Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-cfpbc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-16T17:58:21.363Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

It Must be True – But How Can it Be? Some Remarks on Panpsychism and Mental Composition

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  07 July 2010

Pierfrancesco Basile
Affiliation:
University of Bern, Switzerland

Abstract

Although panpsychism has had a very long history, one that goes back to the very origin of western philosophy, its force has only recently been appreciated by analytic philosophers of mind. And even if many still reject the theory as utterly absurd, others have argued that it is the only genuine form of physicalism. This paper examines the case for panpsychism and argues that there are at least good prima facie reasons for taking it seriously. In a second step, the paper discusses the main difficulty the theory has to face, the ‘composition problem’. This is the problem of explaining how the primitive experiences that are supposed to exist at the ultimate level of reality could give rise to the unified experience of a human being. What assumptions as to the nature of experience generate the composition problem? Is mental composition impossible in principle or do we simply lack at present any understanding of phenomenal parts and wholes?

Type
Papers
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Skrbina, D., Panpsychism in the West (Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press, 2005), 4Google Scholar; my emphasis.

2 McGinn, C., The Problem of Consciousness: Essays Towards a Resolution (Oxford: Blackwell, 1991)Google Scholar, 2n.

3 Searle, J., Mind: A Brief Introduction (Oxford-New York: Oxford University Press, 2004), 149–50Google Scholar.

4 Ibid., 150.

5 Ross, D. and Ladyman, J. (with Spurrett, D. and Collier, J.), Every Thing Must Go: Metaphysics Naturalized (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007), 1827Google Scholar.

6 Russell, B., Human Knowledge: Its Scope and Limits (London: Routledge, 1948), 240Google Scholar.

7 Chalmers, D., The Conscious Mind (Oxford-New York: Oxford University Press, 1996), 293Google Scholar.

8 Skrbina, D., ‘Transcending Consciousness: Thoughts on a Universal Conception of Mind’, Journal of Consciousness Studies 16:5 (2009), 81 and 84Google Scholar.

9 Dewey, J., Experience and Nature (New York: Dover, 1958), 3aGoogle Scholar.

10 Wittgenstein, L., Philosophical Investigations, edited by Anscombe, G. E. M. and Rhees, R. (Oxford: Blackwell, 1953), §390Google Scholar.

11 One truly major thinker who went so far as to ascribe experiences to all things is Spinoza. It is significant that this claim was not established empirically, but was inferred as a corollary of a general metaphysical theory established on a priori grounds. Specifically, given his substance metaphysics and the parallelism that goes with it, every mode of extension has its counterpart in a mode of thought. Thus, there must be of necessity a mental correlate to each physical thing. His metaphysical principles, he argues, ‘are completely general and do not pertain more to man than to other individuals, all of which, though in different degrees, are nevertheless animate’. Spinoza, B., Ethics, edited and translated by Curley, E. (London: Penguin Books, 1994), 2p13Google Scholar.

12 Whitehead, A. N., Process and Reality: An Essay in Cosmology, corrected edition by Griffin, D. R. and Sherburne, D. W. (New York: The Free Press, 1978), 83109Google Scholar.

13 James, W., The Principles of Psychology, Vol. I. (New York: Dover, 1950), 146Google Scholar.

14 Ward, J., ‘Mechanism and Morals: The World of Science and the World of History’ in Essays in Philosophy: with a Memoir by Olwen Ward Campell, edited by Sorley, W. R. and Stout, G. F. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1927), 247Google Scholar.

15 Strawson, G., ‘Real Materialism: Why Physicalism Entails Panpsychism’ in Consciousness and its Place in Nature: Does Physicalism Entail Panpsychism?, edited by Freeman, A. (Exeter: Imprint Academic, 2006), 1221Google Scholar.

16 Clayton, P., Mind and Emergence: From Quantum to Consciousness (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004), viGoogle Scholar; my emphasis.

17 An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, abridged and edited by John W. Yolton (London: Dent, 1994), IV. X. 11.

18 Ibid., 19; for a similar point, see Nagel, T., ‘Panpsychism’ in Mortal Questions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979), 194Google Scholar.

19 See P. Simons, ‘The Seeds of Experience’ in A. Freeman (ed.), Consciousness and its Place in Nature, op. cit., 148–49, for an objection along these lines.

20 As he has it, ‘we are cut off by our very cognitive constitution from achieving a conception of that natural property of the brain (or of consciousness) that accounts for the psychophysical link…the felt mystery comes from our own cognitive limitations, not from any objective eeriness in the world’. McGinn, C., ‘Can we solve the mind-body problem?’, Mind 98 (1989), 359Google Scholar.

21 C. McGinn, ‘Hard Questions. Comments on Galen Strawson’ in A. Freeman (ed.), Consciousness and its Place in Nature, op. cit., 98.

22 Nagel, T., The View from Nowhere (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986), 52Google Scholar.

23 Sprigge, T. L. S., The Vindication of Absolute Idealism (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1983), 128Google Scholar.

24 W. James, The Principles of Psychology, op. cit., 160.

25 P. Goff, ‘Experiences Don't Sum’ in A. Freeman (ed.), Consciousness and its Place in Nature, op. cit., 57.

26 Goff, P., ‘Can the panpsychist get around the combination problem?’ in Skrbina, D. (ed.), Mind that Abides: Panpsychism in the new millennium (Amsterdam-Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishing Company, 2009), 133Google Scholar.

27 Another limitation, already implicit in what has been said so far, is that the problem will be discussed with respect to consciousness' synchronic unity, as opposed to its unity over time.

28 James, W., A Pluralistic Universe: Hibbert Lectures at Manchester College on the Present Situation in Philosophy (London-Bombay-Calcutta: Longmans, Green, and Co., 1909), 192Google Scholar.

29 Ibid., 198–9.

30 Ibid., 200.

31 Hume, D., A Treatise of Human Nature, edited by Norton, D. F. and Norton, M. J. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), 137–8Google Scholar.

32 W. James, The Principles of Psychology, op. cit., 279n; see also 145 and 241.

33 W. James, A Pluralistic Universe, op. cit., 181.

34 Ibid., 212 and 214.

35 Using Samuel Alexander's little known but very apt terminology, ‘knowing’ our experiences means here apprehending them by way of ‘enjoyment’, simply by living through them as it were, rather than knowing them as one knows an object of contemplation. See his Space, Time and Deity: The Gifford Lectures at Glasgow, 1916–1918, Vol. I (London: MacMillan & Co., 1924), xiv.

36 For a critical assessment of phenomenal holism, see Dainton, B., Stream of Consciousness. Unity and Continuity in Conscious Experience (London and New York: Routledge, 2000), 181213Google Scholar and see his paper in this volume.

37 T. Nagel, The View from Nowhere, op. cit., 29.

38 T. Nagel, ‘Panpsychism’, op. cit., 193.

39 Leibniz, G. W., ‘Introduction to New Essays on the Human Understanding’, in The Monadology and Other Philosophical Writings, edited and translated by Latta, R. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1898), 370Google Scholar.

40 I would like to thank Leemon McHenry, Pauline Phemister and Galen Strawson for helpful comments on an earlier version of this paper.