Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-t5pn6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-18T12:43:52.160Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Lakatosian Consolations for Economics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 December 2008

Alexander Rosenberg
Affiliation:
Syracuse University

Extract

The F-twist is giving way to the methodology of scientific research programs. Milton Friedman's “Methodology for Economics” is being supplanted as the orthodox rationale for neoclassical economics by Imre Lakatos' account of scientific respectability. Friedman's instrumentalist thesis that theories are to be judged by the confirmation of their consequences and not the realism of their assumptions has long been widely endorsed by economists, under Paul Samuelson's catchy rubric “the F-twist.” It retains its popularity among economists who want no truck with methodology, but among the increasing number of able economists who are writing on methodology the F-twist has been surrendered, not so much because these writers have decided it is false, as because something better has finally come along.

Type
Review Essay
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1986

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Becker, G. 1976. The Economic Approach to Human Behavior. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blaug, Mark. 1980. The Methodology of Economics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Cross, R. 1982. “The Duhem-Quine Thesis, Lakatos, and the Appraisal of Theories in Macroeconomics.” Economic Journal 92: 320–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feyerabend, Paul. 1975. Against Method. London: New Left Books/Verso.Google Scholar
Friedman, Milton. 1953. Essays in Positive Economics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Goodman, Nelson. 1955. Fact, Fiction and Forecast. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.Google Scholar
Goodwin, C. 1980. “Towards a Theory of the History of Economics.” History of Political Economy 12: 610–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hands, D. Wade. 1984. “What Economics Is Not: An Economist's Response to Rosenberg.” Philosophy of Science 51: 495503.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hempel, Carl Gustav. 1965. Aspects of Scientific Explanation. New York: MacMillan.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas. 1962. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Lakatos, Imre. 1978. The Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lakatos, Imre. 1963. “Proofs and Refutations.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 14: 1117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lakatos, Imre, and Musgrave, Alan. 1970. Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Latsis, Spiro. 1976. Method and Appraisal in Economics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCloskey, Donald. 1983. “The Rhetoric of Economics.” Journal of Economic Literature 21: 481517.Google Scholar
Quine, W.V.O. 1953. “Two Dogmas of Empiricism.” In From a Logical Point of View. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Rosenberg, Alexander. 1979. “Can Economic Theory Explain Everything?Philosophy of Social Sciences 9: 509–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenberg, Alexander. 1983. “If Economics Isn't Science, What Is It?Philosophical Forum 14: 296314.Google Scholar
Rosenberg, Alexander. Forthcoming. “What Rosenberg's Philosophy of Economics Is Not.” Philosophy of Science.Google Scholar
Weintraub, E. Roy. 1985. General Equilibrium Analysis: Studies in Appraisal. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar