Skip to main content
Log in

Singular thoughts and singular propositions

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

A singular thought about an object o is one that is directly about o in a characteristic way—grasp of that thought requires having some special epistemic relation to the object o, and the thought is ontologically dependent on o. One account of the nature of singular thought exploits a Russellian Structured Account of Propositions, according to which contents are represented by means of structured n-tuples of objects, properties, and functions. A proposition is singular, according to this framework, if and only if it contains an object as a constituent. One advantage of the framework of Russellian Structured propositions is that it promises to provide a metaphysical basis for the notion of a singular thought about an object, grounding it in terms of constituency. In this paper, we argue that the attempt to ground the peculiar features of singular thoughts in terms of metaphysical constituency fails, and draw some consequences of our discussion for other debates.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. “A singular proposition is a proposition that is about one of its own components by virtue of containing it.” (Salmon 2005, p. 419).

  2. Though see Boer and Lycan (1986) for criticism of the view that ordinary attributions of knowing-wh are necessary and sufficient singular thought.

  3. See Evans (1982, p. 44) and Potter (2008), p. 55) for more discussion.

  4. Although this consensus is certainly not universal; see e.g. Jeshion (2002).

  5. Again, this consensus is not universal. Alvin Plantinga (see Plantinga (1983)) and Thomas Crisp (see Crisp (2003)) have rejected the object dependence of singular propositions. In each case, the rejection of object dependence is motivated by puzzles concerning the truth-value of singular thoughts at worlds or times in which the objects these singular propositions are about do not exist. Perhaps a “truth in/truth at” distinction akin to the one suggested by Adams (1981), Fine (1985), and more recently developed by Jeff King (King (2007), can be used to resolve the puzzles that motivate Plantinga and Crisp to reject the object dependence of singular thought.

  6. For example, on the theory in King (2007, Chapter 2), it would be a proposition in which an object occurred as one of the relata of the propositional relation of that proposition.

  7. Note that despite Kaplan’s attraction to a structured approach to propositions, he gives his formal semantics in the standard possible world framework and explicitly states that the structured approach is not a part of his official theory (p. 496).

  8. Matters are obscured somewhat by the fact that “actual” and “actually” appear to have a purely rhetorical use as an intensifier—as in “I am actually a philosopher”. Used in this way, “actually” does not appear to contribute to semantic content. Soames (2007) argues that in fact “actually” is not ambiguous, and its role as a rigidifier explains its pragmatic role as an intensifier.

  9. More specifically, she grants that what is said by an utterance of “Mount Everest is tall” has an interest-relative profile; it could only be true in a world in which there are people or interests. But she argues that in counterfactual evaluation, we keep certain facts fixed, which has the effect of rigidifying on the relevant interests. Then she argues that Stanley “exploits our correct judgment” about the counterfactual to make false conclusions about the what-is-said claims.

  10. Her first point is that on an unstructured conception of content, there is no room to make the sort of objection involving epistemic involvement that Stanley levels against her interest-relative account of vagueness. We disagree with this claim, but discussion of it will take us too far afield of our topic.

  11. Another point worth emphasizing is that Fara’s response to Stanley’s objection involves the particular details of the syntax and semantics of gradable adjectives. It is far from clear that other vague expressions (that is, almost all expressions) have a similar syntax and semantics. Insofar as her response to Stanley’s objection to her metaphysics is local to the details of gradable adjectives, it is therefore unsatisfying.

  12. We owe this argument to Timothy Williamson (p.c.).

  13. This is not Salmon’s distinction, introduced in the quote above, between immediate and mediate constituency. Presumably, grasp of the proposition that it is not the case that Hannah is a philosopher requires acquaintance with Hannah, even though Hannah is not an immediate constituent of the proposition that it is not the case that Hannah is a philosopher.

  14. One fruitful avenue to explore would begin with the account of the paradox in King (2007, Chap. 7).

  15. We are grateful to Jeffrey King, Ian Proops, Timothy Williamson, and audiences at St. Andrews University and Oxford University for discussion.

References

  • Adams, R. (1981). Actualism and thisness. Synthese, 49, 3–41.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boer S., & Lycan W. (1986). Knowing who. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. (1977). Belief de re. Journal of Philosophy, 75, 119–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crisp, T. (2003). Presentism. In M. Loux & D. Zimmerman (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of metaphysics (pp. 211–245). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dowty, D., Wall, R., & Peters, S. (1981). Introduction to montague semantics. Boston: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, G. (1982). The varieties of reference. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fara, D. G. (2000). Shifting sands: An interest-relative theory of vagueness. Philosophical Topics, 28(1), 45–81. (Published under the name ‘Delia Graff’).

    Google Scholar 

  • Fara, D. G. (2008). Profiling interest relativity. Analysis, 68(4), 326–335.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (1985). Plantinga on the reduction of possibilist discourse. In J. Tomberlin & P. van Inwagen (Eds.), Alvin Plantinga (pp. 145–186). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeshion, R. (2002). Acquaintanceless de re belief. In J. K. Campbell, M. O’Rourke, & D. Shier (Eds.), Meaning and truth. New York: Seven Bridges.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. (1989a). Demonstratives. In Themes from Kaplan (pp. 481–563), Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Kaplan, D. (1989b). Afterthoughts. In Themes from Kaplan (pp. 565–614), Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • King, J. (2007). The nature and structure of content. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1972). Naming and necessity. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1984). De re senses. Philosophical Quarterly, xxxiv, 283–294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1986). Singular thought and the extent of inner space. In P. Pettit & J. McDowell (Eds.), Subject, thought and context. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montague, R. (1973). The proper treatment of quantification in ordinary English. (Reprinted in Formal Philosophy. Selected Papers by Richard Montague, by R. Thomason, Ed., New Haven: Yale University Press).

  • Plantinga, A. (1983). On existentialism. Philosophical Studies, 44, 1–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Potter, M. (2008). “The birth of analytic philosophy” The Routledge companion to twentieth century philosophy. London: Routledge Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prior, A. N., & Fine, K. (1977). Worlds, times, and selves (pp. 116–161). Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Proops, I. (Forthcoming). Logical atomism in Russell and Wittgenstein. In M. McGinn (Ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Wittgenstein.

  • Russell, B. (1903, reprinted 1996). The principles of mathematics. London: W.W. Norton Press.

  • Salmon, N. (1986). Frege’s puzzle. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, N. (2005). On designating. (Reprinted in Metaphysics, mathematics, and meaning, by N. Salmon (Ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press).

  • Salmon, N. (2007). About aboutness. European Journal of Analytic Philosophy, 3.2, 59–76.

    Google Scholar 

  • Soames, S. (2007). Actually. In M. Kalderon (Ed.), Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume LXXXI.

  • Stalnaker, R. (1988). Belief attribution and context. In R. Stalnaker (Ed.), Context and content. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Stalnaker, R. (2010). Merely possible propositions. In B. Hale & A. Hoffmann (Eds.), Modality: metaphysics, logic and epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Stanley, J. (2003). Context, interest-relativity, and the sorites. Analysis, 634, 269–280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J. (2005). Knowledge and practical interests. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jason Stanley.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Armstrong, J., Stanley, J. Singular thoughts and singular propositions. Philos Stud 154, 205–222 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-010-9532-1

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-010-9532-1

Keywords

Navigation