Skip to main content

Wang Yangming as a Virtue Ethicist

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Part of the book series: Dao Companions to Chinese Philosophy ((DCCP,volume 1))

Abstract

Three ideas are implicit in the title of this essay. To begin with, it is constructive to view Wang Yangming 王陽明 (1472–1529), widely acknowledged as the most influential Confucian thinker of the Ming dynasty, as a virtue ethicist. Second, because Wang has much in common with many other Neo-Confucian philosophers, the Neo-Confucian approach to ethics quite generally can be fruitfully understood as a type of virtue ethics. If this is true, then a third idea also follows, namely that Western virtue ethicists should pay attention to Wang and to Neo-Confucian philosophy, because here is a new (to the Western philosophers) source of thinking about ethics from which they may well have things to learn.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   259.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   329.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   329.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For a significant discussion in Chinese of early Confucianism and virtue ethics, see Chen (2002).

  2. 2.

    This is not to imply that virtue ethics has nothing to say about “right action.” Considerable effort has been spent by recent Western virtue ethicists to show that virtue ethics can help to guide action. The focus of the theories is not on action, however, but on the character of the agent.

  3. 3.

    Good sources on disparate approaches to virtue ethics include Crisp and Slote (1993) and Welchman (2006).

  4. 4.

    My characterization of virtue ethics here is influenced by Swanton (2003: 19, 26).

  5. 5.

    For most virtue ethicists, there is still room for reasoning about what to do. Some (following Aristotle) give reason a central place in their theories. Others (following Hume) do not, yet this does not mean that moral reactions are simply brute feelings, immune to discussion of which factors are (and are not) relevant to a proper reaction. For one discussion of these matters, see Hutton (2001).

  6. 6.

    In this regard, it is relevant that a number of scholars in recent years have argued that we should view classical Confucians as virtue ethicists. See, for example, Hutton (2001); Slingerland (2001); Van Norden (2007); Yu (2007); and Sim (2007).

  7. 7.

    See also the discussion of this theme in Huang and Wei (2007: 101).

  8. 8.

    These are admittedly deep waters and the interpretation I offer here is controversial. For extended exposition and defense, see Chapter 2 of Angle (2009).

  9. 9.

    By “single principle,” I have in mind something like the consequentialist maxim “Do that which maximizes good consequences.” That is, a “principle” is something that can be stated and applied to cases. This is certainly the most common understanding of “principle” in contemporary English-language philosophy, which is one reason why the old-fashioned translation of li as principle is so misleading.

  10. 10.

    Wang recognizes that it is possible to believe mistakenly that one’s feelings and thoughts (yi 意) are liangzhi 良知, though in response he simply instructs his students to apply more effort to introspecting the difference (Wang 1972: 114).

  11. 11.

    Mencius 2A.6 and 7B.31 respectively (Mencius 1970: 82 and 200).

  12. 12.

    Contrast Wang (1983: 319 [§254]), in which Wang discusses cases in which we “bear” things that we should not, and thus “harm coherence.”

  13. 13.

    Elsewhere I discuss issues surrounding situations involving apparent conflicts in much more detail, and argue that Neo-Confucians would have denied that sages face tragic dilemmas (Angle 2009: Chapter 6).

  14. 14.

    A reference to Mencius 2A.6.

  15. 15.

    Also from Mencius 2A.6, and see also Mencius 1A.7, where King Xuan exhibits similar feelings on seeing an ox being led to ritual slaughter. In addition, Mencius 7A.45 bears comparison with Wang: “A gentleman is sparing (ai 愛) with things but shows no benevolence toward them; he shows benevolence towards the people but not filial affection (qin 親)” (Mencius 1970: 192 slightly mod.). The chief difference with Wang is that the underlying sense of continuity emphasized by Wang—since all the feelings he identifies are aspects of “humaneness”—is very attenuated in Mencius.

  16. 16.

    Significant parts of this section draw on Angle (2005), though I have made changes to the presentation of the argument throughout.

  17. 17.

    Contrast Chan’s translation, which effaces zhi 志 completely (Wang 1983: 43).

  18. 18.

    See Chapter 5 of Ivanhoe (2002). Also see Ivanhoe (2000). Ivanhoe describes Zhu Xi’s approach to self-cultivation as “recovery.” Van Norden (2007) has argued that Zhu Xi combines a “discovery” model with elements from “development” and “reformation” models. These both contrast with the pure “discovery” model they see at work in Wang Yangming. I am suggesting here that Wang, too, must be seen as more of a mixed case.

  19. 19.

    On “congealing of the sage-essence,” see Wang (1983: 58). The terms “beautiful person” etc., come from Mencius 7B.25.

  20. 20.

    Chen Lai’s major Chinese-language study of Wang Yangming also puts some emphasis on what one could call a positive side to the process of self-cultivation, especially in the context of Wang’s doctrine of “extending liangzhi 至 良知”; see Chen (1991: 178–185).

  21. 21.

    For more discussion, see David Tien’s essay in this volume, Chen (1991: Chapter 5), and Angle (2005).

  22. 22.

    The parable of the tiger, cited by both the Cheng brothers and Zhu Xi—but not by Wang—makes this point explicitly (Graham: 1992: 80; Chen 1987: 247).

  23. 23.

    Nussbaum herself is not committed to the category of “virtue ethics,” and indeed her sources of philosophical inspiration are diverse. Nonetheless, much of her work is closely cognate with that of scholars who do identify as virtue ethicists. For other important sources of contemporary thinking about moral perception, see Murdoch (1970); Wiggins (1980); McDowell (1979); Sherman (1989); Blum (1991).

  24. 24.

    For an early discussion of this story, see Mencius 5A.2.

  25. 25.

    Wang expressed a similar idea when he explained that it is wrong to be attached to the idea that weeds are always bad, or flowers always good; one needs to follow universal coherence (as it applies to a given, particular situation) rather than following an inflexible rule (Wang 1983: §101).

  26. 26.

    Martha Nussbaum’s discussion of the similarities between creative response, in much the sense I am describing, and improvisational rather than score- or script-based performance, is helpful here. “The salient difference between acting from a script and improvising is that one has to be not less but far more keenly attentive to what is given by the other actors in a situation.” “[She] must suit her choice to the evolving story, which has its own form and continuity.” As in jazz improvisation, Nussbaum continues, “The perceiver who improvises morally is doubly responsible: responsible to the history of commitment and to the ongoing structures that go to constitute her context; and especially responsible to these, in that her commitments are forged freshly on each occasion, in an active and intelligent confrontation between her own history and the requirements of the occasion” (Nussbaum 1990: 94).

  27. 27.

    In light of my discussion of sorrow earlier in this essay, note that Tim’s reflection on how far his society needs to improve will be tinged with sorrow or grief; this does not alter the ease with which Tim-the-sage responds to the situation.

  28. 28.

    Michael Slote (2010) has highlighted Wang as an early anticipator of later Western sentimentalist virtue ethics, insofar as his idea of the feeling of forming one body with all things suggests the modern idea of empathy.

Bibliography

  • Angle, Stephen C. 2005. “Sagely Ease and Moral Perception.” Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy 5.1: 31–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Angle, Stephen C. 2009. Sagehood: The Contemporary Significance of Neo-Confucian Ethical and Political Philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press. (An effort to take Neo-Confucian philosophy—particularly that of Zhu Xi and Wang Yangming—seriously as contemporary philosophy.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Blum, Lawrence A. 1991. “Moral Perception and Particularity.” Ethics 101: 701–725. (An influential account of what “moral perception” can be: well-grounded and accessible.)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chan, Wing-tsit. 1963. A Sourcebook in Chinese Philosophy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chen, Chun. 1986. Neo-Confucian Terms Explained (The Pei-hsi tzu-i). Translated by Wing-tsit Chan. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chen, Lai 陳來. 1987. Research into Z hu Xi’s Philosophy 朱熹哲學研究. Beijing 北京: Shehui kexue chubanshe 社會科學出版社.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chen, Lai 陳來. 1991. The Border between Being and Nonbeing—The Spirit of W ang Yangming’s Philosophy 有無之境—王陽明哲學的精神. Beijing 北京: Renmin chubanshe 人民出版社. (A major contemporary interpretation of Wang Yangming’s philosophy.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Chen, Lai 陳來. 2002. “Ancient Virtue Ethics and the Special Characteristics of Early Confucian Ethical Learning” 古代德行倫理與早期儒家倫理學的特點. Hebei Academic Journal 河北學刊, 22.6: 31–39. (Discusses the transition from pre-Analects treatment of virtues, to the unified account centering on ren 仁 in the Analects.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Crisp, Roger, and Slote, Michael (eds.). 1993. Virtue Ethics. New York: Oxford University Press. (A collection of many of the most important essays in the contemporary revival of virtue ethics.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Cua, Antonio S. 1998. Moral Vision and Tradition: Essays in Chinese Ethics. Washington: Catholic University of America Press. (A collection of a number of Cua’s groundbreaking papers. Cua’s work is challenging but very important, as he shows us at least one way to engage with Confucianism as live philosophy.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Graham, A.C. 1986. “What was New in the Ch’eng-Chu Theory of Human Nature?” In his Studies in Chinese Philosophy and Philosophical Literature. Singapore: Institute of East Asian Philosophies. (An insightful account of this fundamental aspect of Neo-Confucian theory.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Graham, A.C. 1992. Two Chinese Philosophers. La Salle: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huang, Weiyuan 黄維元, and Wei Hao 尉浩. 2007. “Analysis of Wang Yangming’s Category of ‘Virtue’ ” 王陽明“德”範疇論析. Lilun xuekan 理論學刊 159.5: 101–103.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutton, E.L. 2001. Virtue and Reason in the Xunzi. PhD. Disseratation. Stanford University. (Hutton’s dissertation is important for its sustained effort at thinking through how “virtue ethics” should be understood in general, and then applying this framework to a Confucian thinker.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Ivanhoe, Philip J. 2000. Confucian Moral Self Cultivation. Indianapolis: Hackett. (A remarkable amount of information, based on careful interpretations, is presented in this slim volume. An excellent introduction to Classical Confucianism and Neo-Confucianism.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Ivanhoe, Philip J. 2002. Ethics in the Confucian Tradition: The Thought of Mencius and Wang Yangming. Indianapolis: Hackett. (Among other things, a detailed study of important themes in Wang Yangming. Required reading.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Mencius. 1970. Mencius, translated by D.C. Lau. Harmondsworth: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, John. 1979. “Virtue and Reason.” The Monist 62.3: 331–350. (Highly influential formulation of virtue ethics.)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murdoch, Iris. 1970. The Sovereignty of the Good. New York: Routledge. (Early and insightful approach to virtue ethics, drawing loosely on Plato; many themes resonate with Wang Yangming’s concerns.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, Martha. 1990. “The Discernment of Perception: An Aristotelian Conception of Private and Public Rationality.” In her Love’s Knowledge: Essays on Philosophy and Literature. Oxford: Oxford University Press. (There is a great deal of insight in this somewhat sprawling essay.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Sherman, Nancy. 1989. The Fabric of Character: Aristotle’s Theory of Virtue. Oxford: Oxford University Press. (An excellent starting place for understanding Aristotle’s virtue ethics.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Sim, May. 2007. Remastering Morals with Aristotle and Confucius. New York: Cambridge University Press. (A demonstration that Aristotle and Confucius can fruitfully engage with one another; chapters focus on methodology, the mean, political philosophy, and other themes.)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Slingerland, Edward. 2001. “Virtue Ethics, the Analects, and the Problem of Commensurability.” Journal of Religious Ethics 29.1: 97–125. (An argument that early Confucianism contains a virtue ethics.)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Slote, Michael. 2010. “The Mandate of Empathy.” Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy 11.3. (A leading Western virtue ethicist takes a comparative perspective, and finds much to like in Wang Yangming.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Swanton, Christine. 2003. Virtue Ethics: A Pluralistic View. Oxford: Oxford University Press. (A sophisticated and distinctive theory of virtue ethics, full of riches that resonate with Neo-Confucian ideas.)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Van Norden, Bryan W. 2007. Virtue Ethics and Consequentialism in Early Chinese Philosophy. New York: Cambridge University Press. (Among other things, lays out a framework for thinking of early Confucianism as virtue ethics; discusses contrasts between early and Neo-Confucian ideas; and sketches what a Neo-Mencian virtue ethics might look like.)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wang, Yangming. 1963. Instructions for Practical Living, translated by Wing-tsit Chan. New York: Columbia University Press. (A complete translation of Wang Yangming’s chief work, with important supplementary material. In general quite reliable.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Wang, Yangming. 1972. The Philosophical Letters of Wang Yang-ming, translated by Julia Ching. Canberra: Australian National University Press. (Splendid translation of those of Wang Yangming’s letters with philosophical content, arranged chronologically. Highly recommended.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Wang, Yangming. 1983. Record of Practicing What Has Been Transmitted with Detailed Annotations and Collected Commentary 傳習錄詳註集評. Taibei 臺北: Xuesheng shuju 學生書局.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wang, Yangming. 1985. Complete Writings of Wang Yangming 陽明全書. Shanghai 上海: Shanghai guji chubanshe 上海古籍出版社.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wang, Yangming. 1992. Complete Works of Wang Yangming 王陽明全集. Shanghai 上海: Shanghai guji chubanshe 上海古籍出版社.

    Google Scholar 

  • Welchman, Jennifer, ed. 2006 The Practice of Virtue: Classic and Contemporary Readings in Virtue Ethics. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiggins, David. 1980. “Deliberation and Practical Reason.” In Amélie Oksenberg Rorty (ed.), Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. (Dense but influential account of the role of perception in Aristotle’s ethics.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Yu, Jiyuan. 2007. The Ethics of Confucius and Aristotle: Mirrors of Virtue. New York: Routledge. (A systematic comparison between Aristotle’s key works and the Four Books of classical Confucianism, stressing the ways in which both sides offer quite similar versions of virtue ethics. Controversial in some places but stimulating throughout.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Zhu, Xi 朱熹. 1997. Topically Arranged Conversations of Master Zhu 朱子語類. Changsha 長沙: Yuelu shushe 岳麓書社.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Stephen C. Angle .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2010 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Angle, S.C. (2010). Wang Yangming as a Virtue Ethicist. In: Makeham, J. (eds) Dao Companion to Neo-Confucian Philosophy. Dao Companions to Chinese Philosophy, vol 1. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-2930-0_15

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics