Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. On the Artist's Privileged Status.Mark Roskill - 1979 - Philosophy 54 (208):187 - 198.
    The topic of this paper is one more alluded to than actually studied, both in current philosophy of art and in the theory of criticism. There is a reason for this, which both clarifies the issue and suggests how it is to be approached. To suppose that the person responsible for a work of art has at least something interesting to say about it is only natural, and even commonplace. But granted this, the qualifications to be put on that assumption (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Wittgenstein, Kant, Schopenhauer, and critical philosophy.Julian Young - 1984 - Theoria 50 (2-3):73-105.
  • Ideals of rationality in dialogic.John Woods - 1988 - Argumentation 2 (4):395-408.
    Needed for such dialogue games as dialectic are appropriate standards of fairness and rationality. The rules of procedure of dialectic must describe a game playable by actual human participants. The present paper centers on certain idealizations of the dialectician that are not allowable.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Thesis: The phenomenon of embodied speech.Calvin Schrag - 1969 - World Futures 7 (4):2-27.
  • Ontology, semantics and philosophy of mind in Wittgenstein's tractatus: A formal reconstruction. [REVIEW]Gert Jan Lokhorst - 1988 - Erkenntnis 29 (1):35 - 75.
    The paper presents a formal explication of the early Wittgenstein's views on ontology, the syntax and semantics of an ideal logical language, and the propositional attitudes. It will be shown that Wittgenstein gave a language of thought analysis of propositional attitude ascriptions, and that his ontological views imply that such ascriptions are truth-functions of (and supervenient upon) elementary sentences. Finally, an axiomatization of a quantified doxastic modal logic corresponding to Tractarian semantics will be given.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Continuum, name and paradox.Vojtěch Kolman - 2010 - Synthese 175 (3):351 - 367.
    The article deals with Cantor's argument for the non-denumerability of reals somewhat in the spirit of Lakatos' logic of mathematical discovery. At the outset Cantor's proof is compared with some other famous proofs such as Dedekind's recursion theorem, showing that rather than usual proofs they are resolutions to do things differently. Based on this I argue that there are "ontologically" safer ways of developing the diagonal argument into a full-fledged theory of continuum, concluding eventually that famous semantic paradoxes based on (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Wittgenstein et le logicisme de Russell : Remarques critiques sur « A Mathematical Proof Must be Surveyable » de F. Mühlhölzer.Sébastien Gandon - 2012 - Philosophiques 39 (1):163-187.
    Ce texte discute certaines conclusions d’un article récent de F. Mülhölzer et vise à montrer que le logicisme russellien a les moyens de résister à la critique que Wittgenstein lui adresse dans la partie III des Remarques sur les fondements desmathématiques.This paper discusses some conclusions of a recent article from F.Mülhölzer. It aims at showing that Russell’s logicism has the means to overcome the criticisms Wittgenstein expounded in Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics, part III.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Operations and Truth‐Operations in the Tractatus.João Vergílio Gallerani Cuter - 2005 - Philosophical Investigations 28 (1):63-75.
    Formal series are associated with ascriptions of numbers. They are ordered by formal operations that, unlike negation and disjunction, are not truth-operations. In spite of this, they are required to build propositions involving generic reference to numbers, and are essential to the Tractarian version of the logicist project.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Wittgenstein's philosophical grammar: A neglected discussion of vagueness.Nadine Faulkner - 2009 - Philosophical Investigations 33 (2):159-183.
    In this paper I explore a neglected discussion of vagueness put forward by Wittgenstein in his Philosophical Grammar (1932–34). In this work, unlike Philosophical Investigations (1953), Wittgenstein not only discusses the venerable Sorites paradox but provides a novel conception of vagueness using an analogy with coin tossing and converging intervals. As he sees it, the problematic picture of vagueness arises because we conflate aspects of the functioning of vague concepts with those of non-vague ones. Thus, while we accept that vague (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Misunderstanding the Talk(s) of the Divine: Theodicy in the Wittgensteinian Tradition.Ondřej Beran - 2017 - Sophia 56 (2):183-205.
    The paper discusses the unique approach to the problem of evil employed by the Wittgensteinian philosophy of religion and ethics that is primarily represented by D. Z. Phillips. Unlike traditional solutions to the problem, Phillips’ solution consists in questioning its meaningfulness—he attacks the very ideas of God’s omnipotence, of His perfect goodness and of the need to ‘calculate’ God’s goodness against the evil within the world. A possible weakness of Phillips’ approach is his unreflected use of what he calls ‘our (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations