Skip to main content
Log in

Amending and defending Critical Contextual Empiricism

  • Original paper in Philosophy of Science
  • Published:
European Journal for Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In Science as Social Knowledge in 1990 and The Fate of Knowledge in 2002, Helen Longino develops an epistemological theory known as Critical Contextual Empiricism (CCE). Knowledge production, she argues, is an active, value-laden practice, evidence is context dependent and relies on background assumptions, and science is a social inquiry that, under certain conditions, produces social knowledge with contextual objectivity. While Longino’s work has been generally well-received, there have been a number of criticisms of CCE raised in the philosophical literature in recent years. In this paper I outline the key elements of Longino’s theory and propose modifications to the four norms offered by the account. The version of CCE I defend, which draws on lessons learned by medical researchers in recent years, gives principles of epistemic diversity a central role and also provides greater specification of three of the four norms. Further, it offers additional resources for defending CCE against Alvin Goldman’s suggestion that there is a need for a “healthy dogmatism” in science, as well as a concern about “manufactured uncertainty” arising out of recent work by David Michaels. Finally, the modified version proposed here is also well positioned to respond (negatively) to a suggestion from Kristen Intemann that CCE needs to be adapted to incorporate a central insight from feminist standpoint theory. In light of the variety of social pressures influencing contemporary scientific research, and the role of science in shaping public policy, I argue that a rigorous social epistemology such as CCE is indispensable for understanding and assessing contemporary scientific practice.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The scientific community is often used as an example of a paradigmatic knowledge-productive community but the arguments of this paper can and should be applied to other knowledge-productive communities as well.

  2. Constitutive and contextual values can be positive or negative, so, for instance, if transparency is a positive value in science, secrecy may be the corresponding negative value.

  3. Perhaps the most famous of these are Steven Shapin and Simon Schaffer’s (1985) Leviathan and the Air Pump on the values in experimentation, Karin Knorr-Cetina’s (1981) analysis of decision-making in the laboratory in The Manufacture of Knowledge, and Donna Haraway’s (1989) investigation into gender bias in primatology in Primate Visions. For an overview of many of these arguments, see J. R. Brown (2001) Who Rules in Science? An Opinionated Guide to the Wars.

  4. Other philosophers might call background assumptions ‘principles of inference’, but, according to Longino, this does not capture the contextual (and non-principled) nature of most background assumptions. I agree and will adopt her terminology in Longino (1993), 260.

  5. This criterion was originally referred to as shared standards. In The Fate of Knowledge it was renamed public standards. It is my understanding that this is a shift in emphasis rather than in content.

  6. The four norms are taken from Longino (1990), 76, with modifications in Longino (2002b), 128135.

  7. Criteria of relevance will be set by the particular community. In the case of the medical research community, it has become clear in light of extensive empirical evidence that industry-funded research tends to have certain biases. This has led to the inclusion of ‘conflict of interest’ statements as a relevant piece of information for the readers of medical journals. Similar changes have occurred with respect to what sort of information needs to be supplied during informed consent. These criteria can and should evolve as the community changes over time and as new evidence emerges.

  8. It is perhaps worth noting that I endorse the modification to standpoint theory that she identifies as necessary, which amounts to a suggestion that standpoint theorists explicitly endorse empiricist criteria for theory choice (or, put another way, become empiricists).

  9. I assume the irony of suggesting that a reduction in the diversity of theories available in feminist epistemology would be better isn’t lost on Intemann, or her audience!

References

  • Borgerson, K. (2005). Evidence-based alternative medicine? Perspectives in Biology and Medicine, 48(4), 502–515.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Borgerson, K. (2009a). Why reading the title isn’t good enough: an evaluation of the 4S approach to evidence-based medicine. International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics, 2(2), 152–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Borgerson, K. (2009b). Valuing evidence: bias and the evidence hierarchy of evidence-based medicine. Perspectives in Biology and Medicine, 52(2), 218–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, J. R. (2001). Who rules in science? An opinionated guide to the wars. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, R. (1998). Illusions of paradox: A feminist epistemology naturalized. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fricker, M. (2007). Epistemic injustice: Power and the ethics of knowing. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (2002). Knowledge and social norms. Review of the fate of knowledge, by H. Longino, Science 296: 2148–2149.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haraway, D. (1989). Primate visions: Gender, race, and nature in the world of modern science. New York: Routledge.

  • Intemann, K. (2010). Feminist standpoint empiricism: rethinking the terrain in feminist philosophy of science. In P. D. Magnus & J. Busch (Eds.), New waves in philosophy of science (pp. 198–225). New York: Palgrave MacMillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knorr-Cetina, K. (1981). The manufacture of knowledge. Oxford: Pergamon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lemmens, T. (2004). Leopards in the temple: restoring integrity to the commercialized research scene. The Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics, 32(4), 641–657.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lexchin, J., et al. (2003). Pharmaceutical industry sponsorship and research outcome and quality: systematic review. BMJ, 326, 1167–1170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. (1990). Science as social knowledge: Values and objectivity in scientific inquiry. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. (1993). Essential tensions—phase two: feminist, philosophical, and social studies of science. In L. M. Antony & C. Witt (Eds.), A mind of one’s own: Feminist essays on reason and objectivity (pp. 257–272). Boulder: Westview.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. (2002a). Reply to Philip Kitcher. Philosophy of Science, 69, 573–577.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. (2002b). The fate of knowledge. Princeton University Press: Princeton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michaels, D. (2008). Doubt is their product: How the industry’s assault on science threatens your health. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Mill, J. S. (1956). On Liberty. New York: The Liberal Arts Press, Inc. [1859].

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapin, S., & Schaffer, S. (1985). Leviathan and the air pump. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, M. (2006). Epistemic diversity or epistemic randomness? (Or, More on the Invisible Hand of Reason). Conference Presentation, 3 rd Annual Episteme Conference (University of Toronto)

  • Wylie, A., Dupré, J., & Kincaid, H. (2007). Value-free science? Ideals and illusions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thank-you to the Canadian Institutes of Health Research (CIHR) for ongoing support and to Margaret Morrison, two anonymous reviewers, and the organizers of SPSP—particularly Mieke Boon—for helpful feedback on this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kirstin Borgerson.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Borgerson, K. Amending and defending Critical Contextual Empiricism. Euro Jnl Phil Sci 1, 435 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-011-0035-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-011-0035-5

Keywords

Navigation