Skip to main content

Attitudes, Content and Identity: A Dynamic View

  • Chapter
  • 228 Accesses

Part of the book series: Philosophical Studies Series ((PSSP,volume 69))

Abstract

In this paper I shall be dealing with Frege’s puzzle, which is a common topic nowadays within philosophy of language and mind. It amounts to the following question: how is it possible for anyone, e.g., Luke Skywalker, to understand and accept

  1. (1)

    Anakin Skywalker does not serve the emperor

without accepting — indeed, emphatically denying —

  1. (2)

    Darth Vader does not serve the emperor,

even though Anakin Skywalker is none other than Darth Vader? Also, how is it possible that whereas

  1. (3)

    Anakin Skywalker is Anakin Skywalker

is absolutely vacuous as its information value is nil,

  1. (4)

    Anakin Skywalker is Darth Vader

may contain the most fascinating discovery of a lifetime? A significant part of contemporary semantics and philosophy of language has centered on questions which differ from these only in the anecdotes that illustrate them. Though attempts to answer them have hardly ever taken into account that Frege’s questions in fact pose a problem concerning the nature of our beliefs (and other mental states), it has usually been assumed that these and other mental states have a fixed and standing content.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. I am assuming that there is only one New Theory of Reference, which is of course utterly false. I am claiming that this is so for the sake of argument.

    Google Scholar 

  2. S. Soames, “Direct Reference, Propositional Attitudes, and Semantic Content”, in N. Salmon & S. Soames, eds.: Propositions and Attitudes (Oxford University Press, 1988), p. 213.

    Google Scholar 

  3. This is not exact in every detail. A supporter of the New Theory of Reference naturally expects to explain out Frege’s data. However, she adds that those data have nothing to do not with a theory of the semantic content of a sentence but with a different one: a theory of the information conveyed by an utterance of that sentence in a conversation (S. Soames, loc. cit., #.5); a theory of ways of conveying or interpreting such information (N. Salmon, Frege’s Puzzle, Cambridge, MA: The MIT. Press, 1986, cap. 8);

    Google Scholar 

  4. or a theory of the information created by an utterance of the sentence (J. Perry, “Cognitive Significance and New Theories of Reference”, Noûs, 22 (1988), 1–18, esp. p.8.)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  5. The locus classicus is J. Fodor, “Propositional Attitudes”, in RePresentations. Philosophical Essays on the Foundations of Cognitive Science, Brighton, Sussex: Harvester Press, 1981.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Cfr., also B. Loewer, “The Role of ‘Conceptual Role Semantics’”, Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 23 (1982) 305–315, esp. p. 310f.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  7. For a range of cases compatible with the form of representationalism I have put forward, see W. Lycan, “Mental Content in Linguistic Form”, Philosophical Studies, 58 (1990) 147–154. My position in the text corresponds approximately to the conjunction of theses (A), (B), (C), (D) and/or (G) of Lycan’s.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. This should remind you of Jaakko Hintikka’s way out of the wreck of substitutivity of identity in indirect contexts in Knowledge and Belief. Cf. op. cit. (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1961), cap. 6. Cf. also “Quine on Quantifying In: A Dialogue”, The Intentions of Intentionality and Other New Models for Modalities, Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1975.

    Google Scholar 

  9. D. Kaplan, “Demonstratives, An Essay on the Semantics, Logic, Metaphysics, and Epistemology of Demonstratives and Other Indexicals”, in J. Almog, J. Perry & H. K. Wettstein, eds.: Themes from Kaplan, Oxford University Press, 1989; N. Salmon, Frege’s Puzzle, loc. cit., chap. 2 and Appendix C.

    Google Scholar 

  10. The first suggestion in this sense was made by H. Kamp and incorporated in his Discourse Representation Theory [= DRT]. For a paper on the intuitions behind this theory, see “Content, Thought and Communication”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, vol. LXXXV (1984/1985) 238–261. One important idea is this: “Not only do the utterances we produce, orally or in writing, often depend on context for their interpretation; they also do much to determine what the context is” (p. 240). My proposal of analysing cognitive meanings as functions from notional worlds to notional worlds benefits from Kamp’s idea. I do prefer to handle notional structures directly, since DRT depends heavily on a very strong form of representationalism, which explicitly welcomes a language of thought hypothesis. Because of this, several philosophers and semanticians are exploring a different form of dynamic semantics, one which does not commit itself to representationalism. See, for example, J. Groenendijk & M. Stokhof, “Dynamic Predicate Logic”, forthcoming Journal of Philosophical Logic vol. 14 (1991) 39–100;

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  11. J. Groenendijk & M. Stokhof, “Dynamic Montague Grammar”, ITLI Prepublication Series, University of Amsterdam, 1990;

    Google Scholar 

  12. F. Veltman, “Semántica de actualización”, Revista española de filosofía, no. 6 (1992); “Defaults in Update Semantics”, ITLI Prepublication Series, University of Amsterdam, 1991.

    Google Scholar 

  13. The distinction between internal and external reference to an individual by a (mental or extramental) file is put forward in J. Perry’s “Cognitive Significance and New Theories of Reference”, loc. cit., p. 13.

    Google Scholar 

  14. A Puzzle About Belief;, A. Margalit, ed.: Meaning and Use, Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1979. Also in N. Salmon & S. Soames, eds.: Propositions and Attitudes, loc. cit.“A Puzzle About Belief”, loc. cit., p. 268. Op. cit., p. 269.

    Google Scholar 

  15. J. Barwise & J. Perry, Propositions and Attitudes (Cambridge, MA: The MIT. Press, 1982), chap. 8.

    Google Scholar 

  16. I am alluding to one sort of case brought up by Kripke. See Op. cit., #. III.

    Google Scholar 

  17. “Cognitive Significance and New Theories of Reference”, loc. cit., p. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  18. D. Lewis, On the Plurality of Worlds (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1986), p. 59.

    Google Scholar 

  19. See Gerald Weissmann’s comments on Edmund Stone’s findings in “Aspirine”, Scientific American, March, 1991.

    Google Scholar 

  20. This one of the reasons why metalinguistic statements of the form is called “N” are so useful. See M. J. Wreen, “Socrates is called ‘Socrates’”, Linguistics and Philosophy, vol. 12 (1989), 359–371.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. “Rational Animals”, Dialectica, vol. 36 (1982) 318–327. See also “Thought and Talk”, Essays on Truth and Interpretation (Oxford University Press, 1984), p. 157. This theoretical position is known as Meaning Holism. For a critical analysis, see J. Fodor, Psychosemantics (Cambridge, MA: The MIT. Press, 1987), chapter 3.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Adjectives such as ‘vertical’ and ‘lateral’ have been introduced in this connection by Brian Loar, to illustrate the point I make in the main text. See B. Loar, Mind and Meaning (Cambridge University Press, 1981), chap. 4 and p. 121.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Others oppose ‘internal’ structural properties to external relations. Cf. M. Crimmins & J. Perry, “The Prince and the Phone Booth: Reporting Puzzling Beliefs”, Journal of Philosophy, vol. LXXXVI (1989), p. 687. As can be seen, I opt for a two-factor theory of meaning and mental content. For recent defences of such a position.

    Google Scholar 

  24. see N. Block, “Advertisement for a Semantics for Psychology”, in P. A. French, Th. E. Uehling & H. K. Wettstein, eds.: Midwest Studies in Philosophy 10, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1986;

    Google Scholar 

  25. J. Fodor, Psychosemantics loc. cit., chaps. 3& 4; F. Dretske, Explaining Behaviour (Cambridge, MA: The MIT. Press, 1988), #. 6.4;

    Google Scholar 

  26. C. McGinn, Mental Content (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1989), chapters 2 (section entitled “Dual Componency”) and 3 (section “Holism”);

    Google Scholar 

  27. P. Jacob, “Thoughts and Belief Ascriptions”, Mind and Language, vol. 2 (1987) #. V; “Externalism Revisited: Is There Such a Thing as Narrow Content?”, Philosophical Studies, 60 (1990) 143–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  28. This idea is inspired by a comment made by R. Stalnaker in “Indexical Belief”, Synthese, 49 (1981) 129–151, esp. p. 139.

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  29. I am very grateful to Jean Stephenson who has steered me away from many errors in my English draft.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1996 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Acero, J.J. (1996). Attitudes, Content and Identity: A Dynamic View. In: Clark, A., Ezquerro, J., Larrazabal, J.M. (eds) Philosophy and Cognitive Science: Categories, Consciousness, and Reasoning. Philosophical Studies Series, vol 69. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-8731-0_7

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-8731-0_7

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-4710-6

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-8731-0

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics