Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

The Aim of a Theory of Justice

  • Published:
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Amartya Sen argues that for the advancement of justice identification of ‘perfect’ justice is neither necessary nor sufficient. He replaces ‘perfect’ justice with comparative justice. Comparative justice limits itself to comparing social states with respect to degrees of justice. Sen’s central thesis is that identifying ‘perfect’ justice and comparing imperfect social states are ‘analytically disjoined’. This essay refutes Sen’s thesis by demonstrating that to be able to make adequate comparisons we need to identify and integrate criteria of comparison. This is precisely the aim of a theory of justice (such as John Rawls’s theory): identifying, integrating and ordering relevant principles of justice. The same integrated criteria that determine ‘perfect’ justice are needed to be able to adequately compare imperfect social states. Sen’s alternative approach, which is based on social choice theory, is incapable of avoiding contrary, indeterminate or incoherent directives where plural principles of justice conflict.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See for instance the contributions to the special issue ‘Social Justice: Ideal Theory, Non-ideal Circumstances’ in Social Theory and Practice, 34 (July 2008); guest editors Ingrid Robeyns and Adam Swift.

  2. The adjective ‘transcendental’ may create confusion because it usually refers to an a priori source of knowledge or to ‘transcendentalism’ in the sense of belief in the existence of things that transcend sense-experience and the possibility of transcendent metaphysics (Blackburn 2005: 368; Honderich 1995: 878). With respect to John Rawls’s theory (which is the main target of Sen’s argument) the phrase ‘transcendental justice’ seems less adequate, because Rawls applies the method of ‘epistemic abstinence’ and emphatically denies that his theory has a metaphysical or transcendental foundation (Rawls 1996: 10, 97). Besides, Sen’s designation ‘perfect justice’ may conceal that Rawls’s theory concerns a ‘realistic utopia’ – justice that is realistically achievable within the limits of the permanent conditions of imperfect human nature – rather than an unfeasible idealistic kind of justice. Rawls: ‘Our hope for the future of our society rests on the belief that . . . a reasonably just, though not perfect, democratic regime is possible’ (2001: 4; emphasis added). Thus, in this context the terms ‘transcendental’ and ‘perfect’, used by Sen, are less fortunate. That is why I put them between inverted commas.

  3. Rawls’s theory of justice orders and integrates competing criteria or principles of justice. It assigns lexical priority to equal basic liberties over equal opportunities and it ranks the latter over the Difference Principle. The Difference Principle, in turn, integrates efficiency of welfare distribution with concern for the worst-off.

  4. In section 7 (‘Intuitionism’) of his A Theory of Justice Rawls gives insightful examples of interpersonally different intuitive balances between principles.

  5. Cf. Rawls 1999: 115–6.

  6. For instance, the multiple criteria or contributory values relevant to comparing two paintings may consist of creative quality, expressiveness, innovative character, authenticity, historical and contemporary significance, etcetera. Together these contributory values constitute an integral covering value with respect to which the paintings can be compared.

  7. This does not mean that the problem for Sen applies only to complex (multidimensional) conceptions of justice and not to simple ones. There is a possible problem in all cases in which we do not have a determinate and unambiguous standard of comparison, irrespective of whether this standard is simple or complex. Indeed, how is it possible to compare two social states if we do not know the relevant and right standard of comparison, even if we suppose that the standard is simple, say ‘utility’ or ‘legitimate entitlement’. It makes a lot of difference if we compare the degrees of justice of two social states with respect to the former or the latter standard of justice.

  8. See also Rawls 1999: 33, 56, 65.

  9. Sen 1995: 46–9, especially figure 3.1. See also Sen 2006: 225; and 2009: 2–3: ‘A number of distinct and divergent arguments can still lead to the same conclusion.’ Cf. Sunstein’s ‘incompletely theorized agreements’, discussed in Sunstein 1996; and Rawls’s (1999) ‘overlapping consensus’.

  10. Of course, the aggregation problem only applies to multiple (more than two) relevant factors that may be ordered differently. As most theorists, including Sen, recognize, this applies to justice as a multifaceted concept.

  11. For a proof see Allingham 2002: 99–101. A clear and concise summary and explanation of the problematic issue of rationality and coherence of democratic decisions in general and with respect to distributive justice in particular are given in chapter 6, ‘Democracy and dictatorship’: 106–110.

  12. Compare a similar example given by Sen 2009: 12–15, also discussed in Sen 2006: 224–5.

  13. This is one of the reasons why Rawls applies the devices of the original position and the ‘veil of ignorance’, in which the agents are detached from their conceptions of the good and comprehensive beliefs, expecting that it promotes an (overlapping) consensus on the ranking of principles. The various individual perspectives are replaced by the perspective of an ‘impartial spectator’, see below.

  14. See also the concise and illuminating discussion of this problem by Wolf 1998: 58–67 (‘Appendix: The Irrationality of Majority Rule’).

  15. See also Shaun Hargreaves Heap et al. 1992: 212–214; Hurley 1989: 228; D’Agostino 2003: 6–20, 28; Kornhauser 1998: 1599–1637. Decisions of multi-judge courts are confronted with similar problems (Kornhauser and Sager 2004).

  16. I owe this point to an anonymous referee.

References

  • Allingham M (2002) Choice theory. A very short introduction. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Arrow KJ (1963) Social choice and individual values. Yale University Press, New Haven and London

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn S (2005) Oxford dictionary of philosophy. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Chang R (1997) Introduction. In: Chang R (ed) Incommensurability, incomparability and practical reason. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Chang R (2001) Making comparisons count, Dissertation in Ethics. Routledge, New York

  • Chang R (2002) The possibility of parity. Ethics 112:659–688

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • D’Agostino F (2003) Incommensurability and commensuration. The common denominator. Ashgate, Burlington

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodin RE (1995) Political ideals and political practice. Br J Polit Sci 25:37–56

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hargreaves Heap S et al (1992) The theory of choice. Blackwell Publishers, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Honderich T (ed) (1995) The Oxford companion to philosophy. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurley S (1989) Natural reasons, personality and polity. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • John Simmons A (2010) Ideal and nonideal theory. Philos Publ Aff 38:5–36

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kornhauser LA (1998) No Best Answer? University of Pennsylvania Law Review 146

  • Kornhauser LA, Sager LG (2004) The many as one: integrity and group choice in paradoxical cases. Philosophy and Public Affairs 249

  • Miller D (2003) Political philosophy. A very short introduction. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls J (1996) Political liberalism. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls J (1999) A theory of justice, Revisedth edn. The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls J (2001) Justice as fairness. A restatement. The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Robeyns I (2008) Ideal theory in theory and practice. Soc Theor Pract 34:341–362

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen A (1995) Inequality reexamined. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sen A (2006) What do we want from a theory of justice? J Philos 103:215–238

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen A (2009) The idea of justice. The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Stemplowska Z (2008) What is ideal about ideal theory? Soc Theor Pract 34:319–340

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein C (1996) Legal reasoning and political conflict. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Swift A (2008) The value of philosophy in nonideal circumstances. Soc Theor Pract 34:363–387

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolff RP (1998) In defense of anarchism. University of California Press, Berkeley

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Martijn Boot.

Additional information

The paper is a result of research conducted at the Erasmus University Rotterdam for the project ‘The Transition from Ideal to Nonideal Theories of Justice’ (head: Ingrid Robeyns). The research was financed by a grant of the Netherlands Organization for Scientific Research (NWO). I thank Anca Gheaus, Ingrid Robeyns, Anders Schinkel and two anonymous referees for their constructive comments.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Boot, M. The Aim of a Theory of Justice. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 15, 7–21 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-011-9308-5

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-011-9308-5

Keywords

Navigation