Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Rights & Nature

Approaching Environmental Issues by Way of Human Rights

  • Articles
  • Published:
Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Due to the significant and often careless human impact on the natural environment, there are serious problems facing the people of today and of future generations. To date, ethical, aesthetic, religious, and economic arguments for the conservation and protection of the natural environment have made relatively little headway. Another approach, one capable of garnering attention and motivating action, would be welcome. There is another approach, one that I will call a rights approach. Speaking generally, this approach is an attempt to address environmental issues via the language and theory of legal and moral rights. Ultimately, it is our duties to our fellow humans that explain why we have duties regarding the natural environment. There are three main contenders among theories that can be called rights approaches to environmental issues. The first identifies the (alleged) human right to a healthful environment as the source of our obligations to conserve and protect nature. The second approach has it that our duties to nature arise from the rights of the constituents of nature themselves, its flora and fauna. The third approach to addressing environmental problems via rights is, I argue, the best path to environmental conservation and protection. This approach—which grounds duties toward nature on the human right to health—has the benefits of being a straightforward, uncontroversial, and simple approach to issues and problems that desperately need to be resolved.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Available online at http://conventions.coe.int/treaty/en/Treaties/Html/035.htm.

  2. Unless otherwise noted, this section draws from Hayward (2005, pp. 1–13).

  3. These, again, are just examples of claims these two groups might make against the destruction of an area of rainforest. They show that while the groups’ ultimate interests might be different—protection of nature for one, protection of human rights for the other—the ways in which these interests might be satisfied can be the same. I don’t mean to suggest that an environmentalist’s only recourse it an appeal to nature’s inherent value or that a human rights advocate’s only option is an appeal to the right to a healthful environment.

  4. Such a proposal is discussed in Alston (1984: 610).

  5. While I will say something below about the adequacy of the set of duties generated by the right to health, I lack the space to attend fully to the matter of an anthropocentric environmental ethic’s ability to adjudicate in cases of competing interests—short- and long-term in particular. My assumption here is that if an anthropocentric environmental ethical theory is capable of adequately dealing with competing claims by, for example, business interests and environmentalists, then it will be a theory rooted in the human right to health (and not the right to nature of a healthful sort). I thank an anonymous reviewer for reminding me of this persistent problem with human-centered environmental ethical theories. I should think that a worthwhile place to begin concerning this topic would be with Rolston (2003) and Sterba (1994).

  6. See Boyle (1996: 54) for such a list.

  7. I drop, for the time being, the modifier “human.” Here, we are dealing with the rights of non-humans, both flora and fauna.

  8. Although I will use the phrase “animal rights” to refer to the rights of non-human animals, I don’t mean to imply that humans are not animals. The phrase is a sort of shorthand for the more cumbersome “non-human animal rights.”

  9. It is not clear whether Regan meant this to be an empirical claim about all moral thinkers or whether he was merely expressing an intuition. This question, and the question of which Regan ought to have meant, has been dealt with in Franklin (2005, p. 22).

  10. Most do not deny this, anyway. Surely some do, but Regan seems to take for granted that “marginal” humans are regarded by the rest of us as possessing as much inherent value as we do. See Regan (1985: 23) for an instance of Regan’s assertion that the retarded child and the mentally deranged have as much inherent value as the rest of us.

  11. A similar statement, one tying respect to rights, comes in Regan (1985: 21). “For either of us to treat the other in ways that fail to show respect for the other’s independent value is to act immorally, to violate the individual’s rights.”

  12. Cahen (2003), Taylor (2003). This is not to suggest that either Cahen or Taylor argues for the rights of the environment. This is merely to suggest that not all environmental ethical views are holistic views.

  13. Perhaps, in recognizing the rights of wholes, one ends up treating wholes as though they were individuals—anthropomorphizing them. If so, perhaps there is something to Regan’s claim that “…paradigmatic rights-holders are individuals…” (Regan 1983: 362). This is one of those interesting questions that cannot be addressed at present.

  14. I say “rights-attainment” to indicate the acquisition of legal rights, things these groups did not possess before the rights were officially granted.

  15. See Carruthers (1992: 114–117).

  16. The point here is not merely that health is necessary in order to realize the particular goals we set for ourselves—though that much is true. The point is to highlight the connection between health and purposive action in general. An unhealthy being cannot behave with complete autonomy, cannot effectively direct itself toward its goals. In other words, a lack of health diminishes the very possibility of goal-directed action, independent of any specific goals.

  17. As reported on http://www.osha.gov/as/opa/oshafacts.html.

  18. A full comparison of the various duties entailed by the right to health and recognized by ethical theories such as Utilitarianism, Deontology, Virtue Ethics, Deep Ecology, and Leopold’s Holism (among others) takes us too far afield at present. Such an undertaking is what motivates some of my current research. See above (footnote 5) for potentially helpful references relating to this matter.

  19. These are, in my hands, fairly arbitrary numbers. I am aware, however, that others have put more thought into such thresholds. See Soulé and Sanjayan (1998) and Wilson (1999) for such accounts and some relevant criticism.

  20. Defined, tentatively, in terms of minimal cultivation or maintenance by humans and involving a dearth of features like roads and buildings.

References

  • Alston, P. (1984). Conjuring up new human rights: A proposal for quality control. The American Journal of International Law, 78(3), 607–621.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, M. R. (1996). Human rights approaches to environmental protection: An overview. In A. Boyle & M. Anderson (Eds.), Human rights approaches to environmental protection. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyle, A. (1996). The role of international human rights law in the protection of the environment. In A. Boyle & M. Anderson (Eds.), Human rights approaches to environmental protection. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cahen, H. (2003). Against the moral considerability of ecosystems. In Andrew Light & Holmes Rolston III (Eds.), Environmental ethics. Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Callicott, J. B. (2008). The conceptual foundations of the Land Ethic. In Pojman & Pojman (Eds.), Environmental ethics. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (1992). The animals issue. Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Center for International and Environmental Law (CIEL) (2012) About the human rights & environment program.. http://www.ciel.org/HR_Envir/About_HRE.html.

  • Daniels, N. (1985). Just health care. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fabra, A. (2002) "The intersection of human rights and environmental issues: A review of institutional developments at the international level,” part of the seminar organized by the Office of the High Commissioner for Human Rights and the U.N. Environment Program (Geneva, Switzerland: 16 January 2002). Online: http://www.unhchr.ch/environment/bp3.html.

  • Franklin, J. H. (2005). Animal rights and moral philosophy. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodin, R. (1989). The ethics of smoking. Ethics, 99(3), 574–624.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hare, R. M. (1999). Why I am only a demi-vegetarian. In Dale Jamieson (Ed.), Singer and his critics. Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayward, T. (1994). Ecological thought. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayward, T. (1998). Political theory and ecological values. New York: St. Martin’s Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayward, T. (2005). Constitutional environmental rights. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnston, B. R. (1995). Human rights and the environment. Human Ecology, 23(2), 111–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leopold, A. (1970). A sand county almanac. New York: Ballantine Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Louv, R. (2005). Last child in the woods. Chapel Hill: Algonquin Books of Chapel Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merrills, J. G. (1996). Environmental protection and human rights: Conceptual aspects. In A. Boyle & M. Anderson (Eds.), Human rights approaches to environmental protection (pp. 25–41). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nash, R. (1989). The rights of nature. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Natural Resources Conservation Service (NRCS) (2012). Soil quality concepts.. http://soils.usda.gov/sqi/concepts/concepts.html.

  • Regan, T. (1983). The case for animal rights. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Regan, T. (1985). The case for animal rights. In P. Singer (Ed.), In defense of animals. New York: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rolston, H., I. I. I. (2003). Value in nature and the nature of value. In A. Light & H. Rolston III (Eds.), Environmental ethics. Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sagoff, M. (1974). On preserving the natural environment. Yale Law Journal, 84(2), 205–267.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sandler, R. (2007). Character and environment: A virtue-oriented approach to environmental ethics. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sayre, L. (2009). The hidden link between factory farms and human illness. http://www.motherearthnews.com/Natural-Health/Meat-Poultry-Health-Risk.aspx.

  • Soulé, M. E., & Sanjayan, M. A. (1998). Conservation targets: Do they help? Science, 279, 2060–2061.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sparshott, F. (1983). Why artworks have no right to have rights. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 42(1), 5–15. Autumn.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterba, J. P. (1994). Environmental justice: Reconciling anthropocentric and nonanthropocentric ethics. Environmental Values, 3(3), 229–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stone, Christopher D. (1974). Should trees have standing? Toward legal rights for natural objects. Los Altos, CA: William Kaufmann, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, Paul. (2003). The ethics of respect for nature. In L. Andrew & H. Rolston III (Eds.), Environmental ethics. Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • United States: Department of Health and Human Services (U.S. DHHS). (1986). The health consequences of involuntary smoking. Washington, D.C.: Government Printing Office.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, E. O. (1999). The diversity of life. New York: W.W. Norton & Co.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank the editors of The Journal of Agricultural & Environmental Ethics and the anonymous reviewers of an earlier version of this paper for their helpful comments. Thanks also to Purdue University’s Mark Bernstein, William McBride, and Patrick Kain, whose assistance made this paper possible.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Andrew T. Brei.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Brei, A.T. Rights & Nature. J Agric Environ Ethics 26, 393–408 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10806-012-9385-z

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10806-012-9385-z

Keywords

Navigation