (3):219-229.
  • Dao and Process.Frank J. Hoffman - 2002 - Asian Philosophy 12 (3):197 – 212.
    This paper is about different types of silence, and about differing processes of philosophical investigation and sagely illumination. It is argued that the sagely Dao of wu wei leads to silence in the sense of no spoken words, and the philosophical way of proof leads to silence in the sense of no spoken words. So both proof and wu wei both lead to silence in the sense of no spoken words. Accordingly there is a type of silence that results from (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Back to truth: Knowledge and pleasure in the aesthetics of Schopenhauer.Paul Guyer - 2008 - European Journal of Philosophy 16 (2):164-178.