Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-dnltx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-17T20:07:11.631Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Anthropology of Misfortune and Cognitive Science. Examples from the Ivory Coast Senufo1

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  26 September 2008

Nicole Alice Sindzingre
Affiliation:
Centre National de laRecherche Scientifique (CNRS) Paris

Abstract

This paper applies the approach developed by the congnitive sciences to a classical field of social anthropology—i.e., the analysis of represetations and behaviors relative to misfortune in “traditional” societies.

The initial argument is that the conceptual division and the modes of description and explanation of anthropology suffer from serious weaknesses: these concepts cannot serve to understand empirical phenomena (utterances and/or behavior); they rely on a confused and erroneous conception of the different domains involved and the causalities between them; and they use simplistic hypotheses about the existence and causal status of the entities that usually form the ultima ratio of anthropological reasoning (e.g., lineage organization, ancestors, witchcraft, etc.). These entities would directly “cause” other individual representations or behaviors. This simplification also affects the analysis of states of belief in these entities, to which individuals would supposedly “adhere”.

I argue here that the cognitivist approach, within a “methodological individualism” framework, provides a more adequate description of phenomena observed in the field. This enables the various levels and domains to be more finely defined. The analysis of “typical” utterances and inferences in a “tranditional” society, the Senufo of the Ivory Coast, is here used to clarify these anthropological problems. Two levels can be distinguished: (1) a priori representations, which are underdetermined, enabling them to occur within valid inferences; (2) perception and/or action, which obeys different cognitive constraints. The existential status of unobservable entities appearing in causal inferences is not equivalent (“symmetrical”) depending on whether they are determined as antecedent or consequent.

This paper suggests a theory of interpretive processes and beliefs having flexible references, because they are incomplete and domain-specific. It allows a comparison with facts observed in Western societies. It is also in contrast to the ordinary conception of religious states of belief — i.e., these states would be purely psychological, states of “adherence,” collective, autonomous, obligatory, part of a systemized set of knowledge; collective notions (of God, church, etc.) would here logically precede individual representations.

Type
Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1995

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

1

A first version of this paper was presented at a Wenner-Gren Foundation for Anthropological Research International Conference, “Analysis in Medical Anthropology,” Lisbon, 5–13 March, 1988.

References

Bogdan, Radu, ed 1986 Belif:Form, Content and Function Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Boyer, Pascal. 1994 “Cognitive Constraints on Cultural Representations: Natural Ontologies and Religious Ideas.” In Mapping the Mind: Domain Specificity in Cognition and Culture, edited by Hirschfeld, L. A. and Gelman, S. A. Cambridge Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Carey, Susan 1982 “Semantic Development: The State of the Art.” In Language Acquisition: The State of the Art, edited by Wanner, E. and Gleitman, L. R. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Davidson, Donald [1969] 1982; “How is Weakness of the Will Possible?” In his Essays on Actions and Events. Oxford Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Donnellan, Keith [1966] 1977 “Reference and Definite Descriptions” In Naming, Necessity and Natural Kinds, edited by Schwartz, Stephen P. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Flavell, John H. and Lee, Ross 1981 Social Cognitive Development Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Fodor, Jerry A. [1975] 1979 The Language of Thought Cambridge Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Fodor, Jerry A. 1981 Representations: Philosophical Essays on the Foundations of Cognitive Science Cambridge MIT Press.Google Scholar
Grice, H. Paul 1975 “Logic and Conversation.” In Synax and Semantics 3: Speech Acts, edited by Cole, P. and Morgan, J. L.. New York Academic Press.Google Scholar
Holland, John. H., Holyoak, Keith, Nisbett, Richard and Thagard, Paul R.. 1986 Processes of Inference, Learning and Discovery Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Horton, Robin. 1982 “Tradition and Modernity Revisited.” In Rationality and Relativism, Hollis, M. and Lukes, S.. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Kahnemann, Daniel, Slovic, Paul and Tversky, Amos, eds 1982 Judgments under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kripke, Saül 1972 “Naming and Necessity.” In The semantics of Natural Language, edited by Davidson, D. and Harman, G Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
Needham, Rodney 1972 Belief, Language and Experience Oxford Blackwell.Google Scholar
Neisser, Ulric ed. 1982 Memory Observed: Remembering in Natural Contexts San Francisco.: Freeman.Google Scholar
Putnam, Hilary 1962 “The Analytic and the synthetic.” In Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 3, edited by Feigl, H. and Maxwell, G.. Minneapolis University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Putnam, Hilary 1975 “The Meaning of Meaning.” In Language, Mind and Knowledge: Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 7, edited by Gunderson, K.. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Rosch, Eleanor 1978 “Principles of Categorization” In Cognition and Categorization, edited by Rosch, E. and Lloyd, B. Hillsdale L. Erlbaum.Google Scholar
Searle, John 1984 Minds, Brains and Science London BBC — Reith Lectures.Google Scholar
Sindzingre, Nicole Alice 1981 Organisation lignagére et représentations de l'infortune chez les Fodonon(Senufo de Côte d'Ivoire), Thése de IIIe cycle. Paris: EHESS.Google Scholar
Sindzingre, Nicole Alice. 1984 “La nécessité du sens: l'explication de l'infortune chez les Senufo.” In Les sens du mal edited by, Augé, M. and Herzlich, C.. Paris Archives Contemporaines Harwood Academic Publishers.Google Scholar
Sindzingre, Nicole Alice 1985Healing Is as Healing Does: Pragmatic Resolution of Misfortune amoung the Senufo(Ivory coast).” In History and Anthropology 2: 3357.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Skorupski, John. 1976 Symbol and Theory: A Philosophical Study of the Theories of Religion in Social Anthropology Cambridge Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sperber, Dan 1985a. On Anthropological knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sperber, Dan. 1985b. “Anthropology and Psychology: Towards an Epidemiology of Representation.” Man 20: 7389.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sperber, Dan 1994 “The Modularity of Thought and the Epidemiology of Representions.” In Mapping the Mind: Domain Specificity in Cognition and Culture edited by, Hirschfeld, L. A., Gelman, S.. Cambridge Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sperber, Dan and Wilson, Deirdre. 1986. Relevance: Communication and Cognition Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Stich, Stephen. 1983 From Folk Psychology to Congnitive Science: The Case against Belief Cambridge: MIT Press, Bradford Book.Google Scholar