Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Judgement and the Epistemic Foundation of Logic.Maria van der Schaar (ed.) - 2012 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer.
    This compelling reevaluation of the relationship between logic and knowledge affirms the key role that the notion of judgement must play in such a review. The commentary repatriates the concept of judgement in the discussion, banished in recent times by the logical positivism of Wittgenstein, Hilbert and Schlick, and the Platonism of Bolzano. The volume commences with the insights of Swedish philosopher Per Martin-Löf, the father of constructive type theory, for whom logic is a demonstrative science in which judgement is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Dummett's mathematical antirealism.James Page - 1991 - Philosophical Studies 63 (3):327 - 342.
  • Verification, falsification, and the logic of enquiry.Peter Milne - 1991 - Erkenntnis 34 (1):23 - 54.
    Our starting point is Michael Luntley's falsificationist semantics for the logical connectives and quantifiers: the details of his account are criticised but we provide an alternative falsificationist semantics that yields intuitionist logic, as Luntley surmises such a semantics ought. Next an account of the logical connectives and quantifiers that combines verificationist and falsificationist perspectives is proposed and evaluated. While the logic is again intuitionist there is, somewhat surprisingly, an unavoidable asymmetry between the verification and falsification conditions for negation, the conditional, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Intuitionism: An introduction to a seminar. [REVIEW]Charles McCarty - 1983 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 12 (2):105 - 149.
  • Five Observations Concerning the Intended Meaning of the Intuitionistic Logical Constants.Gustavo Fernández Díez - 2000 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 29 (4):409-424.
    This paper contains five observations concerning the intended meaning of the intuitionistic logical constants: (1) if the explanations of this meaning are to be based on a non-decidable concept, that concept should not be that of `proof"; (2) Kreisel"s explanations using extra clauses can be significantly simplified; (3) the impredicativity of the definition of → can be easily and safely ameliorated; (4) the definition of → in terms of `proofs from premises" results in a loss of the inductive character of (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Montague’s Paradox, Informal Provability, and Explicit Modal Logic.Walter Dean - 2014 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 55 (2):157-196.
    The goal of this paper is to explore the significance of Montague’s paradox—that is, any arithmetical theory $T\supseteq Q$ over a language containing a predicate $P$ satisfying $P\rightarrow \varphi $ and $T\vdash \varphi \,\therefore\,T\vdash P$ is inconsistent—as a limitative result pertaining to the notions of formal, informal, and constructive provability, in their respective historical contexts. To this end, the paradox is reconstructed in a quantified extension $\mathcal {QLP}$ of Artemov’s logic of proofs. $\mathcal {QLP}$ contains both explicit modalities $t:\varphi $ (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • From the Knowability Paradox to the existence of proofs.W. Dean & H. Kurokawa - 2010 - Synthese 176 (2):177 - 225.
    The Knowability Paradox purports to show that the controversial but not patently absurd hypothesis that all truths are knowable entails the implausible conclusion that all truths are known. The notoriety of this argument owes to the negative light it appears to cast on the view that there can be no verification-transcendent truths. We argue that it is overly simplistic to formalize the views of contemporary verificationists like Dummett, Prawitz or Martin-Löf using the sort of propositional modal operators which are employed (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Elementary realizability.Zlatan Damnjanovic - 1997 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 26 (3):311-339.
    A realizability notion that employs only Kalmar elementary functions is defined, and, relative to it, the soundness of EA-(Π₁⁰-IR), a fragment of Heyting Arithmetic (HA) with names and axioms for all elementary functions and induction rule restricted to Π₁⁰ formulae, is proved. As a corollary, it is proved that the provably recursive functions of EA-(Π₁⁰-IR) are precisely the elementary functions. Elementary realizability is proposed as a model of strict arithmetic constructivism, which allows only those constructive procedures for which the amount (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Explicit provability and constructive semantics. [REVIEW]Jeremy D. Avigad - 2002 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 8 (3):432-432.
  • Explicit provability and constructive semantics.Sergei N. Artemov - 2001 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 7 (1):1-36.
    In 1933 Godel introduced a calculus of provability (also known as modal logic S4) and left open the question of its exact intended semantics. In this paper we give a solution to this problem. We find the logic LP of propositions and proofs and show that Godel's provability calculus is nothing but the forgetful projection of LP. This also achieves Godel's objective of defining intuitionistic propositional logic Int via classical proofs and provides a Brouwer-Heyting-Kolmogorov style provability semantics for Int which (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   112 citations