Skip to main content
Log in

Presuppositions for proportional quantifiers

  • Published:
Natural Language Semantics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Most studies of the so-called proportion problem seek to understand how lexical and structural properties of sentences containing adverbial quantifiers give rise to various proportional readings. This paper explores a related but distinct problem: given a use of a particular sentence in context, why do only some of the expected proportional readings seem to be available? That is, why do some sentences allow an asymmetric reading when other, structurally similar sentences seem to require a symmetric reading? Potential factors suggested in the literature include the distribution of donkey pronouns, certain uniqueness implications, and focus structures. I argue here that the use of an adverbial quantifier presupposes HOMOGENEITY: all individual situations that get lumped into a single case for the purposes of evaluating the quantification must agree on whether they satisfy the nuclear scope. For instance, in order for a token of Usually, if a farmer owns a donkey, he beats it to be felicitous when construed under a farmer-dominant asymmetric reading, the context must be consistent with the proposition that each farmer either beats all or none of his donkeys. Thus proportional sentences are indeed systematically ambiguous, but only some readings will be felicitous in a given context.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Barker, Chris: 1995, Possessive Descriptions, CSLI Publications, Stanford, Cal.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bäuerle, Rainer and U. Egli: 1985, ‘Anapher, Nominalphrase und Eselssätze’, Papier 105 des Sonderforschungsbereichs 99, Universität Konstanz.

  • Chierchia, Gennaro: 1992, ‘Anaphora and Dynamic Binding’, Linguistics and Philosophy 15(2), 111–183.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gawron, Jean Mark, JohnNerbonne and StanleyPeters: 1991, ‘The Absorption Principle and E-Type Anaphora’, in J. Barwise et al. (eds.), Situation Theory and Its Applications, vol. 2, CSLI Publications, Stanford, Cal.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heim, Irene: 1982, The Semantics of Definite and Indefinite Noun Phrases, Ph.D. dissertation, University of Massachusetts, Amherst.

  • Heim, Irene: 1990, ‘E-Type Pronouns and Donkey Anaphora’, Linguistics and Philosophy 13, 137–177.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacobs, Joachim: 1991, ‘Focus Ambiguities’, Journal of Semantics 8, 1–36.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kadmon, Nirit: 1987, On Unique and Non-unique Reference and Asymmetric Quantification, Ph.D. dissertation, University of Massachusetts, Amherst.

  • Kadmon, Nirit: 1990, ‘Uniqueness’, Linguistics and Philosophy 13, 273–324.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kanazawa, Makoto: 1994, ‘Weak vs. Strong Readings of Donkey Sentences and Monotonicity Inference in a Dynamic Setting’, Linguistics and Philosophy 17, 109–158.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kang, YoungEun Yoon: 1994, Weak and Strong Interpretations of Quantifiers and Definite NPs in English and Korean, Ph.D. dissertation, University of Texas at Austin.

  • Kratzer, Angelika: 1989, ‘An Investigation of the Lumps of Thought’, Linguistics and Philosophy 12, 607–653.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer, Angelika: 1995, ‘Stage-Level and Individual-Level Predicates’, in G. N. Carlson and F. J. Pelletier (eds.), The Generic Book, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp. 125–175.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krifka, Manfred: 1992, ‘A Framework for Focus-Sensitive Quantification’, in C. Barker and D. Dowty (eds.), Proceedings of the Second Conference on Semantics and Linguistic Theory, OSUWPL vol. 40, Department of Linguistics, Ohio State University, Columbus, pp. 215–236.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, David: 1975, ‘Adverbs of Quantification’, in E. Keenan (ed.), Formal Semantics, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp. 3–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Partee, Barbara: 1984, ‘Nominal and Temporal Anaphora’, Linguistics and Philosophy 7, 243–286.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, Craige: 1995, ‘Domain Restriction in Dynamic Semantics’, in E. Bach, E. Jelinek, A. Kratzer and B. H. Partee (eds.), Quantification in Natural Languages, Studies in Linguistics and Philosophy vol. 54, Kluwer, Dordrecht. pp. 661–700.

    Google Scholar 

  • Root, Rebecca: 1985, The Semantics of Anaphora in Discourse, Ph.D. dissertation, University of Texas at Austin.

  • Rooth, Mats: 1987, ‘NP Interpretation in Montague Grammer, File Change Semantics, and Situation Semantics’, in P. Gärdenfors (ed.), Generalized Quantifiers, Reidel, Dordrecht, pp. 237–268.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schubert, Lenhart K. and Francis Jeffry Pelletier: 1989, ‘Generically Speaking’, in G. Chierchia, B. H. Partee and R. Turner (eds.), Properties, Types and Meaning, vol. 2: Semantic Issues, pp. 193–268.

  • de Swart, Henriëtte: 1991, Adverbs of Quantification: A Generalized Quantifier Approach, Ph.D. dissertation, Rijksuniversiteit Groningen.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Additional information

I gratefully acknowledge specific comments and advice from Jeroen Groenendijk, Irene Heim, Makoto Kanazawa, Angelika Kratzer, Manfred Krifka, Peter Lasersohn, Stanley Peters, Craige Roberts, Martin Stokhof, Henriëtte de Swart, and two anonymous referees.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Barker, C. Presuppositions for proportional quantifiers. Nat Lang Seman 4, 237–259 (1996). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00372821

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00372821

Keywords

Navigation