1 Introduction

Regulatory and scientific discourse about traceability in food production chains hitherto predominantly focused on the development of traceability schemes as means towards the end of managing food-borne health risks. The overall aim of developing traceability schemes within this context of risk management in production chains has been to ensure that consumers can trust that their consumption of food products as provided on the market is not risky in terms of health consequences.

This regulatory and scientific discourse recently witnessed a call to broaden the established notion of traceability to accommodate consumer concerns about product and process characteristics of foods that are not related to health risks. This call envisions the development of something like ethical traceability. This notion of ethical traceability was introduced by Coff (2004) and may be defined as “the ability to trace and map ethical aspects of the food chain by means of recorded identifications” (Coff et al. 2007). It thus refers to the traceability of ethically relevant product and process characteristics of foods. It should not be confused either with the idea of ethically responsible food safety traceability or with the idea of a moral HACCP that looks at human failure as a critical control point (Hirschauer 2004).Footnote 1

Before engaging in the development of ethical traceability schemes, however, the first question in need of serious scrutiny is the question of why ethical traceability might be a worthwhile objective in the context of the pursuit of a new social contract between food producers, consumers and society at large. In other words, a justification discourse about ethical traceability needs to precede an application discourse. This paper presents a contribution to the justification of ethical traceability. The main line or argument is couched in terms of some basic liberal distinctions, since the call for ethical traceability seems to be based first and foremost on intuitions about consumer rights to informed choice on the food market. This paper is rather strongly embedded in liberal political philosophy as developed – partly in discussion with communitarian and utilitarian political philosophies – after Rawls (1972).Footnote 2 Although consumer freedom is high on the agenda of socio-political debate, this paper explores relatively unknown territory.Footnote 3

The paper starts by introducing the liberal distinctions to be used subsequently. It then argues that the operational domain for ethical traceability should be positioned somewhere between needs like food safety that entail positive unconditional rights of consumers and positive unconditional duties of producers and regulators with respect to the provision and traceability of food products, and non-reasonable and/or superficial wants with respect to food that do not entail any rights and duties. The basic argument is that ethical traceability is operational within the domain of reasonable and non-superficial wants with respect to food, which entail conditional rights of consumers and conditional duties of producers and regulators.

2 Some Basic Liberal Distinctions

This section introduces some basic liberal distinctions that inform the main line of argument in this paper (see Table 1). It offers definitions – or rather circumscriptions – of the key terms that are hopefully non-controversial enough to be acceptable for everyone subscribing to the basic values (liberty, equality and fraternity) of modern liberal-democratic European societies.

Table 1 Some basic liberal distinctions

This paper embraces a pragmatic and modestly perfectionist version of liberalism. It accepts, on the one hand, that in pluralistic democratic societies people have divergent perfectionist visions of the good life but acknowledges, on the other hand, that such societies need to share some minimal basic values. The main pragmatic reason to embrace a modestly perfectionist version of liberalism is that a political philosophy should try to build upon as much of the common morality as possible without becoming controversial. More anti-perfectionist versions of liberalism tend to ignore some shared values, whereas more perfectionist versions of liberalism tend to ignore some divergence.Footnote 4

It should be clear that liberalism has quite different connotations in – analytical – political philosophy and in day-to-day European politics. Basically, one could say that new labour, green realos and left-wing Christian-democrats and liberals at least implicitly embrace such a pragmatic and modestly perfectionist liberalism, whereas old labour, green fundis and right-wing Christian-democrats and liberals accept these minimal basic values but strive after divergent varieties of a fuller perfectionism in public morality. Left- and right-wing populists and fundamentalists, finally, do not even subscribe to one or more of the minimal liberal values.

2.1 Needs and Wants

This paper uses the noun ‘need’ to refer to things that are always necessary for survival no matter where or when one lives or what specific values one might adhere to. The noun ‘want,’ on the other hand, refers to things that are only necessary in specific spatial or temporal contexts or for the pursuit of certain specific values. Some scholars might question the very existence of universal (i.e. non-contingent) needs. However, such a full-blown scepticism would result in the reductio ad absurdum that denies the harsh reality of some primary goods (to use a Rawlsian term) as being necessary for human survival.

2.2 Rights and Duties

This paper uses the noun ‘right’ to indicate that someone is entitled to do or not do something, or to have or not have something being done to him or her. The noun ‘duty,’ on the other hand, indicates that someone has an obligation (not) to provide or do something to someone else. If someone has a right, someone else must have a corresponding duty. If this were not the case, rights would be empty and loose their meaning. It is however not true, as some intuitive accounts would argue, that for someone to have rights assumes that he/she also has duties. One should recognise that the rights/duties vocabulary is one of the strongest in ethics and political philosophy. This is both the power and the weakness of this vocabulary. The rights/duties vocabulary requires strict reasoning and only claims applicability in the domain of the mandatory. The absence of certain rights/duties thus does not imply that it could not be a good idea to arrange certain things in the domain of the voluntary.

2.3 Conditional and Unconditional

This paper uses the adjective ‘unconditional’ to indicate that some right or duty holds always and everywhere without further qualification in terms of a provided that or unless clause. The adjective ‘conditional,’ on the other hand, thus indicates that some right or duty is indeed qualified by such a provided that or unless clause.

2.4 Positive and Negative

This paper uses the adjective ‘negative’ to indicate a duty to refrain from or a right to be restrained from interference with some choice. To have a negative duty thus basically says that you should not do something, whereas a negative right says that something should not be done to you. The adjective ‘positive’ on the other hand indicates that you are entitled to (do) something (positive right) or that someone else owes (or must do) something to you (positive duty).

2.5 Reasonable and Non-reasonable

This paper uses the adjective ‘reasonable’ first and foremost in the rather modest sense that values and consumptive choices will qualify as reasonable, if people arrived at those values and choices under conditions of adequate information or knowledge and on properly functioning markets. The properly functioning clause is the market equivalent of the Rawlsian well-ordered clause in well-ordered societies. Just as it does not make much sense to talk about justice in a political context that simply does not ensure some basic democratic values, it does not make much sense to talk about reason in a market context that simply does not ensure a level playing field between competitors, i.e. prices need to reflect costs.Footnote 5

Furthermore the adjective ‘reasonable’ is restricted to the (egalitarian) realm of values and choices that do not harm others (harm principle) (Feinberg 1987) and do not entail negative repercussions on distributive justice (justice principle) (Rawls 1972). This restriction is indeed only acceptable for people with a willingness to embrace the basic values of liberty and justice for all. The adjective ‘non-reasonable,’ on the other hand, thus indicates that some value or consumptive choice does not meet even a rather limited interpretation of rationality or is at odds with respect for the harm or justice principles.

2.6 Superficial and Non-superficial

This paper uses the adjective ‘non-superficial’ to indicate that some consumptive value or preference is an expression of some vision of the right or the good, which implies that not being able to act upon that value has negative repercussions for the constitution of some individual or collective identity. The adjective ‘superficial,’ on the other hand, is reserved for the more shallow preferences without such existential connotations.

2.7 Overlapping and Non-overlapping

This paper uses the adjective ‘overlapping’ to indicate that some value is shared and non-controversial within some society that is otherwise pluralistic on moral issues. The adjective ‘non-overlapping,’ on the other hand indicates that some value is controversial and thus not shared by all people in a certain society.Footnote 6

2.8 Providing and Tracing

This paper uses the verbs ‘providing’ and ‘tracing’ to distinguish between the product and information parts of the product-information combinations that are the subject of divergent traceability schemes. It is, however, important to acknowledge that traceability schemes are always about a ‘package deal’ of providing products and tracing information.

2.9 Regulating and Facilitating

This paper uses the verbs ‘regulating’ and ‘facilitating’ to distinguish between directive and non-directive strategies of government intervention in food markets. Whereas the former strategies oblige market actors to behave in certain ways, the latter strategies merely entice these actors into certain practices. Regulating is thus a strategy of public management in the mandatory domain, whereas facilitating is a strategy of public-private governance in the voluntary domain.

2.10 Consumers, Producers and Regulators

This paper uses the noun ‘consumers’ for the people buying, preparing and eating foods that are grown, processed and sold by people referred to as ‘producers.’ The noun ‘regulators’ is reserved for people in public, private or public-private bodies that somehow have a responsibility to contribute to a properly functioning market exchange between consumers and producers. This paper basically tries to argue which rights to informed choice consumers might have and then formulates the corresponding duties of producers and regulators. It is, however, important to recognise that the development of ethical traceability schemes should be based on a balanced account of rights and duties among all affected parties.

3 Traceability of Food Safety

3.1 Rights of Consumers

No doubt seems to exist that each and every consumer needs safe food. This need does not vary with the context of consumption and thus does not require any further qualification. This implies that consumers have a positive unconditional right to be provided with safe food products. This would hold true even if historically – and geographically – the right to safe food has not always – and everywhere – been recognised as such.

3.2 Duties of Producers

If consumers have a positive unconditional right to be provided with safe food products, producers will have a positive unconditional duty to provide safe food products. This duty is only qualified by a non-moral clause that what counts as safe is always contingent upon available knowledge. This means that a duty to provide safe food products does not call upon producers to strive after a theoretically and practically unfeasible zero-risk. It does call upon producers to minimise food-borne health risks. Furthermore, in a context of food production chains with more than two links the duty to provide safe food products implies a further duty to trace information about the safety of food products.

3.3 Duties of Regulators

If needs inform rights and duties of different groups of actors in society, it will be the duty of regulators in a well-ordered liberal-democratic society to ensure that rights are respected by corresponding duties. This implies that with respect to consumers’ right to safe food products, in a context of food production chains with more than two links, regulators have positive unconditional duties to secure the safety of food products by developing and enforcing traceability regulations. The whole argument about traceability and food safety is focused on the provision of safe products and the provision of information is only instrumental to that objective.

4 Non-reasonable and/or Superficial Food Values

Moving from the domain of needs to the domain of wants, it is not too difficult to see that not all wants or values with respect to food offer sound reasons to argue for rights and duties on the part of different groups of actors. Two borderline cases should suffice to clarify this point. First, nobody will disagree that a cannibal does not have a valid claim to be provided with meat from involuntarily farmed humans. Some food values are simply beyond the realm of permissible values within well-ordered, liberal-democratic societies because they impose infringements on the harm principle or the justice principle. It is of course contingent where the exact demarcation between reasonable and non-reasonable food values is to be drawn.

Second, nobody will disagree that someone’s preference for blackberries and distaste for blueberries does not provide sufficient reason to claim a right to be provided with blackberry pudding. Talking about rights and duties would lose any meaning if it were not confined to values that transgress some level of superficiality. Again, the exact demarcation between superficial and non-superficial values is of course a matter of contingent discourse.

5 Reasonable and Non-superficial Food Values

It seems that in contemporary European societies the whole plethora of consumer concerns that count as expressions of reasonable and non-superficial food values could be summarised into six categories (see, e.g., Beekman et al. 2006):

  • Concerns about impacts on public and personal health;

  • Concerns about impacts of genetic modification;

  • Concerns about impacts on animal welfare;

  • Concerns about impacts on the natural environment;

  • Concerns about impacts on international justice;

  • Concerns about the preservation of regional foods.

It is important to acknowledge a relevant difference between the first two concerns (health and genetic modification) and the last four concerns. Whereas it is perfectly possible to test products to ensure the accuracy of information about food safety or genetically modified ingredients, such a proof of the pudding is not available for the latter concerns. In colloquial terms, animal-friendly and animal-unfriendly, environment-friendly and environment-unfriendly, fairly traded and unfairly traded, and regional and blended food products are substantially equivalent, i.e. such differences in production processes do not impact on the biochemical properties of food products. These qualities can only be verified with the help of recorded identifications of product (hi)stories through the food chain.

All six concerns might be classified as substantive or end concerns to distinguish them from procedural or instrumental concerns about things like transparency, involvement, responsibility, trustworthiness and authenticity. Bluntly speaking, people mostly have procedural concerns because they are substantively concerned about public and personal health, genetic modification, animal welfare, the natural environment, international justice or regional foods. That is why procedural concerns may also be described as instrumental concerns, and that is why it is rather meaningless to discuss these concerns independently of the substantive or end concerns. This would be a confusion of ends and means. Whereas the substantive concerns refer to reasonableness in terms of the harm and justice principles, the procedural concerns refer to reasonableness in terms of adequate information/knowledge and properly functioning markets.

All six concerns share the characteristic that they go beyond merely personal interests like availability, convenience, price and taste. They are thus properly termed moral concerns.

5.1 Rights of Consumers

The fact – or assumption – of value pluralism within contemporary affluent societies implies that more than one set or hierarchy of reasonable and non-superficial food values exists or might exist. However, this does not yet seem enough to argue that consumers have a positive conditional right to be provided with food products that meet their values. It does seem reasonable to argue that consumers have a negative conditional right not to be – deliberately – misinformed about morally relevant product or process characteristics of foods.

However, one should not ignore the possibility of the existence of some overlapping consensus that holds that, e.g., eggs, meat and milk from livestock production systems should adhere to some minimal standard of animal welfare.Footnote 7 Then, the focus changes from information to products and it does seem reasonable to argue that such cases call for a positive conditional right to be provided with certain foods. The condition is, of course, that – unlike needs such as food safety – these overlapping values are contingent.

5.2 Duties of Producers

If consumers have a negative conditional right not to be – deliberately – misinformed about product and process characteristics that are relevant for some reasonable, non-superficial and non-overlapping food value, it will follow that producers have a corresponding negative conditional duty not to misinform consumers about these characteristics of their food products. The impacts of this duty are actually rather strong, since it would imply considerable changes to prevailing marketing practices.

5.3 Duties of Regulators

Negative conditional rights and duties, on the one hand, call upon the government to develop regulatory assurances that these rights are respected by corresponding duties. The duty of regulators is, on the other hand, to regulate the development of ethical traceability schemes as means towards the end of establishing market niches or segments for consumers and producers with similar food values.

6 Concerns About Impacts of Genetic Modification

It might be wise to provide some further clarification of these points by exploring three possible consumer concerns with respect to the much-debated yet ill-understood case of foods with genetically modified (GM) ingredients.Footnote 8

6.1 Health

First, it might be possible to have concerns about negative repercussions of foods with GM ingredients for public or personal health. If these concerns are at least supported by enough scientific uncertainty about such risks to call upon a precautionary approach, the issue will become a case of needs with a negative unconditional right of consumers not to be provided with foods with GM ingredients until their safety has been established beyond reasonable doubt. Producers and regulators will then have the corresponding negative unconditional duties. If these concerns are not supported by some scientific uncertainty, as seems to be the case in real life (see: Kuiper et al. (eds.) 2004), the issue will become a case of non-reasonable concerns with no rights for consumers and no duties for producers and regulators. This first possibility could thus be translated into cases of either needs or non-reasonable wants.

6.2 Justice

Second, it might be possible to have concerns about negative repercussions of foods with GM ingredients for either developing countries (an issue of intragenerational justice) or the natural environment (an issue of intergenerational justice). This is where old-school Rawlsians (following ‘A theory of justice,’ Rawls 1972) and new-school Rawlsians (following ‘Political liberalism,’ Rawls 1993) will part. The first group of liberals would argue that it is enough to imagine a hypothetical overlapping consensus on the principles of intra- and intergenerational justice that could be reached, if the power of reasonable argument determined the outcome of socio-political discussions. The second group of liberals would argue that one needs an actual overlapping consensus to support positive conditional rights of consumers to be provided with foods without GM ingredients and to support the corresponding positive conditional duties of producers and regulators.

6.3 Naturalness

Third, it might be possible to have concerns about foods with GM ingredients because they interfere with either the order of nature or the creation of God. Such concerns are often voiced in public debate but they cannot count on a supportive overlapping consensus. This is where anti-perfectionist Rawlsian liberals, perfectionist liberals (e.g. Raz 1986) and perfectionist communitarians part. The difference between perfectionists and anti-perfectionists is that the latter argue that governments should somehow be neutral with respect to different visions of the good life, whereas the former argue that governments should be allowed to promote one or more specific visions of the good life.Footnote 9

Anti-perfectionist liberals cannot see how producers and regulators in liberal-democratic societies could have positive conditional duties to ensure the preservation of the specific visions of the good that inform such concerns. They do, however, acknowledge the existence of negative conditional duties of producers and regulators that should ensure that consumers with these food values are not misinformed on labels that qualify certain foods as non-GM. Perfectionist liberals, on the contrary, do believe that producers and regulators have positive conditional duties to ensure opportunities to choose from a wide range of, e.g., regional foods. Otherwise consumers’ freedom of choice would be an empty right. Communitarians even believe that producers and regulators have positive conditional duties to ensure the preservation of specific visions of the good. Hitherto, however, no convincing arguments have been formulated that this latter communitarian position could be in accordance with liberal-democratic governments.

7 Overlapping and Non-overlapping Food Values

The above explorations might be summarised in more general terms – transgressing the case of foods with GM ingredients – by distinguishing two sub-categories of reasonable and non-superficial food values.

If these values are supported by an overlapping consensus, ethical traceability should be developed as a public management, or business-to-business, tool to achieve the wanted changes in food production processes. It seems that concerns about animal welfare, the natural environment and international justice are based on overlapping, reasonable and non-superficial food values in present-day European societies. These concerns thus warrant regulatory enforcement of certain minimum standards of animal welfare, environment-friendliness and fair trade. Actually, this is not a case of informed choice but of reduced choice; the objective being to remove animal-unfriendly, environment-unfriendly and unfairly traded food products from the shelves of the supermarket. This implies that with respect to overlapping, reasonable and non-superficial food values, liberal-democratic governments are justified to enforce certain moral standards of production with rules and regulations. In a context of food production chains with more than two links this furthermore implies an obligation to record information about these standards of production by means of ethical traceability schemes.

If these values, on the other hand, are not supported by an overlapping consensus, ethical traceability should be developed as a public-private governance, or business-to-consumer, tool to achieve the wanted changes in food information processes. The private side of this governance tool consists of voluntary positive labelling and tracing of food products with specific ethically relevant product and process characteristics (e.g. region of origin or higher than minimum standards of animal welfare, environment-friendliness and fair trade). The public side of this governance tool consists of safeguarding consumers’ negative conditional right not be misinformed by corporate marketing. Without this negative right there would be no point in positive labelling, since consumers would then not be able to judge the trustworthiness of the claims on food products. Notice also that a positive conditional information right, which would call for mandatory positive labelling, is almost too absurd to be discussed. Consider, for example, the case of a producer of environment-friendly candy bars, who is for some reason unwilling to label these candy bars as environment-friendly – this is a real life case! Why on earth, and how in practical terms should and could a government enforce positive labelling upon this producer?

8 Conclusion

The whole argument of this paper suggests that two versions of ethical traceability find justification. The first is ethical traceability as a public management tool, used to ensure that consumers are provided with foods that respect some threshold level of animal welfare, sustainability (natural environment) or fair trade (international justice), as supported by a contingent overlapping consensus of food values (several Eurobarometer studies suggest that such an overlapping consensus on these issues indeed exists). Such ethical traceability schemes are intended to ensure that corporate standards and quality assurances are verified by documented product (hi)stories. Concerns about public and personal health are excluded here, since food safety is not a want but a need and thus already covered by traceability schemes without the adjective ‘ethical.’ Concerns about genetic modification are excluded from this whole market application domain, since these concerns are not supported by an overlapping food value consensus. Concerns about regional foods are excluded from the whole market application domain, since it is fundamental to the nature of these concerns that they are only applied to specific food products.

The second version is ethical traceability as a public-private governance tool, used to allow certain consumers to be provided with food products, and sufficient information about these products, that are relevant for reasonable, non-superficial values that are not supported by an overlapping consensus. Governments should then facilitate this in the sense that consumers are not provided with misinformation about product and process characteristics of foods that are relevant for reasonable, non-superficial values that are not supported by an overlapping consensus in contemporary European market democracies.

It is important to notice that these justified versions of ethical traceability should both speak about product-information combinations (and not merely about information), and that in both justified versions of ethical traceability improvements in the tracing of information are instrumental to improvements in the provision of products with some substantive added value. The question then arises of what the two distinguished ethical traceability regimes – as management and governance tool respectively – might look like. Table 2 thus spells out the details of the two versions of ethical traceability.

Table 2 Two versions of ethical traceability

The second version of ethical traceability might be further developed in terms of policy recommendations with respect to the development of ethical traceability schemes for specified niche markets. It is important to rebut the common misunderstanding that niche markets are small. The defining characteristic of a niche market is that it is a meeting place for just one segment of producers and consumers. This segment might be or become a quite large portion of the whole market. Criteria and indicators need to be developed for a (higher than minimum) standard of labelled food products for specified niche markets. Furthermore, the nature of the demand for and provision of information by consumers, retailers, food processing companies, farmers and input companies (e.g. feed and seed) need to be spelled out. Together these criteria, indicators, information flows specify ethical traceability schemes.