Skip to main content
Log in

Why metaphors make good insults: perspectives, presupposition, and pragmatics

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Metaphors are powerful communicative tools because they produce ‘framing effects’. These effects are especially palpable when the metaphor is an insult that denigrates the hearer or someone he cares about. In such cases, just comprehending the metaphor produces a kind of ‘complicity’ that cannot easily be undone by denying the speaker’s claim. Several theorists have taken this to show that metaphors are engaged in a different line of work from ordinary communication. Against this, I argue that metaphorical insults are rhetorically powerful because they combine perspectives, presupposition, and pragmatics in the service of speech acts with assertoric force.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See e.g. Bargh et al. (1996), Dijksterhuis and Van Knippenberg (1998), Banfield et al. (2003), Anderson and Pichert (1978), Lee-Sammons and Whitney (1991).

  2. Linguists sometimes invoke perspectives and frames to describe the sort of relativity displayed by expression pairs like ‘come’/‘go’, or ‘bought’/‘sold’ (Fillmore 1977, 1985), in predicates of personal taste like ‘tasty’, and in expressives like ‘damn’ (Lasersohn 2005, 2007). I take these terms to have as (part of) their lexical function the expression of psychological perspectives; in some cases the perspective in question is closer to literal (spatio-temporal) point of view, while in others it is a more abstract, and possibly richer, interpretive structure like those discussed here.

  3. For details, including discussion of more complex cases, see my 2003.

  4. Cf. Stalnaker (1998, 101).

  5. One might object that perspectives cannot be presupposed on the ground that they do not display the profile of plugging characteristic of presupposition. Moran, for instance, claims that “the framing-effect of a metaphor survives when the statement is denied, subsumed in a hypothetical or a part of a question, or placed in quotation marks” (1989, 101, emphasis added). A similar objection is sometimes lodged against content-based theories of slurs. In both cases, although perspectives do sometimes project across plugs like direct and indirect quotation, they are more often blocked. In this respect they again pattern more closely with expressive presuppositions.

  6. This is not to say that similes may not be more effective for certain rhetorical purposes in certain conversational contexts. In particular, because they focus their assertoric force on the perspective, rather than presupposing it, similes can sometimes be more evocative and open-ended than their correlative metaphors. The point is just that metaphors are more forceful along the dimension of illocutionary commitment to specific contents. Thanks to Robin Jeshion for discussion.

  7. I discuss this phenomenon in the context of insinuation in my (ms.).

  8. Note in this context that Perrott et al’s talk of the futility of resisting analogical insertion in memory is too strong. Their experiments showed that subjects recalled analogically derived propositions as having been explicitly presented by a target text. They did not test whether subjects came to actually believe those propositions; indeed, their own results provide evidence that they did not.

References

  • Anderson, R., & Pichert, J. (1978). Recall of previously unrecallable information following a shift in perspective. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 17, 1–12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Banfield, J., Pendry, L., Mewse, A., & Edwards, M. (2003). The effects of an elderly stereotype prime on reaching and grasping actions. Social Cognition, 21(4), 299–319.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bargh, J., Chen, M., & Burrows, L. (1996). The automaticity of social behavior: Direct effects of trait construct and stereotype activation on action. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 71(2), 230–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Black, M. (1954). Metaphor. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 55, 273–294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blanchette, I., & Dunbar, K. (2002). Representational change and analogy: How analogical inferences alter representations. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 28, 672–685.

    Google Scholar 

  • Booth, W. (1978). Metaphor as rhetoric: The problem of evaluation. Critical Inquiry, 5(1), 49–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Camp, E. (2003): Saying and Seeing-as: The Linguistic Uses and Cognitive Effects of Metaphor. Dissertation, University of California, Berkeley.

  • Camp, E. (2005). Critical study of Josef Stern’s Metaphor in Context. Noûs, 39(4), 715–731.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Camp, E. (2006a). Metaphor and that certain ‘je ne sais quoi’. Philosophical Studies, 129(1), 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Camp, E. (2006b). Contextualism, metaphor, and what is said. Mind and Language, 21(3), 280–309.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Camp, E. (2008). Showing, telling, and seeing: Metaphor and ‘poetic’ language. In The Baltic international yearbook of cognition, logic, and communication: A figure of speech: Metaphor (Vol. 3) (Online), (pp. 1–24).

  • Camp, E. (2009). Two varieties of literary imagination: Metaphor, fiction, and thought experiments. In H. Wettstein (Ed.), Midwest studies in philosophy: Poetry and philosophy XXXIII (pp. 107–130). Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Camp, E. (2012). Sarcasm, pretense, and the semantics/pragmatics distinction. Noûs, 46(4), 587–634.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Camp, E. (2013). Metaphor and varieties of meaning. In E. Lepore & K. Ludwig (Eds.), A companion to Davidson (pp. 361–378). Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Camp, E. (2015). Logical concepts and associative characterizations. In E. Margolis & S. Laurence (Eds.), The conceptual mind: New directions in the study of concepts (pp. 591–621). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchill, W. (1941). Address to the Congress of the United States.

  • Cohen, T. (1978). Metaphor and the cultivation of intimacy. Critical Inquiry, 5(1), 3–12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Danto, A. (1981). The transfiguration of the commonplace: A philosophy of art. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1978). What metaphors mean. Critical Inquiry, 5, 31–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dijksterhuis, A., & van Knippenberg, A. (1998). The relation between perception and behavior, or how to win a game of trivial pursuit. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 74(4), 865–877.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fillmore, C. (1977). Scenes-and-frames semantics. In Zampolli A. (Ed.), Linguistic structures processing (pp. 55–81). Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing Company.

  • Fillmore, C. (1985). Frames and the semantics of understanding. Quaderni di Semantica, 6(2), 222–254.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gentner, D., & Markman, A. (1997). Structure mapping in analogy and similarity. American Psychologist, 52, 45–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H. P. (1957). Meaning. Philosophical Review, 66(3), 377–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • King, J. C. (2013). Supplementives, the coordination account and conflicting intentions. Philosophical Perspectives: Philosophy of Language, 27(1), 288–311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lasersohn, P. (2005). Context dependence, disagreement, and predicates of personal taste. Linguistics and Philosophy, 28(6), 643–686.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lasersohn, P. (2007). Expressives, perspective and presupposition. Theoretical Linguistics, 33(2), 223–230.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lee-Sammons, W., & Whitney, P. (1991). Reading perspectives and memory for text: An individual differences analysis. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 17, 1074–1081.

    Google Scholar 

  • Markman, A. (1997). Constraints on analogical inference. Cognitive Science, 21, 373–418.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moran, R. (1989). Seeing and believing: Metaphor, image and force. Critical Inquiry, 16(1), 87–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, G., & Medin, D. (1985). The role of theories in conceptual coherence. Psychological Review, 92, 289–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perrott, D., Gentner, D., & Bodenhausen, G. (2005). Resistance is futile: The unwitting insertion of analogical inferences in memory. Psychonomic Bulletin and Review, 12(4), 696–702.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sloman, S., Love, B., & Ahn, W.-K. (1998). Feature centrality and conceptual coherence. Cognitive Science, 22(2), 189–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (1973). Presuppositions. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 2, 447–457.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (1998). On the representation of context. In Context and content (pp. 96–114). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Thagard, P. (1989). Explanatory coherence. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 12, 435–502.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A. (1977). Features of similarity. Psychological Review, 84, 327–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Fintel, K. (2004). Would you believe it? The king of France is Back! (Presuppositions and truth-value intuitions). In A. Bezuidenhout & M. Reimer (Eds.), Descriptions and beyond: An interdisciplinary collection of essays on definite and indefinite descriptions and other related phenomena (pp. 315–341). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This paper has benefitted from an enormous amount of feedback, especially from audiences at Queen’s University, Nassau County Community College, the New School for Social Research, the University of Kentucky, Wake Forest University, Union College, the CUNY Graduate Center, the Joint CSMN and Balzan Workshop on Metaphor, Imagery and Communication, Dartmouth College, Leeds, and the Brooklyn Public Library. Special thanks to Mitch Green and Jeff King for very helpful discussion, and to Stephen Laurence for providing the drawing in Fig. 1.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Elisabeth Camp.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Camp, E. Why metaphors make good insults: perspectives, presupposition, and pragmatics. Philos Stud 174, 47–64 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-015-0525-y

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-015-0525-y

Keywords

Navigation