Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-tj2md Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-23T11:39:00.146Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Some relations between classical and constructive mathematics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 March 2014

Michael Beeson*
Affiliation:
Stanford University, Stanford, CA 94305

Extract

This paper is devoted to the general question, which assertions φ have the property,

if φ is provable classically, then φ is

(*) provable constructively.

More generally, we consider the question, what is the “constructive content” of a given classical proof? Our aim is to formulate rules in a form applicable to mathematical practice. Often a mathematician has the feeling that there will be no difficulty constructivizing a certain proof, only a number of routine details; although it can be quite laborious to set them all out. We believe that most such situations will come quite easily under the scope of the rules given here; the metamathematical machinery will then take care of the details.

This basic idea is not new; it has been discussed by Gödel and by Kreisel. Kreisel's investigations [Kr] were based on Herbrand's theorem; in unpublished memoranda he has also used Gödel's methods on some examples. These methods of Gödel (the double-negation and Dialectica interpretations) lie at the root of our work here. Previous work, however, has been limited to traditional formal systems of number theory and analysis. It is only recently that formal systems adequate to formalize constructive mathematics as a whole have been developed. Thus, for the first time we are in a position to formulate logical theorems which are easily applicable to mathematical practice. It is this program which we here carry out.

Now that the work has been placed in some historical context, let us return to the main question: which φ have the property (*)? Upon first considering the problem, one might guess that any φ which makes no existential assertions (including disjunctions) should have the property (*).

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Association for Symbolic Logic 1978

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

[B1]Beeson, M., Principles of continuous choice and continuity of functions in formal systems for constructive mathematics, Annals of Mathematical Logic (to appear).Google Scholar
[B2]Beeson, M., Continuity in intuitionistic set theories (to appear).Google Scholar
[B3]Beeson, M., A type-free Gödel interpretation, this Journal, vol. 43 (1978), pp. 213227.Google Scholar
[Bi]Bishop, E., Foundations of constructive analysis, McGraw-Hill, New York, 1967.Google Scholar
[F1]Feferman, S., A language and axioms for explicit mathematics, Algebra and logic, Springer Lecture Notes, No. 450, pp. 87139.Google Scholar
[F2]Feferman, S., Notes on the formalization of Bishop's constructive analysis, mimeographed notes, Stanford University, 1977.Google Scholar
[Kr]Kreisel, G., The metamathematical significance of consistency proofs, this Journal, vol. 23 (1958), pp. 155182.Google Scholar
[Tr]Troelstra, A. S., Metamathematical investigation of intuitionistic arithmetic and analysis, Springer Lecture Notes, No. 344.Google Scholar
[Z]Zucker, J., Iterated inductive definitions, trees, and ordinals, Springer Lecture Notes, No. 344.Google Scholar