Skip to main content
Log in

Understanding endogenously active mechanisms: A scientific and philosophical challenge

  • Original paper in Philosophy of Science
  • Published:
European Journal for Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Although noting the importance of organization in mechanisms, the new mechanistic philosophers of science have followed most biologists in focusing primarily on only the simplest mode of organization in which operations are envisaged as occurring sequentially. Increasingly, though, biologists are recognizing that the mechanisms they confront are non-sequential and the operations nonlinear. To understand how such mechanisms function through time, they are turning to computational models and tools of dynamical systems theory. Recent research on circadian rhythms addressing both intracellular mechanisms and the intercellular networks in which these mechanisms are synchronized illuminates this point. This and other recent research in biology shows that the new mechanistic philosophers of science must expand their account of mechanistic explanation to incorporate computational modeling, yielding dynamical mechanistic explanations. Developing such explanations, however, is a challenge for both the scientists and the philosophers as there are serious tensions between mechanistic and dynamical approaches to science, and there are important opportunities for philosophers of science to contribute to surmounting these tensions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Important predecessors of the new mechanistic philosophy of science are Wimsatt (1976, p. 671), who argued that “at least in biology, most scientists see their work as explaining types of phenomena by discovering mechanisms . . .” and Salmon (1984), who defended a “causal-mechanical view” that drew out the importance of causal relations but said little about what renders a set of causal processes into a mechanism.

  2. There are some important differences between the basic circadian mechanism in Drosophila and mammals, but it is largely conserved. This conservation facilitated the identification of parts of the mammalian mechanism, and the discovery of new components in the mammalian mechanism also supported comparable discoveries in Drosophila (see Bechtel, 2009).

  3. One might view the context-sensitive behavior of parts and operations as a reason to repudiate the project of decomposition. For reasons indicated below, I contend that the project of decomposition remains crucial to mechanistic biology. The context sensitivity of components can be accommodated by articulating the interaction between intrinsic features of components with processes external to them.

References

  • Abrahamsen, A., & Bechtel, W. (2011). From reactive to endogenously active dynamical conceptions of the brain. In T. Reydon & K. Plaisance (Eds.), Philosophy of behavioral biology. New York: Spinger.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aton, S. J., & Herzog, E. D. (2005). Come together, right…now: Synchronization of rhythms in a mammalian circadian clock. Neuron, 48(4), 531–534.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (2009). Generalization and discovery by assuming conserved mechanisms: Cross species research on circadian oscillators. Philosophy of Science, 76, 762–773.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Abrahamsen, A. (2005). Explanation: A mechanist alternative. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 36, 421–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Abrahamsen, A. (2009). Decomposing, recomposing, and situating circadian mechanisms: Three tasks in developing mechanistic explanations. In H. Leitgeb & A. Hieke (Eds.), Reduction and elimination in philosophy of mind and philosophy of neuroscience (pp. 173–186). Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Abrahamsen, A. (2010). Dynamic mechanistic explanation: Computational modeling of circadian rhythms as an exemplar for cognitive science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 41(3), 321–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Richardson, R. C. (1993/2010). Discovering complexity: Decomposition and localization as strategies in scientific research. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. 1993 edition published by Princeton University Press.

  • Boogerd, F., Bruggeman, F. J., Hofmeyr, J.-H., & Westerhoff, H. (Eds.). (2007). Systems biology: Philosophical perspectives. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bullmore, E., & Sporns, O. (2009). Complex brain networks: graph theoretical analysis of structural and functional systems. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 10(3), 186–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chemero, A. (2000). Anti-representationalism and the dynamical stance. Philosophy of Science, 67(4), 625–647.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (2007). Explaining the brain: What a science of the mind-brain could be. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darden, L. (2006). Reasoning in biological discoveries: Essays on mechanisms, interfield relations, and anomaly resolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Felleman, D. J., & van Essen, D. C. (1991). Distributed hierarchical processing in the primate cerebral cortex. Cerebral Cortex, 1, 1–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glennan, S. (1996). Mechanisms and the nature of causation. Erkenntnis, 44, 50–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glennan, S. (2002). Rethinking mechanistic explanation. Philosophy of Science, 69, S342–S353.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldbeter, A. (1995). A model for circadian oscillations in the Drosophila Period protein (PER). Proceedings of the Royal Society of London. B: Biological Sciences, 261(1362), 319–324.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gonze, D., Bernard, S., Waltermann, C., Kramer, A., & Herzel, H. (2005). Spontaneous synchronization of coupled circadian oscillators. Biophysical Journal, 89(1), 120–129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodwin, B. C. (1965). Oscillatory behavior in enzymatic control processes. Advances in Enzyme Regulation, 3, 425–428.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grebogi, C., Ott, E., & Yorke, J. A. (1987). Chaos, strange attractors, and fractal basin boundaries in nonlinear dynamics. Science, 238(4827), 632–638.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hardin, P. E., Hall, J. C., & Rosbash, M. (1990). Feedback of the Drosophila period gene product on circadian cycling of its messenger RNA levels. Nature, 343(6258), 536–540.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1965). Aspects of scientific explanation. In C. G. Hempel (Ed.), Aspects of scientific explanation and other essays in the philosophy of science (pp. 331–496). New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herzog, E. D., Aton, S. J., Numano, R., Sakaki, Y., & Tei, H. (2004). Temporal precision in the mammalian circadian system: A reliable clock from less reliable neurons. Journal of Biological Rhythms, 19(1), 35–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. M., & Craver, C. (2011). The explanatory force of dynamical and mathematical models in neuroscience: A mechanistic perspective.

  • Konopka, R. J., & Benzer, S. (1971). Clock mutants of Drosophila melanogaster. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences (USA), 89, 2112–2116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leloup, J.-C., & Goldbeter, A. (2000). Modeling the molecular regulatory mechanism of circadian rhythms in Drosophila. BioEssays, 22(1), 84–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leloup, J.-C., & Goldbeter, A. (2004). Modeling the mammalian circadian clock: Sensitivity analysis and multiplicity of oscillatory mechanisms. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 230(4), 541–562.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C. F. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67, 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noble, D. (2006). The music of life: Biology beyond the genome. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. C. (1984). Scientific explanation and the causal structure of the world. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Silver, R., LeSauter, J., Tresco, P. A., & Lehman, M. N. (1996). A diffusible coupling signal from the transplanted suprachiasmatic nucleus controlling circadian locomotor rhythms. Nature, 382(6594), 810–813.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. A. (1969). The sciences of the artificial. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smolen, P., Hardin, P. E., Lo, B. S., Baxter, D. A., & Byrne, J. H. (2004). Simulation of Drosophila circadian oscillations, mutations, and light responses by a model with VRI, PDP-1, and CLK. Biophysical Journal, 86(5), 2786–2802.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sporns, O., & Zwi, J. D. (2004). The small world of the cerebral cortex. Neuroinformatics, 2(2), 145–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strogatz, S. H. (2001). Exploring complex networks. Nature, 410(6825), 268–276.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • To, T.-L., Henson, M. A., Herzog, E. D., & Doyle, F. J., III. (2007). A molecular model for intercellular synchronization in the mammalian circadian clock. Biophysical Journal, 92(11), 3792–3803.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van den Pol, A. N. (1980). The hypothalamic suprachiasmatic nucleus of rat: Intrinsic anatomy. The Journal of Comparative Neurology, 191(4), 661–702.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vasalou, C., Herzog, E. D., & Henson, M. A. (2009). Small-world network models of intercellular coupling predict enhanced synchronization in the suprachiasmatic nucleus. Journal of Biological Rhythms, 24(3), 243–254.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Watts, D., & Strogratz, S. (1998). Collective dynamics of small worlds. Nature, 393(440–442).

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, M. (2005). Philosophy of experimental biology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Welsh, D. K., Engle, E. M. R. A., Richardson, G. S., & Dement, W. C. (1986). Precision of circadian wake and activity onset timing in the mouse. Journal of Comparative Physiology. A, Neuroethology, Sensory, Neural, and Behavioral Physiology, 158(6), 827–834.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Welsh, D. K., Logothetis, D. E., Meister, M., & Reppert, S. M. (1995). Individual neurons dissociated from rat suprachiasmatic nucleus express independently phased circadian firing rhythms. Neuron, 14(4), 697–706.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, W. C. (1976). Reductive explanation: A functional account. In R. S. Cohen, C. A. Hooker, A. C. Michalos, & J. van Evra (Eds.), PSA-1974 (pp. 671–710). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to William Bechtel.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Bechtel, W. Understanding endogenously active mechanisms: A scientific and philosophical challenge. Euro Jnl Phil Sci 2, 233–248 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-012-0046-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-012-0046-x

Keywords

Navigation