Hostname: page-component-7c8c6479df-8mjnm Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-03-19T04:47:28.468Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

PROPERTY IN THE MORAL LIFE OF HUMAN BEINGS

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 February 2014

Christopher Bertram*
Affiliation:
Philosophy, University of Bristol

Abstract

Liberal egalitarian political philosophers have often argued that private property is a legal convention dependent on the state and that complaints about taxation from entitlement theorists are therefore based on a conceptual mistake. But our capacity to grasp and use property concepts seems too embedded in human nature for this to be correct. This essay argues that many standard arguments that property is constitutively a legal convention fail, but that the opposition between conventionalists and natural rights theorists is outmoded. In doing this, the essay draws on recent literature in evolutionary biology and psychology. Even though modern property in a complex society involves legal conventions, those conventions should be sensitive to our natural dispositions concerning ownership.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Social Philosophy and Policy Foundation 2013 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Snare, Frank, “The Concept of Property,” American Philosophical Quarterly 9, no. 2 (1972): 201Google Scholar.

2 Such as, most famously, Nozick, Robert, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974)Google Scholar.

3 A view most strongly expressed recently in Murphy, Liam and Nagel, Thomas, The Myth of Ownership: Taxes and Justice (New York: Oxford University Press, 2002)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

4 For example, Nagel, Thomas, “The Problem of Global Justice,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 33, no. 2 (2005): 113–47CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

5 In this essay, I refer most to the work of Tomasello, Michaelsuch as hisThe Origins of Human Communication: The Jean Nicod Lectures (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2008)Google Scholar and Why We Cooperate (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2009)Google Scholar, but other work such as Boehm, Christopher, Hierarchy in the Forest: The Evolution of Egalitarian Behavior (Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 1999)Google Scholar, Boehm, Christopher, Moral Origins: The Evolution of Virtue, Altruism, and Shame (New York: Basic Books, 2012)Google Scholar, and de Waal, Frans, Primates and Philosophers: How Morality Evolved (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2006)CrossRefGoogle Scholar fits in the same general space.

6 Here, I take Snare, “The Concept of Property,” as a guide.

7 For that, Waldron, Jeremy, The Right to Private Property (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1988)Google Scholar remains unsurpassed.

8 For a recent work arguing the importance of a stable system of property rights for economic growth and development, see de Soto, Hernando, The Mystery of Capital (New York: Basic Books, 2000)Google Scholar.

9 Murphy and Nagel, The Myth of Ownership, 9.

10 Nozick, Robert, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974), 169Google Scholar.

11 Hobbes, Thomas, Leviathan, ed. Malcolm, Noel, The Clarendon Edition of the Works of Thomas Hobbes (1651; Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012), vol. 2, 220Google Scholar.

12 These three Kant, ian arguments are set out inThe Doctrine of Rightwhich forms part of The Metaphysics of Morals and is included inPractical Philosophy, ed. Gregor, Mary J., The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant (1797; Cambridge University Press, 1996)Google Scholar. I draw on the presentation of the arguments in Ripstein, Arthur, Force and Freedom: Kant's Legal and Political Philosophy (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2009), ch. 6CrossRefGoogle Scholar; See also Gibbard, Allan, “Natural Property Rights,” Nous 10, no. 1 (1976): 7786CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

13 See Hobbes, Leviathan, p. 224.

14 Arguably, another way in which such anthropological antiquarianism persists is via the influence and prestige of modern economic theory, to the extent to which it relies on the stock figure of homo economicus, the individual rational utility maximizer. I say, “to the extent” to indicate an awareness that modern utility theory is formally indifferent to the content of people's preference functions, which can be egoistic, altruistic, or anything you like. This does not altogether banish the older figure from the tacit assumptions made in much economic thinking.

15 Remarkably, Murphy and Nagel, The Myth of Ownership: Taxes and Justice, 74–75 rely on the conventional nature of language as a parallel with property to bolster their case for the dependence of property on positive law, seemingly not noticing that language has its natural side too.

16 This latter view derives from Tomasello, Origins of Human Communication. Tomasello is skeptical about Chomskyan universal grammar.

17 See Tomasello, Why We Cooperate and particularly Tomasello, Origins of Human Communication, chap. 5. Tomasello in turn draws on work on joint intention pioneered by philosophers such as Gilbert, Margaret in her On Social Facts (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1989)Google Scholar.

18 On blushing, see Boehm, Moral Origins.

19 On this, see, for example, Ellickson, Robert C., Order Without Law (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1991)Google Scholar. Hernando de Soto, The Mystery of Capital, chapter 5 has interesting discussion of how informal property holdings in the United States often predate their formal legal recognition.

20 Nietzsche, Friedrich, On the Genealogy of Morals, ed. Ansell-Pearson, Keith (1887; Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994), 38Google Scholar.

21 See Tomasello, Origins of Human Communication, chap. 2.

22 For discussion see Stake, J. E., “The Property ‘Instinct’,” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 359, no. 1451 (2004): 1763Google Scholar. On the evolution of behaviors favoring first possession, see Maynard-Smith, John and Parker, G. A., “The Logic of Asymmetric Contests,” Animal Behaviour 24 (1976): 159–75CrossRefGoogle Scholar. The connection to the endowment effect is discussed in Gintis, Herbert, The Bounds of Reason: Game Theory and the Unification of the Behavioral Sciences (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2009), chap. 11Google Scholar.

23 As reported by Brosnan, Sarah F., “Property in Nonhuman Primates,” New Directions for Child and Adolescent Development 132 (2011): 922CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

24 Friedman, Ori and Ross, Hildy, “Twenty-One Reasons to Care About the Psychological Basis of Ownership,” New Directions for Child and Adolescent Development 132 (2011): 18CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

25 Rochat, Philippe, “Possession and Morality in Early Development,” New Directions for Child and Adolescent Development 132 (2011): 3031Google Scholar.

26 Ibid., 32.

27 Blake, Peter R. and Harris, Paul L., “Early Representations of Ownership,” New Directions for Child and Adolescent Development 132 (2011): 3945CrossRefGoogle Scholar, drawing also on earlier work by Michael Tomasello.

28 Rochat, “Possession and Morality in Early Development,” 34.

29 Blake, Peter R. and Harris, Paul L., “Children's Understanding of Ownership Transfers,” Cognitive Development (2009)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

30 Noles, Nicholaus S. and Keil, Frank C., “Exploring Ownership in a Developmental Context,” New Directions for Child and Adolescent Development 132 (2011): 97Google Scholar.

31 Friedman, Ori and Neary, Karen R., “Determining Who Owns What: Do Children Infer Ownership From First Possession?Cognition 107, no. 3 (2008): 829–49CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Friedman, Ori, “First Possession: An Assumption Guiding Inferences About Who Owns What,” Psychonomic Bulletin & Review 15, no. 2 (2008): 290–95CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

32 Kanngiesser, Patricia, Gjersoe, Nathalia, and Hood, Bruce M., “The Effect of Creative Labor on Property-Ownership Transfer by Preschool Children and Adults,” Psychological Science 21, no. 9 (September 2010): 1236–41CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

33 Pierson v. Post, 3 Cai. R. 175, 2 Am. Dec. 264 (N.Y. 1805)Google Scholar.

34 Friedman, Ori and Neary, Karen R., “First Possession Beyond the Law: Adults' and Young Children's Intuitions About Ownership,” Tulane Law Review, vol. 83 (2009)Google Scholar.

35 Kanngiesser, Gjersoe, and Hood, “The Effect of Creative Labor on Property-Ownership Transfer by Preschool Children and Adults.”

36 Ross, Hildy S., “Effects of Ownership Rights on Conflicts Between Toddler Peers,” Infancy (March 2012): 120Google Scholar; Ross, Hildy S., Conant, Cheryl, and Vickar, Marcia, “Property rights and the resolution of social conflict,” New Directions for Child and Adolescent Development, 132 (2011): 5364CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

37 Ross, Conant, and Vickar, “Property Rights and the Resolution of Social Conflict.”

38 For an interesting argument to this effect, see Brosnan, Kevin, “Do the Evolutionary Origins of Our Moral Beliefs Undermine Moral Knowledge?Biology and Philosophy 26, no. 1 (2011): 5164CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

39 This is one of the central themes of Boehm, Moral Origins.

40 See, Hume, David, A Treatise of Human Nature, eds. Selby-Bigge, L. A. and Niddich, P. H., 2d ed. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978), 484501Google Scholar.

41 It might be thought (for example) that this is exactly what documents such as the Berne Convention do, when they recognize the moral rights of authors.