Skip to main content
Log in

Masters of Our Meanings

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The two-dimensional framework in semantics has the most power and plausibility when combined with a kind of global semantic neo-descriptivism. If neo-descriptivism can be defended on the toughest terrain — the semantics of ordinary proper names — then the other skirmishes should be easier. This paper defends neo-descriptivism against two important objections: that the descriptions may be inaccessibly locked up in sub-personal modules, and thus not accessible a priori, and that in any case all such modules bottom out in purely causal mechanisms, and that thus an externalist causal metasemantic theory will best account for them. I agree both that many descriptions are in some sense modularized, and that they bottom out in causal mechanisms. But I argue that these are not the relevant descriptions that two-dimensionalism trades in, and which make us, in an important sense, masters of our meanings.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

REFERENCES

  • Braddon-Mitchell, D. and Jackson, F. (1996): The Philosophy of Mind and Cognition, Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D.J. (2002): ‘On Sense and Intension’, Philosophical Perspectives 16, 135–182.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D.J. (2004): ‘The Foundations of Two-Dimensional Semantics’, in M. García-Carpintero and J. Macià (eds.), The Two-Dimensional Framework, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, G. (1979): ‘Reference and Contingency’, The Monist 62: 161–189.

    Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (1981): Designation, New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (1996): Coming to Our Senses: A Naturalistic Program for Semantic Localism, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1998): From Metaphysics to Ethics: A Defence of Conceptual Analysis, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (2001): ‘Locke-ing onto Content’, in D. Walsh (ed.), Naturalism, Evolution and Mind, (pp. 127–143), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1980): Naming and Neccessity, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Margolis, E. and Laurence, S. (eds.) (1999): Concepts: Core Readings, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J.S. (1974): ‘The Early Draft of the Logic (1836)’, Collected Works of John Stuart Mill (J.M. Robson. Toronto: Routledge and Kegan Paul) VIII. 978–985.

    Google Scholar 

  • Soames, S. (1998): ‘The Modal Argument: Wide Scope and Rigidified Descriptions’, Noûs 32, 1–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Soames, S. (2002): Beyond Rigidity: The Unfinished Semantic Agenda of Naming and Necessity, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Soames, S. (forthcoming): ‘Naming and Asserting’.

  • Stalnaker, R.C. (2003): ‘Conceptual Truth and Metaphysical Necessity’, in R.C. Stalnaker (ed.), Ways a World Might Be: Metaphysical and Anti-Metaphysical Essays, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Braddon-Mitchell, D. Masters of Our Meanings. Philosophical Studies 118, 133–152 (2004). https://doi.org/10.1023/B:PHIL.0000019545.11503.2d

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1023/B:PHIL.0000019545.11503.2d

Keywords

Navigation